Wittgenstein and the Creativity of Language edited by Grève & Mácha

Similar documents
THE CREATIVE LIFE AND WORK OF LUDWIG WITTGENSTEIN

Book Reviews 427. University of Manchester Oxford Rd., M13 9PL, UK. doi: /mind/fzl424

Ludwig Wittgenstein: Philosophical Investigations

Matters of Fact and Relations of Ideas

Philosophy Courses-1

Philosophy Courses-1

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Helpful Hints for doing Philosophy Papers (Spring 2000)

RECENT WORK THE MINIMAL DEFINITION AND METHODOLOGY OF COMPARATIVE PHILOSOPHY: A REPORT FROM A CONFERENCE STEPHEN C. ANGLE

Responses to Respondents RESPONSE #1 Why I Reject Exegetical Conservatism

Grade 7. correlated to the. Kentucky Middle School Core Content for Assessment, Reading and Writing Seventh Grade

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

BOOK REVIEW. Thomas R. Schreiner, Interpreting the Pauline Epistles (Grand Rapids: Baker Academic, 2nd edn, 2011). xv pp. Pbk. US$13.78.

SPRING 2014 UNDERGRADUATE COURSE OFFERINGS

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

Study Guide: Academic Writing

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp

Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge by Dorit Bar-On

Genre Guide for Argumentative Essays in Social Science

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox

ON WRITING PHILOSOPHICAL ESSAYS: SOME GUIDELINES Richard G. Graziano

Intro Viewed from a certain angle, philosophy is about what, if anything, we ought to believe.

Russell on Plurality

12 Bible Course Map--2013

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Spinoza, the No Shared Attribute thesis, and the

The New Wittgenstein, ed. Alice Crary and Rupert Read, London and New York, 2000, pp. v + 403, no price.

Reviewed by Colin Marshall, University of Washington

Prentice Hall United States History Survey Edition 2013

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

PHILOSOPHY EPISTEMOLOGY ESSAY TOPICS AND INSTRUCTIONS

Gilbert. Margaret. Scientists Are People Too: Comment on Andersen. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 6, no. 5 (2017):

Some questions about Adams conditionals

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Russell: On Denoting

Prentice Hall Literature: Timeless Voices, Timeless Themes, Silver Level '2002 Correlated to: Oregon Language Arts Content Standards (Grade 8)

Prentice Hall Literature: Timeless Voices, Timeless Themes, Bronze Level '2002 Correlated to: Oregon Language Arts Content Standards (Grade 7)

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

NOTE: Courses, rooms, times and instructors are subject to change; please see Timetable of Classes on HokieSpa for current information

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Pihlström, Sami Johannes.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Sentence Starters from They Say, I Say

To the first questions the answers may be obtained by employing the process of going and seeing, and catching and counting, respectively.

Kingdom, Covenants & Canon of the Old Testament

The Tractatus for Future Poets: Dialectic of the Ladder by B. Ware

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

Checking Your Arguments

This is a collection of fourteen previously unpublished papers on the fit

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary

Wittgenstein s The First Person and Two-Dimensional Semantics

"Can We Have a Word in Private?": Wittgenstein on the Impossibility of Private Languages

AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING

Introduction 5. What Must I Do to Be Saved? 9. Saved by Grace... Isn t That Too Good to Be True? 17

Is anything knowable on the basis of understanding alone?

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 5

The Representation of Logical Form: A Dilemma

Accessing the Moral Law through Feeling

Epistemology Naturalized

DESCARTES ONTOLOGICAL PROOF: AN INTERPRETATION AND DEFENSE

Prentice Hall U.S. History Modern America 2013

THE GREAT DEBATE ABOUT ENGLISH BIBLE VERSIONS: A CALL FOR REALISM AND CIVILITY

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information

GCE Religious Studies Unit B (RSS02) Religion and Ethics 2 June 2009 Examination Candidate Exemplar Work: Candidate A

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

Review: The Objects of Thought, by Tim Crane. Guy Longworth University of Warwick

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 100, No. 3. (Jul., 1991), pp

Death and Immortality (by D Z Phillips) Introductory Remarks

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Kevin MacNeil, Culver Academies

SOUTHEASTERN BAPTIST THEOLOGICAL SEMINARY HERMENEUTICS: AN EXAMINATION OF ITS AIMS AND SCOPE, WITH A PROVISIONAL DEFINITION

Chadwick Prize Winner: Christian Michel THE LIAR PARADOX OUTSIDE-IN

Bart Streumer, Unbelievable Errors, Oxford: Oxford University Press, ISBN

Ronald Dworkin, Religion without God, Harvard University Press, 2013, pp. 192, 16.50, ISBN

How Will I Be Graded in This Class?

