CONTENT NORMATIVITY AND THE INTERDEPENDENCY OF BELIEF AND DESIRE. Seyed Ali Kalantari Lecturer of philosophy at the University of Isfahan, Iran

Similar documents
The normativity of content and the Frege point

Skepticism and Internalism

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Why Is Epistemic Evaluation Prescriptive?

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

The Transparent Failure of Norms to Keep Up Standards of Belief

Normativity and Concepts. Hannah Ginsborg, U.C. Berkeley. June 2016

Matthew Parrott. In order for me become aware of another person's psychological states, I must observe her

Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

The Limits of Normative Detachment 1 Nishi Shah Amherst College Draft of 04/15/10

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth).

Korsgaard and Non-Sentient Life ABSTRACT

DISAGREEMENT AND THE FIRST-PERSON PERSPECTIVE

An Inferentialist Conception of the A Priori. Ralph Wedgwood

The Limits of Normative Detachment 1. Nishi Shah Amherst College Draft of 10/23/08

BELIEF AND NORMATIVITY. Pascal Engel University of Geneva

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Dave Elder-Vass Of Babies and Bathwater. A Review of Tuukka Kaidesoja Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

The Normativity of the Intentional. Ralph Wedgwood. Many philosophers have claimed that the intentional is normative. (This claim is the

Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification?

Correct Beliefs as to What One Believes: A Note

Transparency and Reasons for Belief

A Rational Solution to the Problem of Moral Error Theory? Benjamin Scott Harrison

On the alleged perversity of the evidential view of testimony

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

SCHAFFER S DEMON NATHAN BALLANTYNE AND IAN EVANS

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

a0rxh/ On Van Inwagen s Argument Against the Doctrine of Arbitrary Undetached Parts WESLEY H. BRONSON Princeton University

How Gödelian Ontological Arguments Fail

What is Good Reasoning?

Lawrence Brian Lombard a a Wayne State University. To link to this article:

Can the lottery paradox be solved by identifying epistemic justification with epistemic permissibility? Benjamin Kiesewetter

The Paradox of the Question

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

Chadwick Prize Winner: Christian Michel THE LIAR PARADOX OUTSIDE-IN

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports. Stephen Schiffer New York University

Positivism, Natural Law, and Disestablishment: Some Questions Raised by MacCormick's Moralistic Amoralism

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel

MAKING "REASONS" EXPLICIT HOW NORMATIVE IS BRANDOM'S INFERENTIALISM? Daniel Laurier

REVIEW THE DOOR TO SELLARS

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Outsmarting the McKinsey-Brown argument? 1

It is advisable to refer to the publisher s version if you intend to cite from the work.

Reasons for Belief and Normativity. Kathrin Glüer and Åsa Wikforss

REASONS AND ENTAILMENT

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Kripke s Wittgenstein s Sceptical Solution and Donald Davidson s Philosophy of Language. Ali Hossein Khani

Seth Mayer. Comments on Christopher McCammon s Is Liberal Legitimacy Utopian?

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan

Judith Jarvis Thomson s Normativity

RALPH WEDGWOOD. Pascal Engel and I are in agreement about a number of crucial points:

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries

Belief, Rationality and Psychophysical Laws. blurring the distinction between two of these ways. Indeed, it will be argued here that no

Definite Descriptions and the Argument from Inference

A Priori Bootstrapping

CHECKING THE NEIGHBORHOOD: A REPLY TO DIPAOLO AND BEHRENDS ON PROMOTION

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Chance, Chaos and the Principle of Sufficient Reason

Action in Special Contexts

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 5

Truth and the Aim of Belief

The ontology of human rights and obligations

(A fully correct plan is again one that is not constrained by ignorance or uncertainty (pp ); which seems to be just the same as an ideal plan.

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Well-Being, Time, and Dementia. Jennifer Hawkins. University of Toronto

I assume some of our justification is immediate. (Plausible examples: That is experienced, I am aware of something, 2 > 0, There is light ahead.

Truth as the aim of epistemic justification

PLEASESURE, DESIRE AND OPPOSITENESS

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Shieva Kleinschmidt [This is a draft I completed while at Rutgers. Please do not cite without permission.] Conditional Desires.

Faith and Philosophy, April (2006), DE SE KNOWLEDGE AND THE POSSIBILITY OF AN OMNISCIENT BEING Stephan Torre

Physicalism and Conceptual Analysis * Esa Díaz-León.

