Topic Page: Herder, Johann Gottfried,

Similar documents
Lecture 18: Rationalism

Resolutio of Idealism into Atheism in Fichte

A History of Western Thought Why We Think the Way We Do. Summer 2016 Ross Arnold

Chapter 24. Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel: The Concepts of Being, Non-being and Becoming

STAR-CROSSED LOVERS: THE POLITICS & PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN FREEDOM

TABLE OF CONTENTS. A. "The Way The World Really Is" 46 B. The First Philosophers: The "Turning Point of Civilization" 47

Robert Kiely Office Hours: Monday 4:15 6:00; Wednesday 1-3; Thursday 2-3

Introduction to Philosophy: The Big Picture

d) The (first) debate about Pantheism

Thursday, November 30, 17. Hegel s Idealism

Tuesday, November 11, Hegel s Idealism

Robert Kiely Office Hours: Tuesday 1-3, Wednesday 1-3, and by appointment

The Theory of Reality: A Critical & Philosophical Elaboration

Reading Questions for Phil , Fall 2016 (Daniel)

Chapter 25. Hegel s Absolute Idealism and the Phenomenology of Spirit

KINGSBOROUGH COMMUNITY COLLEGE of The City University of New York. Common COURSE SYLLABUS

J. G. Fichte as a Post-Kantian Philosopher and His Political Theory: A Return to Romanticism

ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis

Study on the Essence of Marx s Political Philosophy in the View of Materialism

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins

POL320 Y1Y Modern Political Thought Summer 2016

Topic Page: Heidegger, Martin,

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

Philosophy Quiz 12 The Age of Descartes

EMPIRICISM & EMPIRICAL PHILOSOPHY

Qué es la filosofía? What is philosophy? Philosophy

Spinoza and German Idealism

A History of Western Thought Why We Think the Way We Do. Summer 2016 Ross Arnold

GABRIEL A. GOTTLIEB. Editor 1. Fichte s Foundations of Natural Right : A Critical Guide (Cambridge University Press: Under Contract).

UNIVERSITY OF CALICUT QUESTION BANK

2/8/ A New Way of Thinking: The Birth of Modern Science. Scientific Revolution

POL320 Y1Y/L0101: MODERN POLITICAL THOUGHT Summer 2015

6 February Dr. Cindy Ausec

Kant and his Successors

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

The Age of Enlightenment

Epistemology and sensation

Chapter 24. Section 2. German Unification. 1. Explain how nationalism grew in Germany after the Congress of Vienna.

PHILOSOPHY MICHAEL J. VLACH, PH.D. the Big idea for the 101 Most important People and Concepts in Philosophy. Silverton, or

POLITICAL SCIENCE 3102 (B) Sascha Maicher (Fall 2014)

COURSE GOALS: PROFESSOR: Chris Latiolais Philosophy Department Kalamazoo College Humphrey House #202 Telephone # Offices Hours:

Ibuanyidanda (Complementary Reflection), African Philosophy and General Issues in Philosophy

POLI 342: MODERN WESTERN POLITICAL THOUGHT

PHIL 4242 German Idealism 德意志觀念論 Fall 2016 Professor Gregory S. Moss

Ms. Oase Chapter 17 AP Euro Toward A New Worldview: Scientific Revolution and Enlightenment

The Problem of Normativity

Descartes and Schopenhauer on Voluntary Movement:

PL 406 HISTORY OF MODERN PHILOSOPHY Fall 2009

Anastasia N Artemyev Berg

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES

Religion and Science: The Emerging Relationship Part II

AKC Lecture 1 Plato, Penrose, Popper

John Haugeland. Dasein Disclosed: John Haugeland s Heidegger. Edited by Joseph Rouse. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2013.

Was Berkeley a Rational Empiricist? In this short essay I will argue for the conclusion that, although Berkeley ought to be

1200 Academy St. Kalamazoo, MI 49006

The Human Science Debate: Positivist, Anti-Positivist, and Postpositivist Inquiry. By Rebecca Joy Norlander. November 20, 2007

Syllabus. Primary Sources, 2 edition. Hackett, Various supplementary handouts, available in class and on the course website.

