Intro. First-Order Necessity and Validity. First Order Attention. First Order Attention

Similar documents
Tautological Necessity and Tautological Validity With Quantifiers

Announcements The Logic of Quantifiers Logical Truth & Consequence in Full Fol. Outline. Overview The Big Picture. William Starr

1 Clarion Logic Notes Chapter 4

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

The way we convince people is generally to refer to sufficiently many things that they already know are correct.

Transition to Quantified Predicate Logic

Mr Vibrating: Yes I did. Man: You didn t Mr Vibrating: I did! Man: You didn t! Mr Vibrating: I m telling you I did! Man: You did not!!

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

Introducing truth tables. Hello, I m Marianne Talbot and this is the first video in the series supplementing the Formal Logic podcasts.

Critical Thinking. The Four Big Steps. First example. I. Recognizing Arguments. The Nature of Basics

Homework: read in the book pgs and do "You Try It" (to use Submit); Read for lecture. C. Anthony Anderson

Chapter 6, Tutorial 1 Predicate Logic Introduction

9.1 Intro to Predicate Logic Practice with symbolizations. Today s Lecture 3/30/10

Introduction Symbolic Logic

UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016

2. Refutations can be stronger or weaker.

C. Exam #1 comments on difficult spots; if you have questions about this, please let me know. D. Discussion of extra credit opportunities

Part II: How to Evaluate Deductive Arguments

Philosophy 220. Truth Functional Properties Expressed in terms of Consistency

A. Problem set #3 it has been posted and is due Tuesday, 15 November

13.6 Euler Diagrams and Syllogistic Arguments

Am I free? Freedom vs. Fate

An Introduction to. Formal Logic. Second edition. Peter Smith, February 27, 2019

HANDBOOK. IV. Argument Construction Determine the Ultimate Conclusion Construct the Chain of Reasoning Communicate the Argument 13

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

PHI Introduction Lecture 4. An Overview of the Two Branches of Logic

Complications for Categorical Syllogisms. PHIL 121: Methods of Reasoning February 27, 2013 Instructor:Karin Howe Binghamton University

The SAT Essay: An Argument-Centered Strategy

Facts and Free Logic. R. M. Sainsbury

Facts and Free Logic R. M. Sainsbury

16. Universal derivation

C. Problem set #1 due today, now, on the desk. B. More of an art than a science the key things are: 4.

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014

EXERCISES: (from

Outline. 1 Review. 2 Formal Rules for. 3 Using Subproofs. 4 Proof Strategies. 5 Conclusion. 1 To prove that P is false, show that a contradiction

The cosmological argument (continued)

Kripke on the distinctness of the mind from the body

A Romp through the Foothills of Logic: Session 1

Revisiting the Socrates Example

15. Russell on definite descriptions

Part 2 Module 4: Categorical Syllogisms

A Short Course in Logic Example 3

Elements of Science (cont.); Conditional Statements. Phil 12: Logic and Decision Making Fall 2010 UC San Diego 9/29/2010

Instructor s Manual 1

Can logical consequence be deflated?

A short introduction to formal logic

Venn Diagrams and Categorical Syllogisms. Unit 5

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction

CHAPTER 9 DIAGRAMMING DEBATES. What You ll Learn in this Chapter

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

How to Write a Philosophy Paper

A romp through the foothills of logic Session 3

Logic Book Part 1! by Skylar Ruloff!

SOME RADICAL CONSEQUENCES OF GEACH'S LOGICAL THEORIES

Introducing Our New Faculty

Artificial Intelligence Prof. Deepak Khemani Department of Computer Science and Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Overview of Today s Lecture

Philosophy 57 Day 10

1/19/2011. Concept. Analysis

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

2.3. Failed proofs and counterexamples

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

INTERMEDIATE LOGIC Glossary of key terms

SYLLOGISTIC LOGIC CATEGORICAL PROPOSITIONS

Pastor-teacher Don Hargrove Faith Bible Church September 8, 2011

Russell on Denoting. G. J. Mattey. Fall, 2005 / Philosophy 156. The concept any finite number is not odd, nor is it even.

