Wolfgang Spohn Fachbereich Philosophie Universität Konstanz D Konstanz

Similar documents
Putnam: Meaning and Reference

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Alternative Conceptual Schemes and a Non-Kantian Scheme-Content Dualism

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

Objections to the two-dimensionalism of The Conscious Mind

Dumitrescu Bogdan Andrei - The incompatibility of analytic statements with Quine s universal revisability

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Varieties of Apriority

A PRIORI PRINCIPLES OF REASON

Contextual two-dimensionalism

Subjective Logic: Logic as Rational Belief Dynamics. Richard Johns Department of Philosophy, UBC

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

TWO-DIMENSIONAL TRUTH

Reply to Robert Koons

WHY WATER IS NOT AN INDEXICAL

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Nature and its Classification

Constructing the World, Lecture 4 Revisability and Conceptual Change: Carnap vs. Quine David Chalmers

Constructing the World

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Aboutness and Justification

This is a longer version of the review that appeared in Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 47 (1997)

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

This is a collection of fourteen previously unpublished papers on the fit

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

Kevin Scharp, Replacing Truth, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013, At 300-some pages, with narrow margins and small print, the work

Philosophical Logic. LECTURE TWO MICHAELMAS 2017 Dr Maarten Steenhagen

Grounding and Analyticity. David Chalmers

A Priori Principles of Reason

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7c The World

Lecture 1 The Concept of Inductive Probability

Coordination Problems

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

Contextualism and the Epistemological Enterprise

Gary Ebbs, Carnap, Quine, and Putnam on Methods of Inquiry, Cambridge. University Press, 2017, 278pp., $99.99 (hbk), ISBN

INTERPRETATION AND FIRST-PERSON AUTHORITY: DAVIDSON ON SELF-KNOWLEDGE. David Beisecker University of Nevada, Las Vegas

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

An Empiricist Theory of Knowledge Bruce Aune

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Philosophy of Logic and Language (108) Comprehensive Reading List Robert L. Frazier 24/10/2009

What is an Argument? Validity vs. Soundess of Arguments

sentences in which they occur, thus giving us singular propositions that contain the object

Against the Contingent A Priori

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

Necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pp. i-ix, 379. ISBN $35.00.

Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010).

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

APRIORITY AND MEANING: A CASE OF THE EPISTEMIC TWO-DIMENSIONAL SEMANTICS

Skepticism and Internalism

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Perceiving Abstract Objects

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

Fundamentals of Metaphysics

Phil/Ling 375: Meaning and Mind [Handout #10]

What is Formal in Husserl s Logical Investigations?

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Constructing the World

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Ambitious Two-Dimensionalism

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Lecture 4. Before beginning the present lecture, I should give the solution to the homework problem

Carnap versus Quine, or Aprioristic versus Naturalized Epistemology, or a Lesson from Dispositions

Philip D. Miller Denison University I

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

On Quine, Grice and Strawson, and the Analytic-Synthetic Distinction. by Christian Green

Classical Theory of Concepts

Analyticity and reference determiners

Australasian Journal of Philosophy

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

xiv Truth Without Objectivity

A Posteriori Necessities by Saul Kripke (excerpted from Naming and Necessity, 1980)

Anti-Metaphysicalism, Necessity, and Temporal Ontology 1

Names Introduced with the Help of Unsatisfied Sortal Predicates: Reply to Aranyosi

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers

REVIEW THE DOOR TO SELLARS

1 Why should you care about metametaphysics?

ON CONSIDERING A POSSIBLE WORLD AS ACTUAL. by Robert Stalnaker and Thomas Baldwin. II Thomas Baldwin

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

On Certainty * Wolfgang Spohn

Behavior and Other Minds: A Response to Functionalists

The Inscrutability of Reference and the Scrutability of Truth

[JGRChJ 9 (2013) R28-R32] BOOK REVIEW

Conceptual Analysis meets Two Dogmas of Empiricism David Chalmers (RSSS, ANU) Handout for Australasian Association of Philosophy, July 4, 2006

Reductive Materialism (Physicalism) Identity Theory. UT Place & DM Armstrong on is statements

Twentieth-Century Analytic Philosophy by Avrum Stroll

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first.

