QUESTION 11. Enjoying as an Act of the Will

Similar documents
QUESTION 87. How Our Intellect Has Cognition of Itself and of What Exists Within It

QUESTION 34. The Goodness and Badness of Pleasures

QUESTION 10. The Modality with Which the Will is Moved

QUESTION 26. Love. Article 1. Does love exist in the concupiscible power?

QUESTION 67. The Duration of the Virtues after this Life

QUESTION 59. An Angel s Will

QUESTION 55. The Medium of Angelic Cognition

QUESTION 28. The Divine Relations

QUESTION 55. The Essence of a Virtue

Henry of Ghent on Divine Illumination

QUESTION 36. The Causes of Sadness or Pain. Article 1. Is it a lost good that is a cause of pain rather than a conjoined evil?

QUESTION 54. An Angel s Cognition

QUESTION 8. The Objects of the Will

QUESTION 58. The Mode of an Angel s Cognition

QUESTION 34. The Person of the Son: The Name Word

QUESTION 3. God s Simplicity

QUESTION 90. The Initial Production of Man with respect to His Soul

QUESTION 18. The Subject of Hope

QUESTION 19. God s Will

QUESTION 44. The Procession of Creatures from God, and the First Cause of All Beings

QUESTION 53. The Corruption and Diminution of Habits. Article 1. Can a habit be corrupted?

QUESTION 86. What Our Intellect Has Cognition of in Material Things

QUESTION 27. The Principal Act of Charity, i.e., the Act of Loving

PROLOGUE TO PART 1-2

QUESTION 30. Mercy. Article 1. Is something bad properly speaking the motive for mercy?

QUESTION 44. The Precepts that Pertain to Charity

QUESTION 28. Joy. Article 1. Is joy an effect of charity within us?

QUESTION 59. The Relation of the Moral Virtues to the Passions

QUESTION 45. The Mode of the Emanation of Things from the First Principle

QUESTION 107. The Speech of Angels

QUESTION 65. The Work of Creating Corporeal Creatures

The Names of God. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 12-13) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006)

QUESTION 42. The Equality and Likeness of the Divine Persons in Comparison to One Another

QUESTION 63. The Cause of Virtue

QUESTION 66. The Order of Creation with respect to Division

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination

The Divine Nature. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 3-11) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian J.

QUESTION 40. Hope and Despair

QUESTION 83. The Subject of Original Sin

QUESTION 65. The Connectedness of the Virtues

QUESTION 64. The Punishment of the Demons

QUESTION 45. Daring. Article 1. Is daring contrary to fear?

Peter L.P. Simpson December, 2012

QUESTION 39. The Persons in Comparison to the Essence

QUESTION 47. The Diversity among Things in General

QUESTION 111. The Divisions of Grace

QUESTION 66. The Equality of the Virtues

QUESTION 76. The Union of the Soul with the Body

QUESTION 57. The Distinctions Among the Intellectual Virtues

Thomas Aquinas. Summa Theologiae la Translated, with Introduction and Commentary, by. Robert Pasnau

QUESTION 84. How the Conjoined Soul Understands Corporeal Things That are Below Itself

QUESTION 95. Things Relevant to the First Man's Will, viz., Grace and Justice

QUESTION 69. The Beatitudes

QUESTION 116. Fate. Article 1. Is there such a thing as fate?

QUESTION 39. The Goodness and Badness of Sadness or Pain

QUESTION 45. The Gift of Wisdom

The Five Ways. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Question 2) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006) Question 2. Does God Exist?

QUESTION 94. The Natural Law

QUESTION 4. The Virtue Itself of Faith

QUESTION 92. The Production of the Woman

QUESTION 56. An Angel s Cognition of Immaterial Things

Of the Nature of the Human Mind

On Truth Thomas Aquinas

1 Concerning distinction 39 I ask first whether God immutably foreknows future

Thomas Aquinas The Treatise on the Divine Nature

Aquinas on Law Summa Theologiae Questions 90 and 91

Thomas Aquinas The Treatise on the Divine Nature

The question is concerning truth and it is inquired first what truth is. Now

FREEDOM OF CHOICE. Freedom of Choice, p. 2

QUESTION 22. God s Providence

REFLECTIONS ON THE RELATION BETWEEN PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY GERALD VAN ACKEREN, S.J.