CHAPTER 10 VENN DIAGRAMS

Williams on Supervaluationism and Logical Revisionism

Philosophy 57 Day 10. Chapter 4: Categorical Statements Conversion, Obversion & Contraposition II

What would count as Ibn Sīnā (11th century Persia) having first order logic?

PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE OVERVIEW LOGICAL CONSTANTS WEEK 5: MODEL-THEORETIC CONSEQUENCE JONNY MCINTOSH

Content Area Variations of Academic Language

Haberdashers Aske s Boys School

Quantificational logic and empty names

Ontological Argument page 2

OBJECTIVITY WITHOUT THE PHILOSOPHER S SPECIAL OBJECTS: A PRIORIAN PROGRAM. James Van Cleve, University of Southern California

FIRST PUBLIC EXAMINATION. Preliminary Examination in Philosophy, Politics and Economics INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY TRINITY TERM 2013

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility

Logic: The Science that Evaluates Arguments

Prior, Berkeley, and the Barcan Formula. James Levine Trinity College, Dublin

MCQ IN TRADITIONAL LOGIC. 1. Logic is the science of A) Thought. B) Beauty. C) Mind. D) Goodness

PHILOSOPHY 102 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC PRACTICE EXAM 1. W# Section (10 or 11) 4. T F The statements that compose a disjunction are called conjuncts.

Exposition of Symbolic Logic with Kalish-Montague derivations

Artificial Intelligence Prof. P. Dasgupta Department of Computer Science & Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Kharagpur

Basic Concepts and Skills!

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC FOR METAPHYSICIANS

Paul acknowledges that what s strange about this treasure especially for these status-loving Corinthians is that it comes in clay jars.

What we want to know is: why might one adopt this fatalistic attitude in response to reflection on the existence of truths about the future?

Module 5. Knowledge Representation and Logic (Propositional Logic) Version 2 CSE IIT, Kharagpur

Logic & Proofs. Chapter 3 Content. Sentential Logic Semantics. Contents: Studying this chapter will enable you to:

Day 3. Wednesday May 23, Learn the basic building blocks of proofs (specifically, direct proofs)

A Judgmental Formulation of Modal Logic

Deduction by Daniel Bonevac. Chapter 1 Basic Concepts of Logic

MATH1061/MATH7861 Discrete Mathematics Semester 2, Lecture 5 Valid and Invalid Arguments. Learning Goals

Constructing the World

The antecendent always a expresses a sufficient condition for the consequent

10.3 Universal and Existential Quantifiers

(Refer Slide Time 03:00)

Workbook Unit 17: Negated Categorical Propositions

Transcription:

Intro Mark Criley IWU 10/23/2015 We have added some new pieces to our language: Quantifiers and variables. These new pieces are going to add a new layer of NPEC: Necessity, Possibility, Equivalence, Consequence. This is going to be called First-Order necessity, possibility, etc. That s FO necessity, possibility, etc., for short. The book refers to FO-necessities as FO validities. Ugh. I avoid that, just because I want to reserve the term validity for arguments rather than sentences. First Order Attention First Order Attention FO-NPEC, etc. pays attention to a little bit more than TT-NPEC does. It pays attention to the meanings of the connectives, just like TT-necessity. But it also pays attention to the meanings of the quantifiers and variables. Unlike the truth table. And it pays attention to one special predicate: Identity (=). Unlike the truth table. But FO-necessity pays attention to a little bit less than Logical necessity does. FO-necessity doesn t pay attention to the meaning of any predicates other than =. So FO-necessity doesn t understand the meaning of Cube, BackOf, Between, Small, etc.

