VERIFICATION AND METAPHYSICS

Similar documents
Emotivism. Meta-ethical approaches

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first.

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

145 Philosophy of Science

A Priori Knowledge: Analytic? Synthetic A Priori (again) Is All A Priori Knowledge Analytic?

A-LEVEL Religious Studies

LENT 2018 THEORY OF MEANING DR MAARTEN STEENHAGEN

Ima Emotivist (EM) X is good means Hurrah for X! Moral judgments aren t true or false. We can t reason about basic moral principles.

THE ELIMINATION OF METAPHYSICS

Do we have knowledge of the external world?

Ethical non-naturalism

Faith and Thought. A Journal devoted to the study of the inter-relation of the Christian revelation and modem research. Vol. 92 Number I Summer 1961

Evidence and Transcendence

WHAT IS HUME S FORK? Certainty does not exist in science.

Overview. Is there a priori knowledge? No: Mill, Quine. Is there synthetic a priori knowledge? Yes: faculty of a priori intuition (Rationalism, Kant)

PHILOSOPHY IAS MAINS: QUESTIONS TREND ANALYSIS

Philosophy of Religion

Logic, Truth & Epistemology. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Kantian Deontology. A2 Ethics Revision Notes Page 1 of 7. Paul Nicholls 13P Religious Studies

Hume on Ideas, Impressions, and Knowledge

Hume s emotivism. Michael Lacewing

Theme 1: Ethical Thought, AS. divine command as an objective metaphysical foundation for morality.

Introduction to Philosophy

Module 1-4: Spirituality and Rationality

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

Philosophy 308 The Language Revolution Russell Marcus Hamilton College, Fall 2014

Subject Overview Curriculum pathway

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

Unit 2. WoK 1 - Perception. Tuesday, October 7, 14

Comments on Scott Soames, Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, volume I

PHILOSOPHICAL RAMIFICATIONS: THEORY, EXPERIMENT, & EMPIRICAL TRUTH

Chapter 31. Logical Positivism and the Scientific Conception of Philosophy

Key definitions Action Ad hominem argument Analytic A priori Axiom Bayes s theorem

The Philosophy of Language. Quine versus Meaning

A. J. Ayer ( )

Metaethics: An Introduction

AS Religious Studies. 7061/1 Philosophy of Religion and Ethics Mark scheme June Version: 1.0 Final

Higher National Unit Specification. General information for centres. Unit title: Philosophy C: An Introduction to Analytic Philosophy

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

Religious belief, hypothesis and attitudes

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

Christian Evidences. The Verification of Biblical Christianity, Part 2. CA312 LESSON 06 of 12

Subject Overview Curriculum pathway

PHI2391: Logical Empiricism I 8.0

Chapter Summaries: Language and Theology by Clark, Chapter 2. on secular philosophies of language. Many religious writers, he states, deny the

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

HARE S PRESCRIPTIVISM

1/12. The A Paralogisms

NOTES ON A PRIORI KNOWLEDGE 10/6/03

ON QUINE, ANALYTICITY, AND MEANING Wylie Breckenridge

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

5: Preliminaries to the Argument

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

The Construction of Empirical Concepts and the Establishment of the Real Possibility of Empirical Lawlikeness in Kant's Philosophy of Science

Some Notes Toward a Genealogy of Existential Philosophy Robert Burch

Sydenham College of Commerce & Economics. * Dr. Sunil S. Shete. * Associate Professor

Skepticism is True. Abraham Meidan

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

WJEC. WJEC/Eduqas Religious Studies for A Level Year 2 & A2 DRAFT. David Ballard Rhodri Thomas. Peter Cole, Richard Gray, Mark Lambe, Karl Lawson

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT David Hume: The Origin of Our Ideas and Skepticism about Causal Reasoning

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers

Theme 1: Arguments for the existence of God inductive, AS

AS RELIGIOUS STUDIES. Component 1: Philosophy of religion and ethics Report on the Examination June Version: 1.0

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

LANGUAGE, TRUTH AND LOGIC

Religious Language. Introduction

Varieties of Apriority

PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY

SAMPLE. Religious Language, Reference, and Autonomy

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

A-level Religious Studies

Epistemology. Diogenes: Master Cynic. The Ancient Greek Skeptics 4/6/2011. But is it really possible to claim knowledge of anything?

