Gun Violence Agnosticism

Similar documents
CULTURE AFFECTS OUR BELIEFS ABOUT FIREARMS, BUT DATA ARE ALSO IMPORTANT

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

CONTEMPORARY MORAL PROBLEMS LECTURE 14 CAPITAL PUNISHMENT PART 2

Disvalue in nature and intervention *

Religion, peace and conflict

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

REASONS AND ENTAILMENT

Council on American-Islamic Relations RESEARCH CENTER AMERICAN PUBLIC OPINION ABOUT ISLAM AND MUSLIMS

Philosophy of Religion 21: (1987).,, 9 Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht - Printed in the Nethenanas

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

Jan Narveson, Pacifism: A. Philosophical Examination 1

Time travel and the open future

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University THE DEMANDS OF ACT CONSEQUENTIALISM

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Honor in the Military and the Possible Implication for the Traditional Separation

A Contractualist Reply

If Everyone Does It, Then You Can Too Charlie Melman

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

Comment on Robert Audi, Democratic Authority and the Separation of Church and State

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1

To link to this article:

2014 Examination Report 2014 Extended Investigation GA 2: Critical Thinking Test GENERAL COMMENTS

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships

Christian-Muslim Relationships in Medan. and Dalihan na tolu. A Social Capital Study. of The Batak Cultural Values

The University of Chicago Press

Law and Authority. An unjust law is not a law

Goldman on Knowledge as True Belief. Alvin Goldman (2002a, 183) distinguishes the following four putative uses or senses of

Is Epistemic Probability Pascalian?

R. M. Hare (1919 ) SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG. Definition of moral judgments. Prescriptivism

National Center for Life and Liberty CHURCH SECURITY POLICIES

Bernard Hoose - Proportionalism

THE BELIEF IN GOD AND IMMORTALITY A Psychological, Anthropological and Statistical Study

Phil 108, August 10, 2010 Punishment

The Many Problems of Memory Knowledge (Short Version)

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Norva Y S Lo Produced by Norva Y S Lo Edited by Andrew Brennan

THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY

Citation for published version (APA): Petersen, T. S. (2011). What Is Legal Moralism? Sats, 12(1), DOI: /sats.

RMPS Assignment. National 5/Higher. Name: Class: Teacher: My Question:

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Deontology, Rationality, and Agent-Centered Restrictions

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth).

EXECUTIVE SUMMARY. The mandate for the study was to:

Scanlon on Double Effect

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

The free will defense

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Who Has the Burden of Proof? Must the Christian Provide Adequate Reasons for Christian Beliefs?

THE HUMAN BODY SWORD KRIS BORER * LIBERTARIAN PAPERS VOL. 2, ART. NO. 20 (2010)

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Responsibility and Normative Moral Theories

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

THE POSSIBILITY OF AN ALL-KNOWING GOD

Equality, Fairness, and Responsibility in an Unequal World

ABSTRACT: In this paper, I argue that Phenomenal Conservatism (PC) is not superior to

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Hugh LaFollette: The Practice of Ethics

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

5 A Modal Version of the

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Does law have to be effective in order for it to be valid?

PHENOMENAL CONSERVATISM, JUSTIFICATION, AND SELF-DEFEAT

Proofs of Non-existence

On the Relationship between Religiosity and Ideology

Compatibilist Objections to Prepunishment

Epistemic Consequentialism, Truth Fairies and Worse Fairies

A CRITIQUE OF THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. A Paper. Presented to. Dr. Douglas Blount. Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary. In Partial Fulfillment

On Risk & Responsibility: Gun Control and the Ethics of Hunting

The unity of the normative

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

THE ROAD TO HELL by Alastair Norcross 1. Introduction: The Doctrine of the Double Effect.

Rawls, rationality, and responsibility: Why we should not treat our endowments as morally arbitrary

IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?''

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

THE ROLE OF COHERENCE OF EVIDENCE IN THE NON- DYNAMIC MODEL OF CONFIRMATION TOMOJI SHOGENJI

Blame and Forfeiture. The central issue that a theory of punishment must address is why we are we permitted to

Rethinking Development: the Centrality of Human Rights

Skepticism and Internalism

Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

The Non-Identity Problem from Reasons and Persons by Derek Parfit (1984)

Epistemological Foundations for Koons Cosmological Argument?

What should I believe? What should I believe when people disagree with me?

what makes reasons sufficient?

