Agassi on Smith 1. Hume Studies, 12, 1986,

Similar documents
History of Modern Philosophy

PL 406 HISTORY OF MODERN PHILOSOPHY Fall 2009

COURSE GOALS: PROFESSOR: Chris Latiolais Philosophy Department Kalamazoo College Humphrey House #202 Telephone # Offices Hours:

Skepticism is True. Abraham Meidan

Syllabus. Primary Sources, 2 edition. Hackett, Various supplementary handouts, available in class and on the course website.

Syllabus. Primary Sources, 2 edition. Hackett, Various supplementary handouts, available in class and on the course website.

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7c The World

Introduction to Philosophy: The Big Picture

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition:

Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses. David Hume

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

The British Empiricism

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Huemer s Problem of Memory Knowledge

Courses providing assessment data PHL 202. Semester/Year

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 7 : E P I S T E M O L O G Y - K A N T

Reading Questions for Phil , Fall 2016 (Daniel)

UNIVERSITY OF WATERLOO DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY PHILOSOPHY 110A,

Are Miracles Identifiable?

Mind (1981) Vol xc, To Save Verisimilitude

Agency and Responsibility. According to Christine Korsgaard, Kantian hypothetical and categorical imperative

Evidential arguments from evil

PHILOSOPHY EPISTEMOLOGY ESSAY TOPICS AND INSTRUCTIONS

A History Of Philosophy, Vol. 5: Modern Philosophy - The British Philosophers From Hobbes To Hume By Frederick Copleston

Epistemology Naturalized

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

CONTENTS III SYNTHETIC A PRIORI JUDGEMENTS. PREFACE CHAPTER INTRODUCTldN

West Los Angeles College. Philosophy 1 Introduction to Philosophy. Spring Instructor. Rick Mayock, Professor of Philosophy

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Ethical non-naturalism

The dangers of the sovereign being the judge of rationality

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

1/7. Metaphysics. Course Leader: Dr. Gary Banham. Room Tel. Ext.: 3036

Philosophy 18: Early Modern Philosophy

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

PHILOSOPHY IAS MAINS: QUESTIONS TREND ANALYSIS

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Metaphysics. Gary Banham

1/8. Introduction to Kant: The Project of Critique

The CopernicanRevolution

Putnam and the Contextually A Priori Gary Ebbs University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign

Self-Evidence in Finnis Natural Law Theory: A Reply to Sayers

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 7 : E P I S T E M O L O G Y - K A N T

Courses Description. Philosophy Department

Impact Hour. May 15, 2016

LA Mission College Mark Pursley Fall 2016 Note:

Hume s Critique of Miracles

Hume s Law Violated? Rik Peels. The Journal of Value Inquiry ISSN J Value Inquiry DOI /s

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2014

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

TABLE OF CONTENTS. A. "The Way The World Really Is" 46 B. The First Philosophers: The "Turning Point of Civilization" 47

Evolution: The Darwinian Revolutions BIOEE 2070 / HIST 2870 / STS 2871

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

Class 6 - Scientific Method

THE CRISIS OF THE SCmNCES AS EXPRESSION OF THE RADICAL LIFE-CRISIS OF EUROPEAN HUMANITY

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Introduction. 1 Bertrand Russell, The Problems of Philosophy (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, n.d.), 7.

Chapter 2--How Do I Know Whether God Exists?

LA Mission College Mark Pursley Spring 2018 Note:

The Many Problems of Memory Knowledge (Short Version)

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

Arguing with Libertarianism without Argument : Critical Rationalism and how it applies to Libertarianism

DOMINICAN UNIVERSITY COLLEGE

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Two Kinds of Moral Relativism

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

III. RULES OF POLICY (TEAM) DEBATE. A. General

Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2

Methodological criticism vs. ideology and hypocrisy Lawrence A. Boland, FRSC Simon Fraser University There was a time when any university-educated

STEWART COHEN AND THE CONTEXTUALIST THEORY OF JUSTIFICATION

God has a mind- Romans 11:34 "who has known the mind of the Lord

Wittgenstein, Russell, and Religion. Patrick DUCRAY

Kant and the 19 th Century ***Syllabus***

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

Reid Against Skepticism

HUME'S THEORY OF IMAGINATION

Contents. Detailed Chapter Contents Preface to the First Edition (2003) Preface to the Second Edition (2013) xiii

Immanuel Kant. Great German philosophers whose influence was and continues to be immense; born in Konigsberg East Prussia, in 1724, died there in 1804