QUESTION 24. The Subject of Charity

QUESTION 20. The Goodness and Badness of the Exterior Act

QUESTION 23. Predestination

QUESTION 88. Mortal Sin and Venial Sin

Peter L.P. Simpson December, 2012

The Five Ways of St. Thomas in proving the existence of

WHAT ARISTOTLE TAUGHT

Thomas Aquinas on the World s Duration. Summa Theologiae Ia Q46: The Beginning of the Duration of Created Things

Faith and Reason Thomas Aquinas

QUESTION 36. Envy. Article 1. Is envy a type of sadness?

Thomas Aquinas. Summa Theologiae la Translated, with Introduction and Commentary, by. Robert Pasnau

QUESTION 55. The Vices opposed to Prudence that are Similar to it

270 Now that we have settled these issues, we should answer the first question [n.

Moral Obligation. by Charles G. Finney

Thomas Aquinas. Summa Theologiae la Translated, with Introduction and Commentary, by. Robert Pasnau

NICHOLAS OF CUSA: METAPHYSICAL SPECULATIONS. Six Latin Texts Translated into English by JASPER HOPKINS THE ARTHUR J. BANNING PRESS MINNEAPOLIS

QUESTION 97. The Conservation of the Individual in the First State

QUESTION 113. The Guardianship of the Good Angels

Questions on Book III of the De anima 1

St. Thomas Aquinas Excerpt from Summa Theologica

THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781)

Necessary and Contingent Truths [c. 1686)

Meditations on First Philosophy: Meditation II By: René Descartes

On the Soul. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 75-76) by Thomas Aquinas (~1274 AD) translated by Robert Pasnau (2014)

- 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance

Selections of the Nicomachean Ethics for GGL Unit: Learning to Live Well Taken from classic.mit.edu archive. Translated by W.D. Ross I.

QUESTION 58. Justice

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

Search WJE Online The Jonathan Edwards Center at Yale University

Transcription:

QUESTION 11 Enjoying as an Act of the Will Next, we have to consider the act of enjoying (fruitio). On this topic there are four questions: (1) Is enjoying an act of an appetitive power? (2) Does the act of enjoying belong only to rational creatures, or does it belong to brute animals as well? (3) Is the act of enjoying directed only toward the ultimate end? (4) Is the act of enjoying directed only toward an end that is possessed? Article 1 Does the act of enjoying belong only to an appetitive power? It seems that act of enjoying (frui) does not belong only to an appetitive power: Objection 1: To enjoy seems to be nothing other than to partake of the fruit (fructum capere). But as was shown above (q. 3, a. 4), the fruit of human life, i.e., beatitude, is partaken of by the intellect, an act of which beatitude consists in. Therefore, the act of enjoying belongs to the intellect and not to an appetitive power. Objection 2: Every power has its proper end, viz., its own perfection; for instance, the end of the visual power is to have cognition of the visible, and the end of the auditory power is to perceive sounds, and so on for the others. But a thing s end is its fruit. Therefore, the act of enjoying belongs to every power and not just to an appetitive power. Objection 3: The act of enjoying implies a certain delight (delectatio). But sentient delight belongs to the senses, which take delight in their object; and, for the same reason, intellectual delight belongs to the intellect. Therefore, the act of enjoying belongs to an apprehensive power and not to an appetitive power. But contrary to this: In De Doctrina Christiana 1 and in De Trinitate 10 Augustine says, To enjoy is to adhere to a thing with love for its own sake. But love involves an appetitive power. Therefore, enjoying is likewise an act of an appetitive power. I respond: The act of enjoying (fruitio) and the fruit (fructus) have to do, it seems, with the same thing, and the one is derived from the other. For our present purposes, it makes no difference which is derived from which except that it seems likely that the one that is more manifest was also the one that was named first. Now what is manifest to us in the first place are things that are more able to be sensed. Hence, the name fruitio seems to have been derived from sensible fruits (a sensibilibus fructibus). But a sensible fruit is the ultimate thing that one looks forward to from a tree, and it is perceived with a certain gratification (quadam suavitate). Hence, the act of enjoying (fruitio) has to do, it seems, with someone s love for, or delight in, the ultimate thing that he looks forward to, viz., the end. But the end or the good is the object of an appetitive power. Hence, it is clear that the act of enjoying is an act of an appetitive power. Reply to objection 1: Nothing prevents one and the same thing, thought of in different ways (secundum diversas rationes), from belonging to different powers. Thus, the very vision of God, insofar as it is a vision, is an act of the intellect. But insofar as it is a good and an end, it is an object of the will, and it is in this respect that there is enjoyment of it. And so the intellect attains to this end as an active power (tamquam potentia agens), whereas the will pursues it as a power that (a) effects movement toward the end and that (b) enjoys the end once it is attained. Reply to objection 2: As was explained above (q. 9, a. 1), the perfection and end of every other power is included in the end of the appetitive power, in the way that what is particular (proprium) is included in what is general (commune). Hence, insofar as the perfection and end of any power is a certain good, it pertains to the appetitive power. This is why the appetitive power moves the other powers to their own ends, and the appetitive power itself attains to its end when all the other powers