BRITISH PHILOSOPHICAL ASSOCIATION AQA PHILOSOPHY UNIT 3: MORAL PHILOSOPHY

Philosophy 3100: Ethical Theory

Searle vs. Chalmers Debate, 8/2005 with Death Monkey (Kevin Dolan)

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Introduction. Bernard Williams

Immanuel Kant. Great German philosophers whose influence was and continues to be immense; born in Konigsberg East Prussia, in 1724, died there in 1804

Copan, P. and P. Moser, eds., The Rationality of Theism, London: Routledge, 2003, pp.xi+292

A-level RELIGIOUS STUDIES 7062/1

Philosophical Ethics. Distinctions and Categories

Religious Language. 2+2=4

From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Philosophy Courses-1

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Revision Guide (all topics)

Introduction to Philosophy

Junior Research Fellow and Lecturer in Philosophy Worcester College, University of Oxford Walton Street Oxford OX1 2HB Great Britain

Law as a Social Fact: A Reply to Professor Martinez

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE

Chapter 2--How Do I Know Whether God Exists?

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

Phil/Ling 375: Meaning and Mind [Handout #10]

Emotivism and its critics

Transcription:

Michael Lacewing The project of logical positivism VERIFICATION AND METAPHYSICS In the 1930s, a school of philosophy arose called logical positivism. Like much philosophy, it was concerned with the foundations and possibility of knowledge, but approached the subject through the limitations of meaning. Much impressed by the logical analysis of language developed by Russell and the early Wittgenstein, and by the achievements of science, logical positivists developed a criterion for meaningful statements, called the principle of verification, that enabled them to reject as nonsense many traditional philosophical debates. In response to what they saw as the excesses of Hegelian idealism and the schools of thought it had spawned, they wanted to return philosophy once more to being the underlabourer of the sciences (Locke). In his book Language, Truth and Logic, A J Ayer defends this view. The principle of verification states that a statement only has meaning if it is either analytic or empirically verifiable. An analytic statement is true (or false) just in virtue of the meanings of the words. For instance, a bachelor is an unmarried man is analytically true, while a square has three sides is analytically false. A statement is empirically verifiable if empirical evidence would go towards establishing that the statement is true or false. For example, if I say the moon is made of green cheese, we can check this by scientific investigation. If I say the universe has 600 trillion planets, we can t check this by scientific investigation in practice, but we can do so in principle. We know how to show whether it is true or false, so it is verifiable even though we can t actually verify it. Why think these are the only two possibilities for meaning? Metaphysicians, after all, will reject the bald statement that metaphysics must be founded on the experience of the senses. Ayer accepts this. Given that we should accept outright that empirical hypotheses are meaningful, the debate is, then, over the a priori. As the a priori/a posteriori distinction is exhaustive (there s no third alternative), he seeks to show that all a priori truths are in fact analytic. And this argument is completed by showing that the purported statements of metaphysics, if not analytic, are literally meaningless. Strengths of verification Some logical positivists originally wanted to say that verification must be conclusive, that a statement must be possible to prove true or false. However, this is far too strong, as Ayer argues; empirical hypotheses are only ever more or less probable, never completely certain. So he weakened the claim to verification requires that empirical evidence can raise or reduce the probability that a statement is true. All statements about what is unobservable, therefore, must be translatable into statements that can be observed in order to be meaningful. This applies as much in science as anywhere. Claims about electrons, for instance, are translatable into what is observable in laboratory conditions. This, Ayer goes on to argue, must in fact be an analytic truth, i.e. this is what statements about electrons mean, if they are to mean anything at all. By contrast, metaphysical claims, such as claims about the Absolute or