PROSPECTS FOR A JAMESIAN EXPRESSIVISM 1 JEFF KASSER

The Power of Critical Thinking Why it matters How it works

ON THE VALUE AND NATURE OF TRUTH

PHENOMENALITY AND INTENTIONALITY WHICH EXPLAINS WHICH?: REPLY TO GERTLER

Can logical consequence be deflated?

R. M. Hare (1919 ) SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG. Definition of moral judgments. Prescriptivism

WHY NATURALISM? 179 DAVID COPP WHY NATURALISM?

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Going beyond good and evil

Rawls versus utilitarianism: the subset objection

Replies to Hasker and Zimmerman. Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, I.

NORMATIVITY AND INTENTIONALITY

What asymmetry? Knowledge of self, knowledge of others, and the inferentialist challenge

Transcription:

CONTENT NORMATIVITY AND THE INTERDEPENDENCY OF BELIEF AND DESIRE Seyed Ali Kalantari Lecturer of philosophy at the University of Isfahan, Iran Abstract The normativity of mental content thesis has been very influential in contemporary philosophy of mind and action. Paul Boghossian (2003, 2005) has developed an argument for the normativity of mental content on the basis of two premises- the normativity of the notion of belief and the priority of the notion of belief to the notion of desire. In his article Alexander Miller (2008) has criticised Boghossian s argument for the normativity of mental content. He has argued that the second premise of Boghossian s argument is false to the effect that belief and desire are conceptually interdependent. In this paper, along with proposing a new argument for the normativity of content thesis, I will clarify that the thesis survives Miller's attack. Key words: normativity, belief, desire, content, interdependency, Introduction: It is widely held that a concept is normative only if it is constitutive of our understanding of a statement involving it such that the statement entails an ought. In his papers (2003, 2005) Paul Boghossian has developed an argument for the thesis that mental content is constitutively normative. The argument is criticized by a number of critics. In this paper I will address a key objection against the normativity of content thesis proposed by Miller (2008). In section one I will reformulate Boghossian's argument for the thesis in details. In section two I will 169

UJAH: Unizik Journal of Arts and Humanities clarify Miller's objection against the normativity of content thesis, I will then propose a new argument for the normativity of content thesis to show that Miller's objection fails. 1- Boghossian on the normativity of content: Boghossian's normativity of content thesis can be clarified via the following four steps: In the first step, Boghossian claims that belief attributions are constitutively normative since, it is a condition on understanding them that one understands that one ought to believe that P only if P (Boghossian2005: 212). In other words, he believes that the concept of belief is constitutively normative since grasping an attribution of belief to someone requires grasping that the attribution implies an ought that is, that she ought to believe that P only if P. The is called the normativity of belief thesis in the literature and is endorsed by many key philosophers (see Engel 2001; Gibbard 2003, 2005; Shah 2003; Shah and Velleman 2005; Wedgwood 2002). The following example will clarify the idea: (1) Marco understands that Ebeneezer believes that P. According to the normativity of belief thesis implies: (2) Marco understands that Ebeneezer ought to believe that P only if P. In the second step, Boghossian claims that there are no norms governing propositional attitudes other than 170

Seyed Ali Kalantari: Content Normativity and the Interdependency of belief desire. belief. He considers the case of desire and states that desire attributions are not normative: suppose I say of Ebenezer that he wants that Howard Dean be the next President. In making this attribution, am I in any way speaking oughts? Ebenezer s desire has conditions of satisfaction it will be satisfied if and only if Dean is the next president. But, in and of itself, this doesn t translate either into a correctness fact, or into an ought of any kind (Boghossian2005: 213).Boghossian notes that of course an individual may have a particular desire (for X, say) because she believes it to be a way of securing the satisfaction of another of her desires, and hence it might be said that the desire is correct to the extent that her belief is true. However it does not show that the desire itself is the subject of normative evaluation: rather, this is the underlying belief. What Boghossian insists on is that there are no oughts about desires in virtue of the mere fact that they are contentful states: it s not clear to me, then, that there are norms on desire merely qua contentful state (Boghossian2005: 213). From the considerations embodied in the first and second steps, Boghossian concludes that what is responsible for the normativity of belief attribution relates to the concept of belief and not the concept of content. Since, if content is constitutively normative all the other contentful attitudes, including desire, should be normative too. Boghossian clarifies this point as follows: if it s genuinely constitutive of content that it 171