Part 1-2, Question 11 85 reach their end. Reply to objection 3: There are two elements in delight, viz., (a) the perception of what is fitting, which belongs to an apprehensive power, and (b) being pleased with that which is proposed as fitting (complacentia eius quod offerter ut conveniens). The latter belongs to an appetitive power, in which the nature of delight is brought to completion. Article 2 Does the act of enjoying belong only to men? It seems that the act of enjoying belongs only to men: Objection 1: In De Doctrina Christiana 1 Augustine says, It is we men who enjoy and use. Therefore, it is not the case that other animals are capable of the act of enjoying. Objection 2: The act of enjoying is directed toward the ultimate end. But brute animals are unable to reach the ultimate end. Therefore, the act of enjoying does not belong to them. Objection 3: A natural appetite is subordinate to a sentient appetite in the same way that a sentient appetite is subordinate to an intellective appetite. Therefore, if the act of enjoying belongs to a sentient appetite, then it seems, by parity of reasoning, that it can belong to a natural appetite. But this is clearly false, since the act of delight does not belong to a natural appetite. But contrary to this: In 83 Quaestiones Augustine says, It is not absurd to think that even beasts enjoy food and bodily pleasure. I respond: As is established by what has already been said (a. 1), the act of enjoying is not the act of a power that reaches the end in the sense of executing it (sicut exequentis), but is instead the act of a power that commands this execution (imperantis executionem); for it has been explained that the power in question is an appetitive power. Now in things that lack cognition there is a power that arrives at the end by way of executing it, e.g., the power by which something heavy tends downward, and the power by which something lightweight tends upward. But the power that reaches the end in the sense of commanding it (potentia ad quam pertineat finis per modum imperantis) is found not in these things themselves, but instead in a higher nature that by its command moves their whole nature in the way that, in things with cognition, the appetite moves the other powers to their acts. Hence, it is clear that in the case of things that lack cognition, even though they might attain their end, there is no act of enjoying the end; instead, the act of enjoying is found only in things that have cognition. However, there are two sorts of cognition of the end, perfect and imperfect. Perfect cognition is that by which there is a cognition not only of that which is the end and the good, but of the universal notion of the end and the good; this sort of cognition belongs only to a rational nature. By contrast, imperfect cognition is that by which there is a particularized cognition of the end and the good (qua cognoscitur particulariter finis et bonum); and this is the sort of cognition that exists in brute animals. In addition, the appetitive powers (virtutes appetitivae) in brute animals are not powers that command freely, but are instead powers that are moved by natural instinct toward the things that are apprehended. Hence, a rational nature has the act of enjoying in the perfect sense (secundum rationem perfectam), whereas brute animals have it in an imperfect sense, and other creatures do not have it in any way at all. Reply to objection 1: Augustine is talking here about a perfect act of enjoying. Reply to objection 2: The act of enjoying need not be directed toward the ultimate end absolutely speaking, but is instead directed toward what each thing has as its ultimate end (eius quod habetur ab unoquoque pro ultimo fine).