God or values, cannot be translated into claims about anything observable, and so are, in fact, meaningless (or more accurately literally meaningless they may have other functions). Statements about the past provide an interesting case. They are, now, impossible to prove; should they be taken to mean that there is something we can now experience that is relevant to their truth? This would be odd, since the core of the claim is that something was the case, not that it is now. So Ayer argues that claims about the past are claims that certain observations would have been possible or occurred under certain conditions. This claim as to what someone would or could experience isn t unusual: I make such a claim when I say what the back of my head looks like when no one is standing behind me. Philosophy, then, doesn t give us knowledge of a reality that transcends the investigations of science or is closed to commonsense. It is not a source of speculative truth. The function of philosophy is, instead, to bring to light the presuppositions of science and our everyday claims; in particular, to show what criteria are used to determine the truth of these claims. It does not, however, justify or establish scientific or common-sense beliefs that requires empirical enquiry (but, pace Descartes, Plato, and indeed Hume, nothing more). RULING THINGS OUT Ethics Amongst the claims ruled out as meaningless by the principle of verification are statements about right and wrong. If I say murder is wrong, this is not analytic, nor can any empirical investigation show this. We can show that murder causes grief and pain, or that it is often done out of anger. But we cannot demonstrate, in the same way, that it is wrong. Moral judgements are neither true nor false, because they do not actually state anything. If ethical statements don t state truths, and are therefore literally meaningless, what do they do? Ayer argued that ethical judgements express feelings: If I say to someone, You acted wrongly in stealing that money I am simply evincing my moral disapproval of it. It is as if I had said, You stole that money, in a peculiar tone of horror. (p. 142) Moral judgements express our feelings of approval or disapproval. Feelings are not cognitions of value, and value does not exist independently of our feelings. One of the most powerful objections to emotivism, as this theory became known, is that it seems to entail an unsatisfactory view of ethical discussion. If I say abortion is wrong and you say abortion is right, I am just expressing my disapproval of it and you are expressing your approval. I m just saying Boo! to abortion and you re saying Hurrah! for abortion. This is just like cheering for our own team there is no discussion, no reasoning, going on at all. Even worse, emotivism claims that we are trying to influence other people s feelings and actions. But trying to influence people without reasoning is just a form of manipulation.

Ayer thought this objection partly false, partly true. It is false because emotivists claim that there is a lot more to ethical discussion the facts. When arguing over animal rights, say, we are constantly drawing facts to each other s attention. I point out how much animals suffer in factory farms. You point out how much more sophisticated human beings are than animals. And so on. In fact, says Ayer, all the discussion is about the facts. If we both agree on the facts, but still disagree morally, there is no more discussion that can take place. And this is why the objection is true but not an objection. When all the facts are in, there is nothing left to discuss. Emotivists since Ayer have added another layer. The attitudes and feelings we express in our moral judgements don t occur in isolation. If I disapprove of an action, practically speaking, I must also have similar feelings about similar actions, or my feelings will not provide consistent guidance about how to live. Moral disagreement, then, can be about the relations between different feelings that we have. For example, deciding whether abortion is right or wrong is complicated because there are many feelings involved, sympathy towards the mother, sympathy towards the foetus, feelings about human life, death, and parenthood. It is difficult to work out how these feelings can all be acted upon, and that is why people disagree. But we may still object that a sense of people s rationality in weighing up which feelings or attitudes to give up, which to keep, is still missing. We have no sense of one set of attitudes being part of a better life than any other. Ayer will respond that the idea of one life being better than another is itself an expression of feeling; hence we may still talk this way. Nothing that was ever available in the first place has been lost. Religion God exists, and so all other talk of God, also falls foul of the verification principle, claims Ayer. Despite the best attempts of the ontological argument, we cannot prove God exists from a priori premises using deduction alone. So God exists is not analytically true. Therefore, to be meaningful, God exists must be empirically verifiable. Ayer argues it is not. If a statement is an empirical hypothesis, it predicts our experience will be different depending on whether it is true or false. But this isn t true of God exists. It rules nothing empirical in and it rules nothing out. So it is meaningless. We can object that many people do think that God exists has empirical content. For example, the teleological argument argues that the design of the universe is evidence for the existence of God. And on the other hand, the problem of evil takes the existence and extent of suffering to be evidence against the existence of God. Ayer doesn t explicitly discuss these responses, but the spirit of his response is perhaps captured by Anthony Flew, who argues that God exists is only an empirical hypothesis if we can think of experiences that could lead to belief or disbelief in God; most people s belief in God and so their assertion that God exists isn t open to this kind of disconfirmation (the religious believer s response to the problem of evil is not normally to accept that it decreases the probability that God exists, but rather that it increases the probability that we don t understand God s plans). John Hick argues that even if we can t verify the existence of God in this life, that doesn t mean religious language is meaningless. He develops the idea of eschatological verification, whereby experiences of God in the afterlife would establish the truth of the existence of God. In arguing that talk of God is meaningless, Ayer overlooked possible experiences of life after death. Ayer might respond that the only way that talk of life after