Important dates. PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since David Hume ( )

PH 1000 Introduction to Philosophy, or PH 1001 Practical Reasoning

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Hobbes. Prince of Peace. Bernard Gert. Polity

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

Philosophy 3100: Ethical Theory

A Rational Solution to the Problem of Moral Error Theory? Benjamin Scott Harrison

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

PH 701 Faith, Reason, and Christian Belief

The Role of Love in the Thought of Kant and Kierkegaard

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

Every simple idea has a simple impression, which resembles it; and every simple impression a correspondent idea

Transcription:

Agassi on Smith 1 Hume Studies, 12, 1986, 92-98. A NOTE ON SMITH S TERM NATURALISM The reader of contemporary Hume literature may feel exasperated when reading recent authors. A conspicuous example is A.J. Ayer (Hume, 1982; see index, Art, Natural beliefs), who declares they endorse Kemp Smith s view of Hume s naturalism without sufficiently clarifying what they - or Smith - might exactly mean by this term. Charles W. Hendel, in the 1963 edition of his 1924 Studies in the Philosophy of David Hume, adds eight pages of a new preface and thirty-one pages of a review of Hume scholarship between 1925 and 1962, and he speaks at great length there of his life-long friendship and cooperation with Norman Kemp Smith and appreciation of his work. He says (p. xlviii), There is a disposition today to assimilate Hume s thought to naturalism as understood in the contemporary sense. He does not say what this contemporary sense is, and the statement just quoted seems to have served as the seal of approval and the legitimation of this questionable practice. Hendel s new (1963) material mentions Smith s discussion of Hume s naturalism - but refers only to Smith s early work, The Naturalism of Hume, Mind, 14, 1905, 149-173 and 335-347, not to Smith s famous The Philosophy of David Hume of 1941, even though he deems that work of great consequence for Hume scholarship (p. xxxviii) and a masterwork (p. xxxix). The early work (1905) of Smith is already mentioned by Hendel in the body of the 1924 work (p. 361), although there, clearly, the word naturalism, whatever its meaning is, and however contemporary then, is not necessarily the contemporary sense of 1962. The work which clearly (if implicitly) distinguishes between the traditional sense and Smith s 1905 sense of naturalism is John Laird s

Agassi on Smith 2 Hume s Philosophy of Human Nature, 1932, 1967. We find there a discussion of Hume s naturalism (beginning of Chapter II), as well as of Hume s Naturalism (Chapter VI, fifth and fourth paragraphs from the end), with reference to Smith s 1905 work. Now, the traditional sense of naturalism is straightforward and seems to have been instituted by Pierre Bayle to designate the view of the world as devoid of all supernatural intervention, the view of the world as disenchanted, to use the equivalent term accredited to Max Weber. Clearly, all Epicureans and neo- Epicureans, Hume included, were naturalists in this sense. This is not the sense in which Smith uses it in his 1905 essay, The Naturalism of Hume. The first part of this essay opposes T. H. Green s traditional reading of Hume as a philosopher who streamlined the ideas of Locke and of Berkeley and proposes to replace it with the view of Hume s view as naturalism. Hume s... naturalistic view of reason, we are told (p. 158), is a new theory of belief : Humean belief, on Smith s new reading, is not caused by knowledge but precedes it, and as it is not caused by knowledge it is not destroyed by doubt (p. 165). Smith declared his reading quite revolutionary, yet it may be endorsed without rejecting Green s reading. Smith does not even attempt to re-interpret in detail the passages which prima facie conform to Green s reading. The second part of his essay is the application of his revolutionary reading to psychology and to ethics. Smith devotes the preface of his The Phi1osophy of David Hume (1941) to a revision of his 1905 study. It seems he did not alter his attitude towards the first part but only to the second: he thought the starting point of Hume s study was his concern not for naturalism but for moral philosophy, or the science of human nature (opening words of Hume s