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Introduction. Allen W. Wood

The Ground Upon Which We Stand

Political Science 206 Modern Political Philosophy Spring Semester 2011 Clark University

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

MECHANISM AND MEDICINE. Basic idea: DesCartes ( ): Man as a Machine

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

Critique Of Pure Reason Unified Edition With All Variants From The 1781 And 1787 Editions Hackett Classics

THE KANTIAN REVOLUTION

AP World History Notes Chapter 16: Science and Religion ( )

Critique Of Pure Reason (A Library Of Universal Literature, Part 1-Science) By Immanuel Kant READ ONLINE

Background to Early Modern Philosophy. Philosophy 22 Fall, 2009 G. J. Mattey

POL320 Y1Y/L0101: MODERN POLITICAL THOUGHT Thursday AH 100

PHILOSOPHICAL RAMIFICATIONS: THEORY, EXPERIMENT, & EMPIRICAL TRUTH

William Meehan Essay on Spinoza s psychology.

Undergraduate Calendar Content

General Discourse on the Subject of My Philosophy

The Age of the Enlightenment

Chapter Summaries: Three Types of Religious Philosophy by Clark, Chapter 1

I SEMESTER B. A. PHILOSOPHY PHL1B 01- INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY QUESTION BANK FOR INTERNAL ASSESSMENT. Multiple Choice Questions

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

Introduction to Hegel s Logic

On-Campus Course Syllabus PHI 601 L00.A Topics in Philosophy: Modernity Spring 2017

RS 200A: Proseminar in the History and Theory of Religion

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Teachur Philosophy Degree 2018

Authority Beyond the Bounds of Mere Reason in the Schmitt-Strauss Exchange

Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics

Kant & Transcendental Idealism

In Concerning the Difference between the Spirit and the Letter in Philosophy, Johann

The Advancement: A Book Review

MODELS CLARIFIED: RESPONDING TO LANGDON GILKEY. by David E. Klemm and William H. Klink

THE FICHTEAN IDEA OF THE SCIENCE OF KNOWLEDGE. by Jean Hyppolite*

absolute/unconditioned/infinite. desire. dynamic brokenness fragment creativity sublime strange wonder, wildness hyperbolic: kinship with nature.

God in Political Theory

Free Won't [This Title Was Predetermined] and philosophy. For religious followers, free will is often considered a paradox. If God is all-seeing and

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

A History of Western Thought Why We Think the Way We Do. Summer 2016 Ross Arnold

Apriority from the 'Grundlage' to the 'System of Ethics'

PHILOSOPHY 111: HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY EARLY MODERN Winter 2012

Introduction to the critical project

DALLAS BAPTIST UNIVERSITY THE ILLOGIC OF FAITH: FEAR AND TREMBLING IN LIGHT OF MODERNISM SUBMITTED TO THE GENTLE READER FOR SPRING CONFERENCE

Transcription:

Topic Page: Herder, Johann Gottfried, 1744-1803 Definition: Herder, Johann Gottf ried von from Philip's Encyclopedia German philosopher and poet. He believed human society to be an organic, secular totality that develops as the result of a historical process. Herder was a founder of German romanticism and a critic of Kant. Outlines of a Philosophy on the History of Man (1784-91) is regarded as his masterpiece. Summary Article: Herder, Johann Gottf ried von (17 4 4-1803) from Encyclopedia of Time: Science, Philosophy, Theology, & Culture Born in Mohrungen, Prussia, Johann Gottfried von Herder attended the lectures of Immanuel Kant in Königsberg for 2 years, beginning at 18 years of age. Herder was most fascinated with Kant's early scientific reasoning, especially his philosophy of nature. At the age of 21, Herder became a Protestant pastor. In Königsberg, Herder became friends with the counter-enlightenment figure Johann Image from: Friedrich Georg Hamann. Both Herder and Hamann rejected the later Kantian Rehberg, Johann Gottf ried critical philosophy, and had already rejected any notion of a faculty. Herder... in Encyclopedia of Both had little interest in time as an abstraction. Instead, all the Romantic Era, 1760-1850 consciousness should be thought of as language-based. Though his friend Hamann was averse to the entire tradition of rationalism, and though he himself never accepted Kant's critical philosophy, Herder was a rationalist and an idealist when history was the subject. Herder traveled throughout the German-speaking lands and conversed with many of the greatest minds of his time. He was interested in all things natural, human, and divine. On December 18, 1803, Herder passed away in Weimar. The German Hist orical Sense and Herder Johann Gottfried Herder occupies a permanent, important place in the history of human thought concerning time, for it was he (with his contemporary Hamann) who introduced a historical sense to the German nation as a whole. Of course, before Herder there were authors with a strong historical sense. But all these influences and predecessors were non-germans, especially the figures from the French Enlightenment. And, of course, before the Enlightenment, the Scholastics had understood time and history in the abstract. But they were more interested in eternity than in human history. They distinguished sacred from secular time in order to give absolute priority to the former. The Scholastics lacked a sense centered on natural and human history. Herder provided a new mode of thinking for the German public by offering just such a historical sense. Most important, this historical sense was lacking in the orientations of Leibniz and Kant. The thought of Leibniz was almost entirely nonhis-torical. Mathematics and physics (monadology) do not require a developed notion of human history, because they are largely theoretical, abstract sciences. Perhaps Kant sought to sidestep the question of history (and phenomenology) by focusing largely on the transcendental structures of the ego. His thinking was strikingly nonhistori-cal, even transtemporal. The reader of Kant is often left with a sense of timelessness and of rationality at rest, a sense of the