Euler Diagrammin Remember that necessity (and equivalence and consequence) will expand when we add new things to force sentences to be true or false. Because all of the connectives are still around to do the forcing when we move from TT to FO, All TT-necessities are FO-necessary. But because FO has some more stuff around to do forcing than TT did, Not all FO-necessities are TT-necessary. Not all FO-necessities are TT-necessary. For that to be true, there must be at least one example of a sentence that is FO-necessary but not TT-necessary. Can you think of an example of an FO-necessity that isn t TT-necessary? Euler Diagrammin Remember this sentence from last class? Exercise 10.1.1: x (x=x) We saw that this wasn t TT-necessary. (Why not?) But we saw that it was logically necessary. (Why?) Is it FO-necessary? Yes, x (x=x) is FO-necessary. (Why?) It doesn t contain anything that Logical necessity pays attention to but that FO necessity doesn t. (It doesn t have any predicates other than =.)

Euler Diagrammin What is the relationship between logical necessity and first order necessity? Since logical necessity pays attention to all of the same stuff that forces sentences to be true at the FO level (connectives, quantifiers, variables, names, identity), All FO-necessities are logically necessary. Euler Diagram So here s the Euler Diagram for Necessity (and Consequence and Equivalence) But since there is some stuff that logical necessity pays attention to stuff that the FO level doesn t (namely, the meaning of predicates like Cube, Large, etc. ) Not all logical necessities are FO-necessary. Hint Not all logical necessities are FO-necessary. If that is true, then there must be some logical necessity that is not FO-necessary. Can you think of an example of a logical necessity that is not FO-necessary? Examples will have to exploit the meanings of some predicates that FO-necessity doesn t pay attention to.

Logically Necessary, but Not FO-Necessary Here s an example: x (Cube(x) Dodec(x)) That sentence is logically necessary. (Why?) But it isn t FO-necessary. (Why not?) But not just any example that uses a predicate that FO-necessity doesn t understand will do the trick. For instance, FO-necessity doesn t pay any attention to the meaning of Cube. But the following sentence is FO-necessary: x ((Cube(x) Small(x)) Cube(x)) You don t have to know anything about what Cube means to know that that sentence is true. Same with this one: x Cube(x) x Cube(x) Strategy! We just have to make sure that we replace the same sensible predicate with the same nonsense predicate everywhere it appears. In order to get ourselves to think in a First Order frame of mind, we re going to need a strategy to get ourselves to ignore the meanings of the predicates that FO thinking can t understand. Strategy: We ll just replace all of the predicates FO thinking can t understand with nonsense predicates, ones that we can t understand. If we replace Cube with Caburble in one place, we have to replace it with that everywhere. And we can t reuse the same nonsense predicate for a different sensible predicate. If we have already declared that Caburble means Cube, we can t turn around and say it also means Large.

What s A Schwenky Caburble? Apply this technique to the FO-necessary sentences from before: x ((Cube(x) Small(x)) Cube(x)) Replace the sensible predicate Cube with Caburble. And replace the sensible predicate Small with the nonsense predicate Schwenky. Now the earlier sentence becomes x ((Caburble(x) Schwenky(x)) Caburble(x)) x ((Caburble(x) Schwenky(x)) Caburble(x)) What do Caburble and Schwenky mean? I have no idea! I don t know! I don t want to know! But even so, without knowing anything about schwenky stuff or caburbles, I still know this: That has to be true, right? All schwenky caburbles are caburbles. If you can determine that a sentence must be true even after replacing its sensible with nonsense ones, then the sentence is FO-necessary. If you can t determine whether a sentence must be true after you have replaced its sensible predicates with nonsense ones, then the sentence is not FO-necessary.