Part 1-2, Question 11 86 Reply to objection 3: Sentient appetite follows upon some sort of cognition, but natural appetite does not, especially as it exists in things that lack cognition. Reply to the argument for the contrary: Augustine is here talking about an act of enjoying in the imperfect sense (de fruitione imperfecta). This is clear from his manner of speaking. For he says, It is not all that absurd (non adeo absurde) to think that even beasts enjoy... in the way that it would be altogether absurd (absurdissime) to say that they have the act of using (cf. q. 16, a. 2 below). Article 3 Is the act of enjoying directed only toward the ultimate end? It seems that the act of enjoying is not directed only toward the ultimate end: Objection 1: In Philemon, verse 20, the Apostle says, Brother, I so enjoy you in the Lord. But it is manifest that Paul had not placed his ultimate end in a man. Therefore, the act of enjoying is not directed only toward the ultimate end. Objection 2: A fruit (fructus) is what someone enjoys. But in Galatians 5:22 the Apostle says, The fruits of the Spirit are love, joy, peace, etc. which do not have the character of an ultimate end. Therefore, it is not the case that the act of enjoying is directed only toward the ultimate end. Objection 3: Acts of will are self-reflective; for example, I will that I will, and I love that I love. But to enjoy is an act of the will, since, as Augustine puts it in De Trinitate 10, It is the will through which we enjoy. Therefore, someone enjoys his own act of enjoying. But it is not an act of enjoying that is man s ultimate end; instead, it is an uncreated good alone, viz., God. Therefore, the act of enjoying is not directed only toward the ultimate end. But contrary to this: In De Trinitate 10 Augustine says, There is no act of enjoying if it is for the sake of something else that one desires what he takes into the faculty of the will. But it is the ultimate end alone which is not desired for the sake of something else. Therefore, it is the ultimate end alone that the act of enjoying is directed toward. I respond: As has been explained (a. 1), two things are relevant to the notion of a fruit, viz., (a) that it be something ultimate and (b) that it put the appetite to rest with a certain sweetness or delight (quadam dulcedine vel delectatione). Now something is ultimate either absolutely speaking or relatively speaking. A thing is ultimate absolutely speaking when it is not referred to anything further (ad aliud non refertur), whereas a thing is ultimate relatively speaking when it is the last with respect to certain things (ultimum aliquorum). Thus, what is ultimate absolutely speaking is such that someone takes delight in it as in an ultimate end; and this is what is properly called a fruit and what someone is properly said to enjoy. By contrast, what is not delightful in itself, but is desired only in relation to something else, e.g., a bitter drink for the sake of health, can in no way be called a fruit. On the other hand, what has a certain delight in itself and is such that certain preceding things are referred to it can in some sense be called a fruit even if not properly speaking or in accord with the perfect notion of a fruit (secundum completam rationem fructus) and we are said to enjoy it. Hence, in De Trinitate 10 Augustine says, We enjoy things which we have cognition of and in which the delighted will finds rest. To be sure, the will does not rest in anything absolutely speaking except the ultimate end, since as long as there is still something to look forward to, the will s movement remains uncertain (in suspenso), even if it has already arrived at something. It is like a case of local motion: Even though a point in the middle of a magnitude is a beginning and an end, it is nonetheless not taken as an actual end except when the thing comes to rest in it. Reply to objection 1: As Augustine says in De Doctrina Christiana 1, If he had said I enjoy