UJAH: Unizik Journal of Arts and Humanities be normative, shouldn t it carry this normativity with it wherever it goes? (Boghossian2005: 212) In the third step, Boghossian endorses the idea that our understanding of content has to go via understanding the attitudes that have contents as their objects: I take it that the concept of a proposition, or content, just is the concept of whatever it is that is the object of the attitudes (Boghossian2005: 214). This consideration, of course, implies that the concept of content may be introduced in connection with attitudinal concepts other than that of belief, say, desire. Boghossian, however, asks, whether any non-belief based understanding would covertly presuppose an understanding of its role in belief (2005: 214). This question is considered in the fourth step of the argument as follows. In the fourth step, Boghossian argues that the concept of belief is indeed prior to the concepts of the other propositional attitudes, including the concept of desire: grasp of the concept of desire seems to asymmetrically depend on our grasp of the concept of belief in just the way that, I have argued, the normativity of content thesis requires (Boghossian2005: 215). This consideration implies that we understand the role that content plays in propositional attitudes generally only through our understanding of its role in belief: we would understand content only through belief, and belief only through normative notions (Boghossian2005: 214). Boghossian argues that since the concept of belief is normative, the concept of mental 172

Seyed Ali Kalantari: Content Normativity and the Interdependency of belief desire. content is also normative: if our grasp of the notion of content were somehow to depend in a privileged and asymmetric way on our grasp of the concept of belief, then our only route to the notion of a contentful state would be through our grasp of a constitutively normative notion that would be enough to substantiate the claim that content itself is normative (Boghossian2005: 213). Boghossian emphasizes that the asymmetry in our understanding of belief and desire is a necessary condition for the normativity of content: if, however, it is not true that content depends on belief, that content may be understood through its role in other nonnormative attitudes then we would not have a thesis of the normativity of content but only the rather different thesis of the normativity of belief (Boghossian2005: 214). Below, in order to attain a clearer perspective on the overall argument, I have reformulated the premises and conclusions of Boghossian s argument. The argument involves the following four premises: (3) The concept of belief is constitutively normative. (4) The concept of desire (and also all the attitudinal concepts other than belief) is not normative. (5) Our understanding of content has to go via understanding the attitudes that have contents as their objects. 173

UJAH: Unizik Journal of Arts and Humanities (6) The concept of belief is prior to the concept of desire (and also to other propositional attitudes). Premises (5) and (6), according to Boghossian, imply: (7) Our understanding of content has to go via understanding of belief. From (3) and (7) the argument infers the normativity of content: (8) The concept of mental content is normative. This is because [according to (7)] we would understand content only through belief and [according to (3)] belief through normative notions (Boghossian2005: 214). 2- The normativity of content and the conceptual interdependency of belief and desire: In his recent article, Alexander Miller (2008) argues that premise (6) of Boghossian sargument is implausible. Miller claims that there is good evidence which shows that belief and desire are conceptually interdependent. That is, thinking of someone as having beliefs involves thinking of them as at least capable of having desires, and thinking of someone as having desires involves thinking of them as at least capable of having beliefs (Miller 2008: 237). He argues for the interdependency thesis via the following plausible consideration: both beliefs and desires potentially feature in the generation of action. He clarifies this as follows: grasping the concept of belief... involves grasping that beliefs can lead to action by combining with desires (Miller 2008: 237) and, grasping the concept of desire... involves grasping 174

Seyed Ali Kalantari: Content Normativity and the Interdependency of belief desire. that desires can lead to action by combining with beliefs (Miller 2008: 237). For example, according to Miller: (9) Marco understands that Ebeneezer believes that there is beer in the fridge. Implies: (10) Marco understands that (if Ebeneezer believes that there is beer in the fridge and Ebeneezer desires to drink some beer then, ceteris paribus, Ebeneezer will reach for the fridge). Likewise (11) Marco understands that Ebeneezer desires to drink some beer. Implies: (12) Marco understands that (if Ebeneezer desires to drink some beer and Ebeneezer believes that there is beer in the fridge, ceteris paribus, Ebeneezer will reach for the fridge). These points, according to Miller, are good reasons to endorse the interdependency thesis between belief and desire, far from there being an unidirectional relation of priority between the two. It should be noted here that Bykvist and Hattiangadi (2007) have tried to show that premise (3) of Boghossian s argument is false. Nonetheless, Miller believes that, even if they failed to undermine the normativity of belief, Boghossian sargument for the normativity of content is still implausible. This is because, as explained in section A, Boghossian s 175