Macmillan/McGraw-Hill SCIENCE: A CLOSER LOOK 2011, Grade 4 Correlated with Common Core State Standards, Grade 4

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Religion and Science: The Emerging Relationship Part II

Houghton Mifflin English 2001 Houghton Mifflin Company Grade Three Grade Five

Book Reviews. Reason Papers Vol. 40, no. 1

2004 by Dr. William D. Ramey InTheBeginning.org

South Carolina English Language Arts / Houghton Mifflin English Grade Three

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC

Christ-Centered Critical Thinking. Lesson 6: Evaluating Thinking

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

Skepticism, Naturalism, and Therapy

Transcription:

Book Reviews CC-BY Wittgenstein and the Creativity of Language edited by Grève & Mácha Daniel Sharp Grève, Sebastian Sunday and Mácha, Jakub (eds.), Wittgenstein and the Creativity of Language. London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2016, xxi + 318pp. Wittgenstein and the Creativity of Language brings together ten essays (plus an introduction by the editors) on a family of topics in Wittgenstein scholarship, loosely united by a joint concern with the creative aspects of language. The volume is divided into five sections. After an editorial introduction (I) and an overture in which Stephen Mulhall explores certain parallels between reading poetry and reading philosophy (II), there are three thematic sections one on the creativity of Wittgenstein s own writing process, one on the arts, and a final section on ethics, each consisting of three thematically similar essays. The volume s composition is notably Wittgensteinian in inspiration. The editors and, following their lead, the contributors opted not to treat the question what is creativity in language? by offering some general definition or theory of linguistic creativity. This is in part because they take creativity to be a family resemblance concept, and thus assume that there is no one feature that all instances of (linguistic) creativity share. Instead, the editors themselves express the hope that the essays in the volume might serve as instances and objects of comparison which, when read together, allow the distinctive richness of the concept of linguistic creativity to shine through (4; cf. Wittgenstein 2009, 130). 1 One result of the objects of comparison approach is a strikingly eclectic volume. Topics covered include: Wittgenstein s (creative) writing style and process, mathematics, philosophy of language, aesthetics, art, poetry, metaphysics, and ethics. Given this diversity, and the complexity of the various essays, 1 All citations from Grève and Mácha 2016, unless otherwise indicated. 226

Nordic Wittgenstein Review 5 (2) 2016 the most sensible evaluative approach is to explore whether the volume as a whole achieves its stated ambitions, rather than simply summarizing the contributions. 2 Do the essays, in fact, serve as useful objects of comparisons and do they, when read together, provide a perspicuous presentation of the complex phenomenon of linguistic creativity? The honest verdict is, I think, mixed. Several of the essays do work well together, illuminating overlapping issues from different angles. Other contributions, though, seem frankly out of place. It is worth illustrating both points, to give readers both a sense for the volume s flow and coherence as a whole, and a sense for the successes and pitfalls of the editorial approach. Let us take the positive first. One admirable achievement of the volume is its dispelling of the illusion that the later Wittgenstein s account of language is committed to some sort of linguistic conservatism. This charge is an old one it goes back at least to Ernest Gellner s Words and Things (1959) but has seldom been examined in light of more contemporary understandings of Wittgenstein s work. If valid, the allegation would indeed constitute a serious obstacle to understanding linguistic creativity from a Wittgensteinian perspective, so it 2 This exegetical work is, in any case, nicely provided by the editorial introduction. seems an appropriate place to begin such a volume. The accusation is presented in different ways throughout the volume, and the essays nicely build upon one another in their responses to it. On one version of the charge, Wittgenstein is taken to hold that utterances are meaningful because of (communally endorsed) rules that govern language use. This suggests a puzzle about how linguistic innovation is possible: if meaningful utterances must conform to pregiven rules, it seems that truly new forms of linguistic expression are, perhaps, impossible. Offhand, the accusation looks like a stretch. However, the editors (and Read, in his contribution) suggest plausibly, though perhaps not with maximal charity that many readings of Wittgenstein seem implicitly committed to the implication: not only those who endorse a communitarian interpretation of Wittgenstein s rule-following remarks 3, but equally those who see 3 One should be careful here: not all positions that could be classified as communitarian fall prey to the object. Take Bloor s meaning finitism, which holds that although community consensus helps fix meaning, terms have no fixed extension (1997). They are extended based on parallels with exemplars. Since the extension is always finite, new cases are only decided by the community s agreement that they fit this or that exemplar. But that decision, crucially, is always an open one. Accordingly, this version of communitarianism seems to allow ample room for an account of creative language. 227