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Under contract with Oxford University Press Karen Bennett Cornell University

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

Tuomas E. Tahko (University of Helsinki)

Knowledge of Manifest Natural Kinds

Chapter Six. Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality

Transcription:

CHANGING CONCEPTS * Wolfgang Spohn Fachbereich Philosophie Universität Konstanz D 78457 Konstanz At the beginning of his paper (2004), Nenad Miscevic said that empirical concepts have not received the epistemological treatment they deserve. When first reading this complaint I was surprised. Are the huge philosophical efforts to come to terms with concepts not primarily directed to empirical concepts? Miscevic insists, however, that concepts evolve, that we learn concepts and change concepts, and that this is most obvious in the case of empirical concepts like our concept of whales or our concept of water. I realized then that Miscevic has raised a most important question: How can a concept change? Why is this question important? It is almost standard that a concept is, or may be represented as, an intension, i.e., as a function mapping possibilities to appropriate extensions. Disagreement starts when it comes to say what the possibilities are, which specific function a concept is, etc. It may also be that a concept rather is a two-dimensional entity, i.e., a function mapping two possibilities, possibly of different kinds, to extensions. This standard is widely agreed, and it is important to note that the standard is enforced by the fact that we want concepts to somehow build up propositions and that we want to somehow understand propositions as truth conditions. However, the simple consequence is: different functions, different concepts. We can say that yesterday we had this concept and now we have that, but the standard conception does not allow us to say that yesterday s concept changed into today s. This consequence looks unacceptable. Miscevic is right to point out that the problem is particularly important for an inquiry into the relation between concepts and apriority. If concepts may change, then, presumably, conceptual truths, i.e., truths in virtue of these concepts, may * Originally, this paper was a comment to Miscevic (2004); both papers were presented at the DFG conference Concepts and the A Priori held at the University of Konstanz at June 17-19, 2004. Small revisions were required to make it self-contained. Moreover, I added references and a few additional remarks. So, it can now be read as a relevant appendix to chapter 14 of his volume. I am very grateful to Nenad Miscevic for the illuminating exchange about the topic.

2 change as well. But this badly fits to the guiding idea that concepts are the source of apriority. If conceptual truths change under the influence of experience, they are rather a posteriori and not a priori, as Miscevic (2004) has elaborated. The issue indeed threatens the presuppositions of the dominant approach to apriority. So, how may we conceive of changing concepts? What the standard conception describes is presumably only states or stages of a concept. The question then is what holds the various stages of a concept together so as to form one concept persisting through its possible changes? 1 Let me discuss five different answers: The first answer is that it is simply the word used at various times to express the various stages of a concept. There is a lot of truth in this answer. Still, it is definitely unsatisfactory, for three reasons. First, we should leave room for nonlinguistic concepts not expressed by words. Secondly, it is not so clear what a word is. One may think that a word is identified by its morphophonological shape. But this shape may change, too. So, we would need an account of words as persisting through their morphophonological changes. We may expect, though, that linguistics provide such an account. Thirdly, however, there is the objection, decisive in my view, that no morphophonological individuation of words will do. One and the same word shape may stand for different concepts, by being used ambiguously, by being used in different languages, or by changing to an entirely different meaning. 2 This is a familiar point. If words are to individuate concepts, they have to be semantically interpreted words, and since their semantic interpretation roughly consists in the concepts, we have first to individuate concepts in order to individuate words in this semantic sense. Hence, the first answer is unhelpful. 1 In the German context the question raises quite different associations. There was and still is a very influential movement focussing on so-called Begriffsgeschichte that provided the methodological foundations for the journal Archiv für Begriffsgeschichte founded by Erich Rothacker in 1955 and for the well-known encyclopedia Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie initiated by Joachim Ritter, a renowned student of Rothacker, in the 60 s. Begriffsgeschichte may modestly mean the history of the usage of a philosophical word or term. The projects were, however, more ambitious; the idea rather was to present the history of the concepts themselves (within which concepts were certainly never conceived as functions from something into extensions). If Schröder (2000) is correct, the repeated criticism that it does not make sense to speak of a history of concepts beyond that of terms was never convincingly rebutted by that movement. That is, 50 years of German post-war philosophy did not really get beyond the first and the second deficient answer I am about to discuss. Not that I would help here concerning philosophical concepts. I am happy to talk about ordinary empirical concepts; philosophical concepts clearly are the most difficult ones for the semanticist. 2 See the most illuminating discussion of Kaplan (1990/91) whom the question how words are individuated leads to quite similar considerations than the ones presented here.