UJAH: Unizik Journal of Arts and Humanities argument for the normativity of content is based on both main premises (3) and (6), and Miller attempts to demonstrate the falsity of premise (6). As Miller puts it: even if Bykvist and Hattiangadi are wrong about the normativity of belief- and I do not say that they are- Boghossian s argument for the normativity of content would still grind to a halt (Miller 2008: 237). Miller s argument for the interdependency thesis, of course has important implications for some of the premises and conclusions of Boghossian s argument. However, I will argue that it does not undermine the idea that content is normative. In other words, Boghossian could endorse Miller s reflection that belief and desire are conceptually interdependent, whilst manoeuvring to preserve his argument for the normativity of content. I will now distinguish between two senses in which a concept may be said to be normative. Then I will end by spelling out an alternative argument for the normativity of content, which is immune to Miller s attack: (13) A concept is directly normative only if it is constitutive of our understanding of a statement involving it that the statement entails an ought. And, (14) A concept is indirectly normative only if it is not directly normative and we understand it only through our understanding of a concept that is directly normative. 176

Seyed Ali Kalantari: Content Normativity and the Interdependency of belief desire. The distinction between the two senses in which a concept can be said to be normative, as we will see below, can be useful for understanding the difference between the sense in which desire is normative and the sense in which belief is normative. My alternative argument for the normativity of content has the following four premises: (15)The concept of belief is directly normative. This premise is granted on the basis of Boghossian s consideration, embodied in the first step of his argument, according to which understanding of a statement ascribing a belief requires understanding a statement that involves an ought. (16) The concept of desire is not directly normative. This premise is based upon Boghossian s independent argument, embodied in the second step of his argument, according to which attribution of desire is not directly normative. (17) Our understanding of content has to go via understanding contentful attitudes. This premise comes through the consideration that there is no independent account of content in hand. The concept of content can be introduced only via the concept of contentful attitudes, for contents just are what the attitudes are attitudes towards. (18)Belief and desire are conceptually interdependent. 177

UJAH: Unizik Journal of Arts and Humanities This premise reflects the argument of Miller s rehearsed above according to which belief and desire are conceptually interdependent. Premises (17) and (18) together imply: (19) We understand content through the concept of belief and the concept of desire. Now, premises (15), (16) and (18) imply: (20) The concept of desire is indirectly normative. This is because on one hand, according to Boghossian s argument, desire cannot be directly normative. On the other hand, according to the interdependency, understanding the notion of desire depends on understanding the notion of belief, so it follows that since belief is directly normative, desire must be indirectly normative. Finally we can conclude that: (21) The concept of content is indirectly normative. This is because on one hand, according to (19), we understand content through the concept of belief and the concept of desire. On the other hand, according to (15), the concept of belief is directly normative and, according to (20), the concept of desire is indirectly normative. It follows that the notion of content is grasped through a directly normative notion, hence according to the definition (14) the concept of content must be indirectly normative. Conclusion: 178

Seyed Ali Kalantari: Content Normativity and the Interdependency of belief desire. My argument above, if it is true, then justifies my foregoing claim that even if we give up the conceptual priority of belief over desire in favor of the idea that belief and desire are conceptually interdependent, there is a clear sense in which the concept of content is normative. Thus, Boghossian s argument survives Miller s attack. References 1. Bykvist, K. and A. Hattiangadi. 2007. Does thought imply ought? Analysis 67: 277-85. 2. Boghossian, P. 2003. The Normativity of Content. Philosophical Issues13: 31 45. 3. Boghossian, P. 2005. Is meaning normative? In Philosophy Science Scientific Philosophy, ed. A. Beckermann and C. Nimtz. Paderborn: Mentis. 4. Engel, P. (2001): Is truth a norm? In Interpreting Davidson, eds. P. Kotatko et al. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications. 5. Gibbard, A. (2005): Truth and Correct Belief. Philosophical Issues, 15: 338 350. 6. Gibbard, A. (2003): Thoughts and Norms. Philosophical Issues, 13: 83 98. 7. Shah, N. (2003): How Truth Governs Belief. The Philosophical Review, 112: 447 482. 179

UJAH: Unizik Journal of Arts and Humanities 8. Shah, N. and Velleman, D. (2005): Doxastic Deliberation. The Philosophical Review, 114: 497 534. 9. Miller, A. 2008. Thoughts, oughts and the conceptual primacy of belief. Analysis68: 234 238. 10. Wedgwood, R. (2002): The Aim of Belief. Philosophical Perspectives, 16: 276 297. 180