Book Reviews CC-BY Wittgenstein as committed to a project of grammatical taxonomy. In response to Wittgenstein s alleged conservatism, the editors respond that (a) the rule following discussion is itself intended as an analogy (c.f. Wittgenstein 2009, 81), and (b) Wittgenstein s own creativity as a writer the literary devices (e.g., the metaphors, comparisons, and analogies) that he himself uses suggests that he could not have intended to endorse conservativism. This reply may help shake the confidence of those who take Wittgenstein to be a linguistic conservative. However, this response is only partially satisfactory since, as readers of the Tractatus know, Wittgenstein was not always necessarily averse to using language in ways that flaunt the implications of his own account. Different, more satisfying, responses are found in Rupert Read s and Garry Hagberg s contributions. Metaphysics is Metaphorics, Read s wide-ranging essay, argues that Hackerian approaches of mapping the grammar of language fail to recognize Wittgenstein s fundamentally dynamical vision of language (285). Language is not a fixed unity but, as Wittgenstein emphasized, more like an ancient city: a maze of little streets and squares, of old and new houses, and of houses with additions from various periods (Wittgenstein 2009, 18). What counts as a mistake at one time may, down the road, become part of established use; while all of grammar cannot be, in toto suspended, particular bits of grammar can be recast (286). Building on and expanding this insight, Hagberg s essay, Verbal Creativity and the Expansion of Artistic Style, aims to counter approaches to both language and art that aim to police the borders of sense. By this suggestive turn of phrase, Hagberg means the activity of, in the case of language, producing a sort of map or taxonomy of speech acts such that one can determine a priori whether a statement does or does not make sense, or, in the case of art, producing a taxonomy of artistic forms such that one can determine according to some general rule whether something is or is not art. Both views rely on an impoverished understanding of rule following, envisioning rules as being, necessarily and in all cases, fixed, exact and predictable (158). Rather, Hagberg thinks, communication opens an interpretive space between the giver and the follower of the rule (159) where the rule s implications can be negotiated in a context in which the criteria are often vague. Then, drawing on the work of art historian Kirk Varnedoe, Hagberg shows how artistic style develops by disregarding certain artistic conventions. He emphasizes how modern artists played with areal perspective, flaunting the dominance of vanishing point perspective, in order to produce new and innovative ways of seeing. 228

Nordic Wittgenstein Review 5 (2) 2016 Out of this discussion, then, we get a persuasive response to the thought that Wittgenstein s views imply linguistic conservativism. Moreover, this constitutes a sort of ground-clearing for a potentially fruitful understanding of linguistic creativity. Danièle Moyal-Sharrock adds some further substance to this picture in her essay Wittgenstein: No Linguistic Idealist. In the first part of her essay, Moyal-Sharrock rebuts the charge that the later Wittgenstein s views leave us (as Bernard Williams once suggested) trapped in a kind of linguistic idealism: spinning in our webs of significance, detached from external reality. In the second and here more relevant part, Moyal-Sharrock outlines an understanding of linguistic creativity which draws on Merleau-Ponty s distinction between constituted and constitutive language. Constituted language is everyday conventional language, which contains a reserve of already sedimented meanings; it makes communication with one another possible. In contrast, constitutive language is literary language (in the broadest sense of the term), which brings meanings into existence. It is through this dialectical movement between constitutive language and expressive acts which imperceptibly reconfigure language that new meanings become possible. If there is an overall picture of linguistic creativity we get from the volume, then, it is this: one cannot create ex nihilo. Something some background of established use must be already given in order for artistic creation to unfold; indeed, creativity unfolds precisely through a complex interaction with what is already there. The general insight here is an important one, and it forms the core of the volume. (The point holds even in the limiting case of linguistic creativity that of literally creating a new language; it is no surprise that L. L. Zamenhof, the inventor of Esperanto, already spoke several languages). However, not all of the essays in the volume work so well together. Some seem like outliers, which have little bearing on the volume s other contributions or relevance to the idea of linguistic creativity. This is most obvious in three cases: Ben Ware s Finding it New: Aspect-Perception and Modern Ethics, John Hyman s The Urn and the Chamber Pot and Sebastian Grève s and Wolfgang Kienzler s Wittgenstein of Gödelian Incompleteness, Proofs and Mathematical Practice. I will focus only on the last two cases. John Hyman s contribution focuses on Austrian architect Alfred Loos s influence on Wittgenstein. The essay introduces Loos, chronicles the building of the Wittgenstein House, and then concludes with some general remarks about the similarities between Loos and the early Wittgenstein. In this last respect, the essay concludes both men shared a set of aesthetic values (austerity and practicality), and sought to separate the inessential (the ornament, in Loos s terms) from 229