THE CHARACTER, CLAIMS AND PRACTICAL WORKINGS OF FREEMASONRY. Forward Freemasonry s Attempted Murder of Ed Decker by Ed Decker

DEREK FLOOD. Trinity Institute, The Good News Now Evolving with the Gospel of Jesus

Kelly James Clark and Raymond VanArragon (eds.), Evidence and Religious Belief, Oxford UP, 2011, 240pp., $65.00 (hbk), ISBN

Utilitarianism, Multiplicity, and Liberalism

PLEASESURE, DESIRE AND OPPOSITENESS

ON (NOT) BELIEVING THAT GOD HAS ANSWERED A PRAYER

WHEN is a moral theory self-defeating? I suggest the following.

What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social

Transcription:

Essays in Philosophy Volume 16 Issue 2 Philosophy & Gun Control Article 6 7-7-2015 Gun Violence Agnosticism C'Zar Bernstein Oriel College, Oxford University Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/eip Recommended Citation Bernstein, C'Zar (2015) "Gun Violence Agnosticism," Essays in Philosophy: Vol. 16: Iss. 2, Article 6. http://dx.doi.org/10.7710/ 1526-0569.1534 Essays in Philosophy is a biannual journal published by Pacific University Library ISSN 1526-0569 http://commons.pacificu.edu/eip/

Gun Violence Agnosticism C Zar Bernstein Oriel College, Oxford University Abstract In this paper, I shall argue that the evidence supports, at the very best for the anti-gun side, agnosticism about the negative criminogenic effects of gun ownership. Given the plausible proposition that there is at least a prima facie moral right (a right that can be outweighed given sufficiently weighty considerations) to keep and bear arms, I argue that agnosticism supports the proposition that there ought to be a legal right to keep and bear arms. Essays Philos (2015)16:232-246 DOI: 10.7710/1526-0569.1534 Published online: 7 July 2015. C Zar Bernstein 2015 Contact author: czar.bernstein@oriel.ox.ac.uk 232

Essays in Philosophy 16(2) B eliefs about guns are almost invariably formed in response to highly publicised mass shootings and stories about violent gun crimes, and not on the basis of an impartial examination of the relevant criminological evidence. The emotional responses of people to these kinds of events have a significant impact on public policy, usually in the direction of gun control and outright gun bans. Outright bans and strict controls immediately followed the Dunblane and Port Arthur massacres in the United Kingdom and Australia, respectively. The situation in the United States is much more complex (because gun ownership rights are constitutionally protected), but calls for strict gun controls by high-level politicians (which were ultimately unsuccessful) immediately followed the infamous Aurora and Newtown massacres. In this paper, I shall argue that these kinds of immediate (largely emotional) responses are irrational in the light of the evidence. The evidence that the prevalence of gun ownership significantly increases violent crime is very weak. Indeed, the best evidence suggests either that there is a negative effect on crime or no discernible effect whatever. I shall argue that the evidence supports, at the very best for the anti-gun side, agnosticism about the negative criminogenic effects of gun ownership. Given the plausible proposition that there is at least a prima facie moral right (a right that can be outweighed given sufficiently weighty considerations) to keep and bear arms, I argue that agnosticism supports the proposition that there ought to be a legal right to keep and bear arms. The central thesis of this paper is as follows: (GVA) Nobody who has impartially examined the extant criminological evidence knows that the 233

Gun Violence Agnosticism Bernstein criminogenic harms of gun ownership and carrying outweigh the benefits. The philosophical significance of GVA will become clearer later in this paper, but I shall briefly state why it is significant, if true. If there is a prima facie right to own a gun, then a gun ban would be just (in the fact-relative sense) only if the harms of common gun ownership significantly outweigh the benefits (to a degree sufficient to override the right). Insofar as gun bans ought to be implemented by politicians only after they know that this consequentialist calculation is true on the basis of an impartial examination of the extant evidence, GVA implies that a gun ban in the US that is based on the proposition that the criminogenic harms of gun ownership and carrying outweigh the benefits would be unjust (at least in the evidence-relative sense). i Let us now consider whether GVA is true. The truth of GVA depends importantly on whether the extant criminological evidence significantly supports the following three hypotheses: Crime-increasing hypothesis (CIH): Gun ownership causes significant increases in rates of violent crime. Homicide-increasing hypothesis (HIH): Gun ownership causes significant increases in rates of homicide. Anti-Carrying hypothesis (ACH): Laws that allow civilians to carry firearms concealed in public significantly increase violent crime rates. After an impartial examination of the relevant evidence, someone knows that the criminogenic harms of gun 234