Another example Now let s apply this technique to another sentence we encountered earlier: x Cube(x) x Cube(x) This becomes: x Caburble(x) x Caburble(x) What s a caburble? I still have no idea! But I do know this: If something caburbles, then not everything fails to caburble. That s just got to be true, no matter what caburble means. So the original sentence is FO-necessary. Now, what about this sentence: x (Cube(x) Dodec(x)) Can No Curdiddles Doodiddle? x (Cube(x) Dodec(x)) Replace its sensible predicates with nonsense ones. (I m getting tired of Caburbles, though.) x (Curdiddle(x) Doodiddle(x)) Does that have to be true? x (Curdiddle(x) Doodiddle(x)) Does that have to be true? Is it necessary? I have no idea. It depends on what Curdiddle and Doodiddle mean. That means that the necessity of x (Cube(x) Dodec(x)) depends on the meanings of its predicates. And that means that it is not FO-necessary.

FO-Validity We have just used the technique to see whether a sentence was FO-necessary. We can use the same technique to determine whether an argument is FO-valid or not. Consider the following argument: Is this argument FO-Valid? x SameSize(x,b) x Small(x) x Small(x) x SameSize(x,b) x SameSize(x,b) x Small(x) x Small(x) x SameSize(x,b) Do the nonsense replacement, making sure to replace the same sensible predicate everywhere with the same nonsense predicate. x Scebbies(x,b) x Slolly(x) x Slolly(x) x Scebbies(x,b) Can we determine whether this argument is valid? x Scebbies(x,b) x Slolly(x) x Slolly(x) x Scebbies(x,b) If we can determine whether this argument is valid, then the original sensible argument is FO-valid. (Its validity doesn t depend on the meanings of its predicates.) If we can t, then the original sensible argument is not FO-valid. (It might be logically valid, or TW-valid.) What do you think? x Scebbies(x,b) x Slolly(x) x Slolly(x) x Scebbies(x,b) If everything scebbies Bill, then there is at least one slolly. Nothing is a slolly. At least one thing doesn t scebby Bill.

If everything scebbies Bill, then there is at least one slolly. Nothing is a slolly. At least one thing doesn t scebby Bill. I have no idea who Bill is, or what a slolly is, or what it is for one thing to scebby another. But I can still tell that if the premises are true, the conclusion must be, too. What about this argument? x (Cube(x) Large(x)) x (Cube(x) Small(x)) So the original argument is FO-Valid. x (Cube(x) Large(x)) x (Cube(x) Small(x)) This argument is definitely logically valid. If we weren t sure whether this argument was FO-valid, we could use the nonsense predicate replacement method to check. And what would we find out? The argument is not FO-valid, even though it is logically valid. And in order to show this, we can do something a little bit stronger than the nonsense predicate replacement method. We can construct a FO-counterexample.

FO-Counterexamples Stop The Nonsense! FO-Counterexamples To make a FO-counterexample, we will have to make the premises true and the conclusion false. So to make one, we re going to stop using nonsense predicates, which give us sentences we cannot evaluate as true or false. To make an FO-counterexample, we replace the sensible predicates with other sensible predicates, where the pattern of replacement makes the premises true and the conclusion false. As before, each unique predicate always gets replaced by the same predicate, and we never reuse a predicate we have already substituted in for another, different predicate. x (Cube(x) Large(x)) x (Cube(x) Small(x)) Replace Cube with Chandelier, is Large with is a Light, and is Small with is Silver. You don t have to use words that begin with the same first letter. The key is to make your substitutions consistently (always replacing the same word with the new one). Starting with the same letter just makes it easier to make sure you re doing that. x (Chandelier(x) Light(x)) x (Chandelier(x) Silver(x)) These arguments have the same First order form. So if the first one is FO-valid, the second one would have to be FO-valid, too. x (Chandelier(x) Light(x)) x (Chandelier(x) Silver(x)) All chandeliers are lights. (TRUE) No chandeliers are silver. (FALSE) This counterexample shows that the original argument is definitely not FO-valid: there are counterexamples to this FO-Form. The validity of the original argument depends on more than just the meanings of the connectives, identity, and the quantifiers. Its validity depends upon facts about the large and small.