Book Reviews CC-BY the essential (the logical structure, in Wittgenstein s terms). The parallel is carefully crafted and undoubtedly interesting. Yet, although the essay deals with the aesthetic values involved in Wittgenstein s philosophy, and Wittgenstein s own creative involvement in architecture, the specifically linguistic dimension of creativity receives little attention. It thus remains unclear what the piece contributes the volume s topic. Similar problems befall Kienzler and Grève's contribution. Their essay offers an original close reading of Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics I, Appendix III. The central claim of the chapter is that Wittgenstein's focus in these remarks is not Gödel's proof or its correctness. Rather, Wittgenstein aims to question what role Gödelian explanations (87) of what the proof aims to show. Specifically, the chapter argues, Wittgenstein aims to question the role that a certain kind of sentence of the form "there exists a sentence P, which is true but unprovable" (83) could play in mathematics. Leaving aside the question Wittgenstein is correct in his skepticism about the function of Gödelian explanations, Kienzler and Grève reconstruct the argument of the text with great care and present the relevant passages with remarkable clarity. Yet, as was the case above, it is hard to see how the chapter fits with the larger purpose of the volume. The justification offered is that a close reading of the remarks reveals that Wittgenstein crafted them in a "rigorous and systematic" manner (78). Surely, this is correct. But the demonstration of the remarks tight-knitted (78) internal structure itself constitutes neither a contribution to understanding linguistic creativity nor to understanding Wittgenstein's own creative process. In fairness, Wittgenstien s own creative process is not left unexplored by the volume. An essay that does make a significant contribution to understanding Wittgenstein s creative process is Alois Pichler s Ludwig Wittgenstein and Us Typical Western Scientists. Pichler argues that there is a close connection between the form of Wittgenstein s writing and his conception of philosophy. Wittgenstein s later work exhibits a writing strategy of syncrestic or criss-cross writing 4, which positions itself in a field of questions that is in continuous flux and openended (69), rather than closed and predetermined. Pichler then contrasts this kind of writing with two alternative writing strategies puzzle writing and linear writing which Pichler argues reflect a scientistic conception of philosophy, rejected by Wittgenstein. Pichler s essay helps, as much as any piece on the topic, to make perspicuous why Wittgenstein s later philosophy exhibits the peculiar 4 Pichler borrows the terms writing strategy, as well as syncretistic, puzzle and linear writing from Austrian linguist Hanspeter Ortner. He also challenges Ortner s own view that the Investigations is best characterized as puzzle writing. 230

Nordic Wittgenstein Review 5 (2) 2016 compositional form that it does; that is, why Wittgenstein s Philosophical Investigations is really only an album (Wittgenstein 2009, Preface). In short, at times, the book seems to lack the sort of unity around the theme of linguistic creativity that one desires in an edited volume of this kind. The volume could have also benefited from a deeper engagement with the wide variety of philosophical and psychological theories of creativity on offer. 5 While these theories might uniformly fail to capture the whole of creativity, many certainly capture central parts. A more sustained, critical conversation with such accounts would perhaps have served as useful foils to the Wittgensteinian approach, or at least may have highlighted what sets it apart. 6 Perhaps this will not trouble some readers. Those interested, generally, in all aspects of Wittgenstein s philosophy as well as readers with particular interest in the intersections of philosophy and the arts, I suspect, will tend to find the volume more satisfying than readers with more a narrow interest in the volume s titular theme. Of course, one must add, unity is not the only measure of a successful volume. Many of the essays are of high quality, and the volume explores a theme the creative aspects of 5 Read s piece is here an exception, as it deals with Chomsky s theory of linguistic creativity. 6 See for example: Bardsley, Dutton & Krausz 2009. language that is underexplored in Wittgenstein scholarship. For these achievements, editors should be commended. 7 References New York University, NY, USA des361 @ nyu.edu Bloor, D., 1997. Wittgenstein, Rules, and Institutions. London: Routledge. Bardsley, K., Dutton, D., & Krausz, M. (eds.) 2009. The Idea of Creativity. Leiden: Brill. Wittgenstein, L. 2009. Philosophical Investigations / Philosophische Untersuchungen. Edited by P.M.S. Hacker and Joachim Schulte, transl. G.E.M. Anscombe, P.M.S. Hacker and Joachim Schulte. New York: Wiley. 7 I would like to thank Katharina Sodoma for helpful discussion and insightful comments. 231