Essays in Philosophy 16(2) ownership and carrying outweigh the benefits only if she knows that CIH, HIH, and ACH are true, and she knows that they are true only if the evidence supports these hypotheses. Moreover, the evidence supports them in the relevant sense only if they are more probable than not given that evidence. In what follows, I shall argue that the extant criminological evidence very probably does not support CIH, HIH, or ACH in this way. What, then, does the evidence say? It will be helpful to begin with a very recent methodological survey of the relevant evidence. Kleck (2015) reviewed 41 studies that tested CIH and HIH. He identified methodologically superior studies on the basis of the following criteria: 1. A valid measure of gun levels was used. 2. The authors made an attempt to control for more than a handful of possible confounding variables. 3. The authors used suitable causal order procedures to deal with the possibility of crime rates affecting gun rates, instead of the reverse. It is very clear that the evidence does not support CIH. Of the 90 findings generated by the 41 studies reviewed, only 26 (~29%) support CIH, whereas 64 (~71%) found against CIH. None of the findings of studies for which more than one of (1) (3) are true supported CIH. The same trend holds with respect to HIH. Only 36% of studies for which (1) is true support HIH compared to 62% of studies for which (1) is false. Of the studies for which (3) is false, 57% support HIH; no studies for which (3) is true found in favour of HIH. Of the studies for which (2) is false, that is, of the studies that controlled for fewer than five significant control variables, 59% found in favour of HIH. This drops to just 17% for studies that controlled for more than five significant control variables. Remarkably, 14 of the 41 235

Gun Violence Agnosticism Bernstein studies reviewed by Kleck did not control for a single confounder and these were the studies that were most likely to find in favour of CIH and HIH. Importantly, only six studies controlled for more than five statistically significant control variables and all of them failed to support CIH and 83% found against HIH (they found either that there is no discernible effect or a slight crime-decreasing effect). Finally, there were only three studies for which all of (1) (3) are true and none of them supported CIH or HIH. On the contrary, Kovandzic et al. (2013), who controlled for ten confounding variables, found that increases in noncriminal gun prevalence would moderately decrease both gun and total homicide rates. Of the studies for which all of (1) (3) are false (23 of the 41 reviewed), 65% found in favour of HIH. ii Kleck concludes: The overall pattern is very clear the more methodologically adequate research is, the less likely it is to support the more guns-more crime hypothesis. Kleck s conclusion, if correct, strongly supports GVA. One implication of the above is that many of the arguments endorsed by anti-gun philosophers fail. Dixon (2011), for example, appeals to Killias (1993), Hemenway and Miller (2000), and Killias et al. (2001) in support of CIH and HIH. But, according to Kleck (2015), these were among the studies that controlled for no significant control variables and did not take into account the causal order problem. In other words, the studies to which Dixon appealed in support of his argument from net harms are among the methodologically worst studies available. The best studies cannot be used to support CIH or HIH in an argument for gun bans. The general conclusion to GVA and against CIH or HIH is supported by two meta-analyses published by the U.S. National Academy of Sciences (NAS) and the Centers for 236

Essays in Philosophy 16(2) Disease Control (CDC). Wellford et al. (2004), on behalf of the NAS, reviewed 253 articles, 99 books, and 43 government publications and failed to identify any gun control that had reduced violent crime, suicide, or gun accidents. iii Specifically, they could not determine whether associations between gun ownership and homicide demonstrate a causal relationship. Indeed, they concluded that existing research studies and data include a wealth of descriptive information...but...do not credibly demonstrate a causal relationship between the ownership of firearms and the causes or prevention of criminal violence or suicide. iv Hahn et al. (2003: 18), on behalf of the CDC, also reviewed the then-extant literature and concluded that there was insufficient evidence to determine the effectiveness of any of the firearms laws reviewed for preventing violence. Kleck s (2015) recent review of the literature is an important update and coheres well with these earlier results. Once again, given these findings, GVA is very plausible. What does the evidence say about ACH? So-called shallissue laws allow apparently law-abiding civilians to carry guns concealed in public. One might object by arguing that allowing people to carry firearms significantly harms society, perhaps by increasing violent crime. Presumably the idea is that permit holders are prone to commit violent crimes, particularly with their guns. This is far from obvious. The state with the greatest number of permit holders is Florida (1.2 million, or about 8.2% of the state s population). From 1987 to 2014, Florida issued permits to more than 2.6 million people, but only 168 (about 0.006%) have had their permits revoked for any type of firearms related violation, the most common being accidentally carrying a concealed handgun into a gun-free zone such as a school or an airport, not threats or acts of violence...for all revocations, the annual rate is 0.012%. v 237