structure, but not the content, of time. Herder and Hamann Herder had a noteworthy German cohort in developing a historical sense, Johann Georg Hamann. Herder's senior and friend, Hamann had also embraced history and sought to instill the German nation with it. Hamann's thought was largely a reaction to the Enlightenment and to the ideas of Benedict Spinoza. The German public, in general, had reacted to the twin specters of Spinoza and Enlightenment science with fear and loathing. Spinoza's ideas were considered deterministic and covertly antireligious. The advance of English science, especially chemistry, was threatening because the soul could then perhaps be explained by the chemical processes of the mind within the brain. Hamann sought to guarantee religion a safe respite. Faced with the advance of Spinoza's ideas, Hamann retreated into irrationalism and a sort of counter-enlightenment orientation. He sought to link biblical history with modern history, and to prevent any juncture between history and science, materialism, or atheism. Again, Hamann had a sense of history, but it was of a religiously orthodox orientation; history is the story of the divine will. Above all, he viewed history as entirely sacred; a strictly secular history could not be conceived of. In short, Hamann viewed history as an irrational but divine phenomenon. Confronted by the twin specters of Spinoza and Enlightenment, Herder chose a different strategy from Hamann. While Herder still viewed history as a divine phenomenon, he claimed that history is rational and an object of science. As the third element of his strategy, Herder chose to incorporate a broad range of natural sciences into his scientific account of history. Like Hamann, Herder saw history as divine, but in a very different sense. Hamann had sought to develop history out of revealed scripture; Herder, on the other hand, attempted to delete all religious or mythological content from his history. He would accept no divine intervention, no miracles, as a cause in history. In short, Herder's explicit project was to develop a scientific (non-theological) account of history. He saw the inevitability of considering time not as entirely sacred but also as secular (natural scientific), and even as an agency of human free will (the historical sense). And so he set off on the project of authoring a coherent history of the universe, nature, man, society, and God, all strictly within a natural scientific methodology. Herder was not concerned with Spinoza, since his natural science was strongly influenced by Roger Joseph Boscovich, in that his theory of atoms was a point-particle theory rather than the Newtonian corpuscular theorymeaning that instead of Newton's extended atoms, Herder insisted on Boscovich's dimensionless force-points. (Recall that Herder, like Kant, was in the generation of thinkers immediately after Newton, Leibniz, and Boscovich. It seems most likely that Herder discovered Boscovich's ideas when Kant was struggling with them in the early days at Königsberg. Kant finally resolved his struggle with Boscovich by incorporating the theory of force-points into his own natural philosophy in his late work Metaphysics of Natural Sciences.) Force-points completely subverted Spinoza's monism and determinism so abhorred by the German sense of piety. Boscovich's natural science (Theory of Natural Science, 1776) was a theory of force, not substance. By adopting an atomism most closely related to Kant and Boscovich, Herder was able to sidestep Spinoza's deterministic metaphysics entirely. But Herder could not deny the advance of Enlightenment science, so he chose to concentrate on the natural within history. He began with an explanation of the universe and the origins of nature, and then worked his way through the rise of animal life. Finally, he gave a historical account of human civilizations.