Part 1-2, Question 11 87 you and had not added in the Lord, then he would have seemed to place the end of love in him. But because he added that phrase, he signified that he was placing his end in the Lord and that it was Him whom he was enjoying. So he was saying that he enjoyed his brother not as a terminus, but as an intermediate. Reply to objection 2: A fruit is related in one way to the tree that produces it and in another way to the man who enjoys it. It is related to the tree that produces it as an effect to a cause, whereas it is related to the man who enjoys it in the way that the ultimate thing looked forward to is related to the one who delights in it. Therefore, the things that the Apostle enumerates in this passage are called fruits because they are certain effects of the Holy Spirit in us; hence, they are called the fruits of the Spirit, but not in such a way that we enjoy them as the ultimate end. An alternative reply is that, according to Ambrose, they are called fruits because they are sought for their own sake not, to be sure, in the sense that they are not referred to beatitude, but in the sense that they possess in themselves something that should please us. Reply to objection 3: As was explained above (q. 1, a. 8 and q. 2, a. 7), there are two senses of end, viz., (a) the thing itself and (b) our attainment of it. These are not two ends, but rather a single end that is (a) thought of in itself and (b) applied to something else. Therefore, God is the ultimate end in the sense of the thing that is ultimately sought, whereas the act of enjoying is like the attainment of this ultimate end. Therefore, just as God is not an end different from the enjoyment of God, so it is the same notion of enjoyment by which we enjoy God and by which we enjoy our enjoying God. And the same line of reasoning applies to created beatitude, which consists in the act of enjoying. Article 4 Is the act of enjoying directed only toward an end that is possessed? It seems that the act of enjoying is directed only toward an end that is possessed (non sit nisi finis habiti): Objection 1: In De Trinitate 10 Augustine says, To enjoy is to make use of with joy (frui est cum gaudio uti) no longer with the joy of hope, but now with the joy of the thing itself. But as long as the thing is not possessed, there is the joy of hope and not the joy of the thing itself. Therefore, the act of enjoying is directed only toward an end that is possessed. Objection 2: As has been explained (a. 3), the act of enjoying is directed, properly speaking, only toward the ultimate end, since the ultimate end alone brings the appetite to rest. But the appetite is brought to rest only in an end that is already possessed. Therefore, the act of enjoying is directed, properly speaking, only toward an end that is possessed. Objection 3: To enjoy is to partake of the fruit (fructum capere). But the fruit is partaken of only when the end is already possessed. Therefore, the act of enjoying is directed only toward an end that is possessed. But contrary to this: As Augustine says, To enjoy is to adhere to a thing with love for its own sake. But this can be done even with respect to an end that is not possessed. Therefore, the act of enjoying can be directed even toward an end that is not possessed. I respond: To enjoy implies a certain relation of the will to an ultimate end insofar as the will has something as its ultimate end. Now there are two ways in which an end is possessed: (a) perfectly and (b) imperfectly. The end is perfectly possessed when it is had not only in one s thought (in intentione) but also in reality (in re), whereas it is imperfectly possessed when it is had only in one s thought.

Part 1-2, Question 11 88 Therefore, there is a perfect act of enjoying an end which is already possessed in reality. But there is also an imperfect act of enjoying an end which is possessed only in thought and not in reality. Reply to objection 1: Augustine is talking about a perfect act of enjoying. Reply to objection 2: There are two ways in which the will s rest is impeded: (a) on the part of the object, viz., because it is not the ultimate end but is ordered toward something else; and (b) on the part of the one who desires the end but who has not yet attained to the end. Now the object is what gives an act its species, whereas the manner of acting depends on the agent, with the result that the act is perfect or imperfect depending on the agent s condition. And so when the end in question is not the ultimate end, the act of enjoying is improper in the sense of falling short of the species enjoyment. And when the ultimate end is not possessed, then there is a proper act of enjoying but an imperfect one, because of the imperfect mode of possessing the ultimate end. Reply to objection 3: As has been explained, someone is said to receive or possess an end not only in reality but also in thought.