Gun Violence Agnosticism Bernstein By comparison, the annual rate of firearms violations by police (from 1 Jan 2005 to 31 Dec 2007) in Florida was 0.007%, higher than the rate for permit holders. vi Moreover, far from supporting ACH, the evidence seems to support the hypothesis that these laws reduce violent crime. Of the peer-reviewed studies, 20 found in favour of the crime-reduction hypothesis vii and 11 found no discernible effect. No peer-reviewed study published in an academic journal has hitherto supported ACH. viii Interestingly, the number of people with concealed handgun permits has increased significantly in the last few years. In 2011, at least 8 million people had permits, an increase from 4.6 million in 2007. This increased to well over 11 million people as of June 2014 (this is just over 4.5% of the total population). ix If it were true that shallissue laws contributed significantly to violent crime, we would expect significant increases in violent crime to follow significant increases in the number of permit holders and gun carriers. In fact, the opposite is the case: Between 2007 and the preliminary estimates for 2013, murder rates have fallen from 5.6 to 4.4 per 100,000 a 22 percent drop in the murder rate at the same time that the percentage of the adult population with permits soared by 130 percent. Overall violent crime also fell by the same percentage, 22 percent, over that period of time. Using this new state level permit data from 2007 on, our analysis suggests that each one percentage point increase in the percent of the adult population holding permits is roughly associated with a 1.4 percent drop in the murder rate. x At the very best for the anti-gun side, the evidence supports the middle ground on which these laws do not contribute 238

Essays in Philosophy 16(2) significantly to rates of violent crime one way or the other. At worst, the evidence supports the hypothesis that these laws reduce violent crime. There is no evidence from the academic, peer-reviewed literature to suppose that ACH is the case. If the crime-reduction hypothesis is correct, the best explanation is that criminals are deterred from committing crimes in areas where there is a reasonable chance that potential victims will be armed. Because these handguns are carried concealed, criminals are not able to know in advance which of their victims will be unarmed. The risk to criminals in these areas is, therefore, far greater than in areas where gun carrying by civilians is prohibited. Here is where we stand so far. The qualitatively best studies support neither CIH nor HIH. Studies that support either of these two hypotheses suffer from significant methodological flaws. If this is right, the conclusion we ought to draw is that the extant scholarly criminological research does not make CIH and HIH more probable than not, and because this is a requirement of knowing whether CIH and HIH are true (after an impartial examination of the evidence), it follows that anybody who is aware of these facts does not know that CIH and HIH are true. We saw, furthermore, that not a single published peer-reviewed article supports ACH and most support the hypothesis that carry laws decrease violent crime. Given the extant evidence on this question, we are at best warranted in believing that these laws do not contribute significantly to violent crime one way or the other. If all of the above is correct, then GVA is true. Knowledge that gun ownership and carrying causes more harm from crime than good requires knowledge that CIH, HIH, and ACH are true, which in turn requires sufficient evidence. As we have seen, we lack sufficient evidence to know that these hypotheses are correct. I conclude that GVA is true. 239

Gun Violence Agnosticism Bernstein What is the significance of GVA s being true? I claim that GVA, in conjunction with the proposition that we have a prima facie right to keep and bear arms, implies that there ought to be a legal right to keep and bear arms and that, therefore, a gun ban would be unjust. Before we see why, let us first examine the reasons we have to suppose that such a right exists. Most philosophers argue for the right to keep and bear arms from the right of self-defence. xi Elsewhere, I, with colleagues, have argued as follows: If x (where x is an artifact or tool) is a reasonable means of individual selfdefence, then people have a prima facie right to be allowed to own x. Firearms are a reasonable means of individual selfdefence. Hence, people have a prima facie right to be allowed to own firearms. xii By a reasonable means of individual self-defense, I mean a means of self-defense that is able to effectively and reliably deliver a proportionate amount of force and is able to discriminate between an aggressor and innocent bystander (unlike, say, nuclear weapons). xiii There is a good amount of empirical evidence that guns qualify as reasonable in this sense. Using data from the U.S. Department of Justice s National Crime Victimization Survey, Kleck (2001: 289) found that using a gun defensively is very effective at reducing a victim s risk of injury in assaults. After assault victims took selfprotection action with a gun, only 3.6 per cent were injured, compared to 12.6 per cent of victims who screamed, 15.2 per cent of victims who tried to reason with the offender, 8.6 per cent of victims who attacked the offender without a weapon, 5.4 per cent of victims who attempted to flee, and 55.2 per cent of victims who took no self-protection actions whatever. In the vast majority of these cases, victims did not actually fire the gun; they merely had to brandish the weapon in order to break off an attack. xiv But we do not need to argue from self-defence to get to this conclusion. Liberty considerations will get us to it, for we 240