3 A second answer is that the continuity of a concept lies in the continuity of its possessor. The answer is still incomplete; we would still have to say what makes for the continuity of a concept within the possessor. Anyhow, the proposal won t do. Whether concept-possessors are persons or entire linguistic communities, a concept does not live and die with its possessor. Moreover, if the possessor is somehow essential to a concept, it becomes difficult to explain how a concept can be shared by different possessors. There is a possibly useful notion of cultural identity according to which a cultural community is constituted by its shared concepts. Accordingly, we still form a cultural community with the ancient Greeks and Romans (to some extent at least). In this sense, it is indeed trivial that a concept is continuous with the community possessing it. However, the present proposal obviously becomes circular by this move. A third idea proceeds from the observation that concepts have aims; concepts aim, we might say, at their subject matter. So, perhaps, the various stages of a concept are united by their common aim. To speak less metaphorically: What a concept is about, aims at, or attempts to grasp, is its actual extension or reference or rather, speaking two-dimensionally, its actual secondary or C-intension. And a concept may change while its reference remains fixed. Our notion of gold, e.g., has changed several times; still, it is always our notion of gold that always refers to the same stuff. When Putnam (1975) calls upon us: Let s be realistic!, he refers exactly to this point, as Miscevic (2004) has again emphasized. 3 I think this idea is on the right track; but it still won t do. Clearly, we, individuals as well as communities, may have two different concepts for the same subject matter, as long as we don t notice it; this is the familiar story about Hesperos and Phosphorus before the Babylonian discovery of their identity. Conversely, a concept may remain the same while changing its reference, as long as we don t notice it. This is the jade story. Originally, the reference of the Chinese jade concept was Chinese jade. Yet, after the massive import of substantially different, but phenomenologically indistinguishable Burmean jade into China the reference changed to Chinese or Burmean jade without, I contend, any change in the concept. 3 To be sure, Putnam (1975) is reluctant to speak of concepts. But he pleads that the intension at least of natural kind terms is rigid, i.e., the projection of their actual extension to other possible worlds, and that this intension remains constant throughout possible changes of our grasp of that extension.

4 For both of these exceptions the qualification as long as we don t notice it was essential. So it seems it is not the actual aim or reference of a concept that counts, since we might be in error about the actual aim in some way or other. What counts, this is the fourth proposal I want to make, is rather the believed reference or the intended aim of the concept. 4 This fits well to the conception of concepts in Haas-Spohn, Spohn (2001). We have argued there that my concept of an object or a property is what I believe this object or property to be. Since what an object or property is is determined by its essence, the collection of its essential or metaphysically necessary properties, this means that my concept of an object or property consists in my belief about its essential properties. And we have argued that this conception does not only fit to our concepts of natural kinds, on which Miscevic has focussed, but also to our concepts of objects and other properties. The only modification I have to add in view of the present considerations is that what we then called concepts are rather concept stages in the present sense. Given this conception of concepts or rather concept stages, there is no fundamental mystery in conceptual change. Beliefs about essences may change just as any other beliefs, and thus, in principle, all the well-elaborated accounts of belief change apply to conceptual change as well. The details and the particular role of beliefs about essences within our overall net of inductively connected beliefs would certainly need most careful considerations. Still, the framework is well prepared by Spohn (1988) and subsequent papers. The crucial point, of course, is that I have much more beliefs about an object or property than about its essence, and the former may change without the latter. Thus, not every belief change is a conceptual change. To avoid this badly holistic consequence was indeed our main goal in Haas-Spohn, Spohn (2001). What is it, then, that unites all these concept stages to one concept? It is my belief that they are all about the same subject matter. If I first believe that, necessarily, whales are fishes, and then believe that, necessarily, whales are mammals and thus change my concept of whales, I still take these beliefs to be about the same subject matter, namely about those animals, and hence as expressing various stages of the same concept. This is how the fourth proposal to individuate con- 4 Kaplan (1990/91) arrives at the corresponding conclusion concerning the identity of words through their history of usage.