Agassi on Smith 3 Inquiry, cf. Hendel, op. cit., p. xlvi). This statement has to do with emphasis, not with the meanings of terms or with ascriptions of views (and it is erroneous, or at least limited; but this is another matter). This is not to deny that Hume was a naturalist in Bayle s sense, as everyone today agrees. Most philosophers today share this naturalism with Hume. His attitude and way of thinking are virtually ubiquitous, says Hendel (p. xl), no matter what the topic of discourse may be, yet he says this in the context of a discussion of Hume s naturalism in Bayle s sense. It is doubtless true that Hume was deeply concerned with that naturalism and linked it with moral philosophy and with his own naturalism in Smith s sense. (See E. C. Mossner, Hume s Earliest Memoranda, J. Hist. Id., 9, 1948, 492-518 and Mossner s later works.) I have myself explained in The Unity of Hume s Thought, Hume Studies, 10, 1985, why I share Smith s reading of Hume s naturalism as an essential ingredient of his moral philosophy, or the science of human nature, but unlike Smith I do not read this as the basis of Hume s mitigated skepticism or of any other epistemology which we might attribute to Hume. This, too, is an open matter. What is obvious, however, is that anyone who endorses Smith s reading of Hume s naturalism and its role should explain his meaning with some care, and, in the light of the criticism of Smith s reading of Hume s use of his naturalism in epistemology, perhaps also try to do better than Smith. Though priority problems are distasteful and, at least in philosophy, very hard to settle, I feel I should mention a prior expression of Smith s 1905 revolutionary thesis that since according to Hume beliefs are prior to reason, Hume deemed the critique of reason as irrelevant to beliefs. It is to be found in the work of an American expatriate, Ezra Albert Cook, Humes

Agassi on Smith 4 Theorie über die Realität der Aussenwelt, Inaugural Dissertation, etc., Halle, 1904. Even the table of contents of this 40 page book should suffice, with titles like, Ch. 1. The Faith in the Outer World is Unavoidable, or The Faith in the Outer World not from Reason Deduced (my stilted translation). He concludes by quoting both Hume s and Kant s insistence that realism is unavoidable. The only difference is that this author declares Hume s view to be skepticism, and he sides with Kant against Hume. Thus, his reading of Hume is traditional, and yet Smith introduces the same reading as if it were opposed to tradition and therefore revolutionary. I have argued in The Unity of Hume s Thought that a position like Cook s is more logical than Smith s since there is no contradiction between the view that beliefs are irrational and phenomenalism, so that we may ascribe both to Hume without thereby imputing to him an inconsistency: both ascriptions agree that Hume allows no justification of realism either by reason or by sense-experience. This very reading, endorsed by both Cook and Smith, and by everyone before and up till World War II, is now challenged, as I have described in The Unity of Hume s Thought, where I ascribe to him the moderate view between justification and skepticism, as he wished, though without considering his effort successful. As to the origins of naturalism and of naturalism, the former doctrine is ancient, the latter modern. It was known in the Talmudic literature as Epicureanism. It is the corollary to Democritus doctrine of atoms and the void; the fragments indicate he was aware of it; certainly Plato was, and this explains his unbounded hostility to Democritus. Naturalism was a reaction to attempts to impose beliefs, i.e., to religious wars. Robert Boyle has clearly expressed it in his Occasional Reflections (sec. 4, Disc. xi): A senate or a monarchy may indeed command my life and fortune: but

Agassi on Smith 5 as for my opinions,... I cannot in most cases command them myself, but must suffer them to be such, as the nature of things. The same view is also expressed by Spinoza, Tractatus Politico-Theologicus. The importance of naturalism for Boyle, however, is that it supports freedom of thought; it was not meant to conflict with the Baconian rationalistic demand for giving up received opinion and accepting only empirically founded belief. Hume denied the claim that belief is rational. Yet, clearly, Hume thought belief can be rational, as his History of England, Appendix to Reign of King Charles II, clearly indicates:...there flourished during this period a Boyle and a Newton, men who trod with cautious, and therefore, with more secure steps, the only road which leads to true philosophy. Newton, he says, was cautious in admitting no principles but such as were founded on experiment; but resolute to adopt every such principle, however new and unusual. Thus, whereas Boyle held naturalism with respect to all humans, Hume held it only with respect to the vulgar, not the philosopher. The revolutionary claim of Smith, namely the view that naturalism makes criticism irrelevant to belief and hence mitigates it, is thus inconsistent with other claims of Hume. For more detail see The Unity of Hume s Thought. Hence, it was a misreading of Hume s philosophy that invited the claim that it has opened the floodgates for irrationalism (Russell, A History of Western Philosophy, chapter on Hume; Popper, Conjectures and Refutations, Chapter 1). At most it was this misreading that is responsible for that. More likely it was the failure of the French Revolution. Hence, the boot is on the other foot: it was the philosophy that Hume criticized as too cock-sure that has opened the floodgates for irrationalism. Joseph Agassi Tel-Aviv University and York University, Toronto