Essays in Philosophy 16(2) may argue as follows. People have a right to be allowed to own x if owning x is not intrinsically immoral and there are no overriding contingent reasons for prohibiting the owning of x. That is, there is a defeasible presumption in favour of liberty. But ownership of guns is not intrinsically immoral. There are clearly situations in which gun ownership is not wrong. Consider cases in which one s government is extremely repressive or in which one s country is occupied by a foreign and brutal invader. It is very implausible to suppose that armed resistance of this kind of oppression is wrong (think about resistance fighters during the Second World War). Or consider cases in which one s government has completely failed to fight violent crime such that there is a significant probability that one s life will be threatened. Defence of the citizenry falls under the police powers of the state. It is plausible to suppose that when the state is unable to fulfill its obligations the power falls back into the hands of the citizenry. Would we say of someone who has decided to obtain a gun in order to protect his family when his government has failed to do so that he has acted wrongly? Surely not. If this is right, then ownership of firearms is not intrinsically immoral. Consequently, people have a right to be allowed to own a gun if there are not overriding contingent reasons for prohibition. This just is a prima face right to be allowed to own a gun. xv So far we have the conclusion: given that there are no overriding contingent reasons for prohibition, people have a right to own a gun. In this paper, I have questioned whether one reason to suppose that there are overriding contingent reasons for prohibition succeeds, namely, that the criminogenic harms outweigh the benefits. But one can still question whether guns ought to be allowed given the obvious truth that some people are harmed as a result of their being permitted. In response, why should this fact be seen as an overriding consideration? Rights are supposed to 241

Gun Violence Agnosticism Bernstein hold in the face of negative consequences; so merely pointing out that people sometimes use guns to wrongly harm other people is not sufficient to establish the conclusion that there is an overriding reason to ban guns. The proponent of this line would have to say that the harm caused by private gun ownership is so great that the prima facie right is overridden, but she cannot say that if there are no significant effects one way or the other. If what I have argued above is close to being accurate, it is unlikely, given the evidence, that this is the case. It is hard to see why guns should be banned because the harm they cause is so great if the same harm would obtain in the absence of guns. Moreover, for all the objector knows, more people would be harmed following a gun ban as a result of their not having a very effective self-defense tool, and these considerations seem to be at least on a par. We now have the truth of GVA and the proposition that people have a prima facie right to own a gun. How do these two propositions imply that there ought to be a legal right to keep and bear arms and that a gun ban would be unjust? As previously mentioned, a prima facie right is a right that can be outweighed or overruled by sufficiently weighty considerations. The government ought to infringe on these rights only if (a) the reason for doing so is sufficiently weighty (i.e. is such that if it were true, it would justify infringement), (b) it knows that this reason is true (or at least that it is likely to be true, given the evidence), and (c) is based on an impartial examination and correct assessment of the extant evidence. Otherwise, the infringement will be unjust. Laws that will infringe on the rights of people on the basis of empirical considerations ought not be based on ideology, feelings, emotions, prejudices, etc. They ought to be based on a fair examination of the evidence. We would be entitled to criticize the government for basing a policy that infringes 242

Essays in Philosophy 16(2) on our rights on the basis of, say, one study that is inconsistent with the findings of all other studies on the relevant question. Given GVA, (b) and (c) are false, which implies that the consequent of the conditional claim is false. As we have seen, the extant evidence does not make it probable that any of the anti-gun hypotheses we have considered are true. If I am right about the evidence, then politicians who correctly impartially examine the evidence cannot justify their support for gun bans on the basis of that evidence. It follows that governments ought not infringe on the right of people to own guns. Gun bans are unjust in the light of these considerations. xvi REFERENCES Bernstein, C. et al. (2015a). The Moral Right to Keep and Bear Firearms. Public Affairs Quarterly, forthcoming. Bernstein, C. (2015b). Arguing About Guns. Practical Ethics. <http://blog.practicalethics.ox.ac.uk/2015/03/oxforduehiro-prize-in-practical-ethics-arguing-about-guns-byczar-bernstein/>. Dixon, N. (2011). Handguns, Philosophers, and the Right to Self-Defense. International Journal of Applied Philosophy, 25(2): 151-170. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/ijap201125215 Gius, M. (2014). An Examination of the Effects of Concealed Weapons Laws and Assault Weapons Bans on State-level Murder Rates. Applied Economics Letters 21(4): 265-267. 243