Herder saw that the sciences had to be given a sense of time. Previously the sciences were taught as a hierarchy rather than as having a shared history. The static classifications of Aristotle and Linnaeus could no longer do justice to the advance of science. To account adequately for the development of the universe, Earth, and man, a timeline was necessary with which to distinguish developmental stages. This meant discovering the unidi-rectionality of time and of a sequence of events following that linear model. The sciences could no longer burst forth fully grown from the brow of Zeus. Developing an interdisciplinary history of the sciences was a daunting challenge for Herder. Writing well before Charles Darwin, Herder did not have a theory of evolution. Nor did Herder have the advantage of the theory of developmental history authored by Karl Ernst Ritter von Baer. Yet he traced history from the origins of the universe to the rise of humankind across a panorama of the sciences. Breaking completely with Hamann, Herder saw in history not the divine will of God, but instead the actualization of divinity in man. Herder's Legacy Herder's contributions to the historical sense religion, rationality, and scienceproved fateful to subsequent German thought on history. After Herder, the first on the scene, Johann Gottlieb Fichte, adopted the religious interpretation of history provided by Herder; history was indeed the actualization of the absolute ego in man. Fichte also adopted the notion that there is a deeper logic and rationality to history; it is the gradual actualization of the Idea (logos). Fichte returned to Hamann's tradition of pietism and developed his system of ethical idealism entirely within a quite preachy, harshly moralistic tone. But Fichte ignored the natural sciences in favor of his own principle of ego. Next in the line of succession came E W. J. Schelling. In keeping with these predecessors, Schelling viewed history as sacred time. He also saw history as the gradual unfolding of an Idea, and so all things are ultimately know-able by reason. In contrast to Fichte, Schelling greatly esteemed the natural sciences. If Fichte's system may be called ethical idealism, Schelling's system could be called an idealism of nature or objective idealism. Thus Schelling was a more complete replication of Herder's historical sense even if in the strange new idiom of systematic idealism. After Schelling, Hegel advanced the historical sense to perhaps its most extreme form. In fact, Hegel adopted Herder's three contributions, mediated through Fichte and Schelling, as his own. Religion had its eternal safe haven in Hegel's Absolute Spirit, and history was the moving image of eternity. Also, history had its own rational process for Hegel, which may be captured in a system of logic. Rationality is indeed only the standard of knowledge for a historical stage of development. Hegel's Absolute sought to subsume Nature and man entirely within itself. Finally, Karl Marx reworked Hegel's absolute idealism, mediated by Ludwig Feuerbach, the Utopian socialists, and later Darwin, into an all-inclusive theory of historical materialism. Directly or indirectly, these thinkers traced several fundamental elements of their historical sense back to Herder. It should be observed that each stage within Herder's history was equal to every other; there is no progress or higher spirituality as history proceeds (in contrast to Hegel's notion). He did believe, though, that human history should be narrated ultimately in terms of races and nations. Thus Herder truly set the scene for Fichte's entrance onto the stage. See also Baer, Karl Ernst Ritter von, Boscovich, Roger Joseph, Fichte, Johann Gottlieb, Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, Idealism, Kant, Immanuel, Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm von, Marx, Karl, Schelling, Friedrich W. J. von, Spinoza, Baruch de, Time, Sacred

Beck, L. W ( (1965).). Early German philosophy: Kant and his predecessors (chap. 15). Bristol, UK: Thoemmes Press. von Herder, J. G. ( (1963).). God, some conversations. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill. (Original work published 1787). Herder, J. G von. ( (2002).). Philosophical writings. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Whitlock, Greg Copyright 2009 by SAGE Publications, Inc.

APA Whitlock, G., & Whitlock. (2009). Herder, Johann Gottfried von (1744-1803). In H. J. Birx (Ed.), Encyclopedia of time: science, philosophy, theology, & culture. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications. Retrieved from Chicago Whitlock, Greg, and Whitlock. "Herder, Johann Gottfried von (1744-1803)." In Encyclopedia of Time: Science, Philosophy, Theology, & Culture, edited by H. James Birx. Sage Publications, 2009. Harvard Whitlock, G. and Whitlock. (2009). Herder, Johann Gottfried von (1744-1803). In H.J. Birx (Ed.), Encyclopedia of time: science, philosophy, theology, & culture. [Online]. Thousand Oaks: Sage Publications. Available from: [Accessed 30 January 2018]. MLA Whitlock, Greg, and Whitlock. "Herder, Johann Gottfried von (1744-1803)." Encyclopedia of Time: Science, Philosophy, Theology, & Culture, edited by H. James Birx, Sage Publications, 1st edition, 2009. Credo Reference,. Accessed 30 Jan 2018.