death makes sense is if there are experiences we can relate it to now. If so, Hick could reply that invoking the counterfactual what we would experience after our death, if anything is as legitimate as invoking counterfactuals about the past. Some philosophers argue that religious language attempts to capture something of religious experience, although it is inexpressible in literal terms. Ayer responds that whatever religious experiences reveal, they cannot be said to reveal any facts. Facts are the content of statements that purport to be intelligible and can be expressed literally. If talk of God is non-empirical, it is literally unintelligible, hence meaningless. REJECTING THE VERIFICATION PRINCIPLE The verification principle has since been rejected by philosophers as an inadequate account of what it is for a statement to have meaning. A first famous objection is that it renders universal statements, such as All swans are white meaningless because although you could prove this false, no experience will prove it true (there might always be a swan out there somewhere which isn t white). This, though, is dealt with by Ayer s weakening of verification to only require experience to support or reduce the probability of a claim. And, in his discussion of induction, he argues that it is rational to believe, not as a certainty, but as a probability that grows with the range of experience we have, that what we haven t experienced will conform to what we have. It is irrational to expect a proof. The main difficulty with logical positivism is that according to the principle of verification, the principle of verification itself is meaningless. The claim that a statement only has meaning if it is analytic or can be verified empirically is not analytic and cannot be verified empirically. But if the principle of verification is meaningless, then what it claims cannot be true. So it does not give us any reason to believe that the claims of ethics are meaningless. Ayer claims, in his Introduction to the second edition, that the principle is intended as a definition, not an empirical hypothesis about meaning, though not an arbitrary one. In other words, it is intended to reflect upon and clarify our understanding of meaningful uses of words. Since we do use the term meaningful in a variety of ways, he wishes only to focus on literal meaning. Ayer accepts that the verification principle isn t obviously an accurate criterion of literal meaning, but that is why he provides arguments in specific cases ethics, religion, a priori knowledge which support it. But to this, any philosopher may respond by rejecting both his specific arguments and the verification principle wholesale. It would seem, then, that the verification principle is only as certain as the arguments that are intended to exemplify the consequences of its application. If we do not find those convincing, the principle provides no independent support. However, verificationism opens up a question: are statements about God and values meaningful, and if so, how? It seems clear that not all language consists of making statements about how the world is. Are religious and ethical language like statements of science, or do they serve some other human purpose? One problem with thinking that they make statements about the world is that these statements refer to things (God, values) that we cannot see or experience via the senses. Should we think that moral and mystical intuition is a type of experience of a supernatural or metaphysical world? Or are they not experiences of the world at all? The debate about verification becomes a

debate about naturalism, and how human beings and their capacities for knowledge fit into the scientific image of the world.