Gun Violence Agnosticism Bernstein Hahn, R. et al (2003). First Reports Evaluating the Effectiveness of Strategies for Preventing Violence: Early Childhood Home Visitation and Firearms Laws. Center for Disease Control. <http://www.cdc.gov/mmwr/pdf/rr/rr5214.pdf> Hemenway, D. and Miller, M. (2000). Firearm Availability and Homicide Rates Across 26 High-Income Countries. The Journal of Trauma, 49(6): 985-988. http://dx.doi.org/10.1097/00005373-200012000-00001 Huemer, M. (2003). Is There a Right to Own a Gun? Social Theory and Practice, 29(2): 297-324. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/soctheorpract200329215 Kates, D. and Mauser, G. (2007). Would banning firearms reduce murder and suicide? Harvard Review of Law and Public Policy, 30. Killias, M. (1993). Gun ownership, suicide, and homicide: an international perspective in Understanding Crime: Experiences of Crime and Crime Control, edited by Frate, A., Zvekic, U., and Dijk, J. (Rome: UNICRI). Killias, M., Kesteren, J., and Rindlisbacher, M. (2001). Guns, Violent Crime, and Suicide in 21 Countries. Canadian Journal of Criminology, 43(4): 438. Kleck, G. (2001). Armed. (New York: Prometheus Books). Kleck, G. (2015). The Impact of Gun Ownership Rates on Crime Rates: A Methodological Review of the Evidence. Journal of Criminal Justice, 43: 40-48. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.jcrimjus.2014.12.002 244

Essays in Philosophy 16(2) Kovandzic, T. et al. (2013). Estimating the Causal Effect of Gun Prevalence on Homicide Rates: A Local Average Treatment Effect Approach. Journal of Quantitative Criminology, 29(4): 477-541. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s10940-012-9185-7 Lott, J. and Mustard, D. (1997). Crime, deterrence, and the right-to-carry concealed handguns. The Journal of Legal Studies, 26:1-68. http://dx.doi.org/10.1086/467988 Lott, J. (2014a). Research shows crime goes down with concealed-carry. The Columbus Dispatch. <http://www.dispatch.com/content/stories/editorials/2014/0 5/03/1-research-shows-crime-goes-down-with-concealedcarry.html> (Accessed 03/31/15). Lott et al. (2014b). Concealed Carry Permit Holders Across the United States. Crime Prevention Research Center. <http://crimepreventionresearchcenter.org/wp- content/uploads/2014/07/concealed-carry-permit-holders- Across-the-United-States.pdf> (Accessed 25/10/14). Plassman, F. and Whitley, J. (2003). Confirming More Guns, Less Crime. Stanford Law Review, 55: 1313-1369. Wellford et al (2004). Firearms and Violence: A Critical Review. (Washington DC: National Academies Press). NOTES i In this paper, I deal only with crime as a potential reason for gun bans, but it is also possible to construct an argument from gun suicides for gun bans. For the purposes of this paper, I shall assume that all such arguments fail. 245

Gun Violence Agnosticism Bernstein ii There were 15 studies for which only one of (1) (3) are true; seven supported CIH and eight failed to support CIH. There were no studies for which only two of (1) (3) were true. iii Kates and Mauser (2007: 654) iv Wellford et al. (2004: 6). v Lott (2014b: 7). vi Ibid. vii For example, Lott and Mustard (1997), Plassman and Whitley (2003), and Gius (2014) all found in favour of the crime reduction hypothesis. viii See Lott (2014a). ix Lott (2014b: 8-9). x Ibid. xi See, for example, Huemer (2003). xii Bernstein et al. (2015a; forthcoming). xiii Most other tools require the victim to physically engage her attacker, which is problematic for victims who tend to be physically weaker than their attackers (e.g. women, the elderly, the disabled, etc.). xiv See Lott (2010: 3). xv See Bernstein (2015b). xvi Thanks to Tim Hsiao and an anonymous referee for helpful comments and suggestions. 246