5 cepts and the specific conception of concept stages Haas-Spohn, Spohn (2001) fit together. How, then, should we relate analyticity and apriority to concepts thus conceived? Miscevic (2004) proposes to apply analyticity to concept stages, and thus the above assertions about whales become analytic relative to the relevant concept stages; i.e., whales are mammals is analytic relative to our present whale concept. Miscevic is right in calling this assertion a posteriori and thus arrives at paradoxical conclusions. I doubt that this is a wise terminological choice; I think we better relate analyticity to concepts and not to concept stages. At the end of this note, I shall touch upon the issue how much analyticity then remains. Miscevic also distinguishes weak or superficial apriority related to concept stages and strong or deep apriority related to concepts, and he goes on to argue that all alleged conceptual apriority turns out to be only weak, thus suggesting that there is no strong apriority related to empirical concepts. I disagree; there are, I believe, also strongly a priori sentences. At least two kinds come to my mind: The one kind is given by sentences of the form: Whales are called whales, or rather whales are called whales in my language. In a way, this is simply disquotation, but there is more to it. It brings out the a priori connection between a linguistically expressible concept and the word expressing it. This is the truth behind the first answer discussed above. We cannot identify a concept via an antecedently identified word; still, the one is a priori accompanied by the other. More importantly, this a priori sentence brings out that semantic deference is built into a concept right from the start. Whales are called whales not only by me, but by my teachers and by my linguistic community as well, and thus the power of determining what whales are is automatically deferred to my community. The other kind of strongly a priori sentences has the form: Most of what we take to be whales are whales. This has a Davidsonian ring. But it is not as general as asserting that most of our beliefs about whales are true; the a priori assumption is the more restricted one that most of our reference-fixing beliefs concerning whales are true. Moreover, the assumption does not ground in a theory of interpretation according to which a person can only be rationalized by the principle of charity as having mostly true beliefs. The point is rather that this assumption is the only base on which to change and develop our concept at hand; only

6 when its believed reference is largely maintained, we may claim to have changed our old concept rather than to have acquired a new concept. 5 Note, by the way, that the apriority of most of what we take to be whales are whales entails the apriority of there are whales. Quine (1969, p. 86) revolted against the analyticity of there are dogs ; he then took the indistinguishability of information that goes into understanding a sentence and information that goes beyond as a further reason for abolishing analyticity. Apart from Quine s continuous refusal to distinguish analyticity and apriority, I think he is wrong. There are dogs is strongly a priori in Miscevic sense. This is not quite to say that it is unrevisably a priori. But it is to say that we must believe that there are dogs as long as we have the concept of a dog; if we lose the belief (due to very strange circumstances), we lose the concept as well. So, to resume, I contend, opposing Miscevic (2004), that there are some strongly a priori beliefs associated with a changing empirical concept. Indeed, I want to suggest that these beliefs are presupposed by the concept; otherwise, we could not meaningfully speak of that concept as a possibly changing one. Hence, these a priori beliefs embody my fifth and last idea for what it is that persists in, and thus individuates, changing concepts. A final brief remark: We have seen that Miscevic relates analyticity to concept stages and thus arrives at paradoxical consequences. My observations suggest the question whether there are also strongly analytic sentences related to a concept. Only trivial ones, it seems, like whales are whales, etc. In particular, if we follow Kripke in defining an analytic sentence as being a priori necessary, the above strongly a priori sentences associated with a concept turn out to be synthetic, since they are only contingently true. They are basically analogous to the sentence I presently exist which is the paradigm of an a priori, but contingently true sentence. Thus, we may perhaps vindicate old suspicions of Quine, Putnam, and others about the poverty of the notion of analyticity despite the richness of the notion of apriority. 5 This a priori sentence applies to each moment of time. This allows for the peculiar case where this sentence is true at all times, though the many gradual changes may accumulate so that we end up with applying a concept to objects most or all of which did initially not fall under the concept. I am not quite sure whether we should really say in such a case that we have the same concept throughout. This is, however, a general and well-known ontological puzzle.

7 References Haas-Spohn, Ulrike, and Wolfgang Spohn (2001), Concepts Are Beliefs About Essences, in: A. Newen, U. Nortmann, and R. Stuhlmann-Laeisz (eds.), Building on Frege. New Essays on Sense, Content, and Concept, Stanford: CSLI Publications, pp. 287-316. Kaplan, David (1990/91), Words, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 64, 93-119. Miscevic, Nenad (2004), Empirical Concepts and A Priori Truth, Conference Paper 2004. Putnam, Hilary (1975), The Meaning of Meaning, in: H. Putnam, Philosophical Papers, Vol. II: Mind, Language and Reality, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 215-271. Quine, Willard V.O. (1969), Epistemology Naturalized, in: W.V.O. Quine, Ontological Relativity and Other Essays, New York: Columbia University Press, pp. 69-90. Schröder, Winfried (2000), Was heißt Geschichte eines philosophischen Begriffs?, Archiv für Begriffsgeschichte, Sonderheft 42, pp. 159-172. Spohn, Wolfgang (1988), Ordinal Conditional Functions. A Dynamic Theory of Epistemic States, in: W. L. Harper and B. Skyrms (eds.), Causation in Decision, Belief Change, and Statistics, Dordrecht: Kluwer, pp. 105-134.