Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of

Similar documents
Logic: inductive. Draft: April 29, Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of premises P1,

INDUCTIVE KNOWLEDGE. (For Routledge Companion to Epistemology) Alexander Bird

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction

Scientific Method and Research Ethics Questions, Answers, and Evidence. Dr. C. D. McCoy

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

On The Logical Status of Dialectic (*) -Historical Development of the Argument in Japan- Shigeo Nagai Naoki Takato

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Reductio ad Absurdum, Modulation, and Logical Forms. Miguel López-Astorga 1

UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice

Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

WHAT IS HUME S FORK? Certainty does not exist in science.

Informalizing Formal Logic

Critical Thinking 5.7 Validity in inductive, conductive, and abductive arguments

Philosophy 12 Study Guide #4 Ch. 2, Sections IV.iii VI

Evidential Support and Instrumental Rationality

6AANA026 Philosophy of Science Syllabus Academic year 2015/16

Detachment, Probability, and Maximum Likelihood

THE ROLE OF COHERENCE OF EVIDENCE IN THE NON- DYNAMIC MODEL OF CONFIRMATION TOMOJI SHOGENJI

The New Paradigm and Mental Models

Deduction by Daniel Bonevac. Chapter 1 Basic Concepts of Logic

POLLOCK ON PROBABILITY IN EPISTEMOLOGY. 1. Some Remarks on Pollock s Critique of Bayesian Epistemology

2nd International Workshop on Argument for Agreement and Assurance (AAA 2015), Kanagawa Japan, November 2015

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

PHILOSOPHIES OF SCIENTIFIC TESTING

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome

A Solution to the Gettier Problem Keota Fields. the three traditional conditions for knowledge, have been discussed extensively in the

7AAN2075 Philosophy of Science Syllabus Academic year 2016/17

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

NB: Presentations will be assigned on the second week. Suggested essay topics will be distributed in May.

Bayesian Probability

Action in Special Contexts

Dispelling the Disjunction Objection to Explanatory Inference Kevin McCain and Ted Poston

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

General Philosophy. Stephen Wright. Office: XVI.3, Jesus College. Michaelmas Overview 2. 2 Course Website 2. 3 Readings 2. 4 Study Questions 3

5 A Modal Version of the

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility

On the Equivalence of Goodman s and Hempel s Paradoxes. by Kenneth Boyce DRAFT

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

McDowell and the New Evil Genius

Logic & Proofs. Chapter 3 Content. Sentential Logic Semantics. Contents: Studying this chapter will enable you to:

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

Epistemic Utility and Theory-Choice in Science: Comments on Hempel

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

HOW TO ANALYZE AN ARGUMENT

A Priori Bootstrapping

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER IX CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE

Bayesian Probability

Illustrating Deduction. A Didactic Sequence for Secondary School

Carnap s Non-Cognitivism as an Alternative to Both Value- Absolutism and Value-Relativism

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

ROBUSTNESS AND THE NEW RIDDLE REVIVED. Adina L. Roskies

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

Is Epistemic Probability Pascalian?

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Realism and instrumentalism

* I am indebted to Jay Atlas and Robert Schwartz for their helpful criticisms

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

Logic Appendix: More detailed instruction in deductive logic

Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio

PHI2391: Logical Empiricism I 8.0

Christ-Centered Critical Thinking. Lesson 6: Evaluating Thinking

PHIL 155: The Scientific Method, Part 1: Naïve Inductivism. January 14, 2013

How Gödelian Ontological Arguments Fail

Van Inwagen's modal argument for incompatibilism

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

The Theory/Experiment Interface of the Observation of Black Holes

Lecture 1 The Concept of Inductive Probability

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

5.6.1 Formal validity in categorical deductive arguments

Situations in Which Disjunctive Syllogism Can Lead from True Premises to a False Conclusion

Evidential arguments from evil

BENEDIKT PAUL GÖCKE. Ruhr-Universität Bochum

Evidence and Normativity: Reply to Leite

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

INTRODUCTION: EPISTEMIC COHERENTISM

WEEK 1: WHAT IS KNOWLEDGE?

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Inductive Inference, Rationality and Pragmatism: Peirce and Ajdukiewicz

Sydenham College of Commerce & Economics. * Dr. Sunil S. Shete. * Associate Professor

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII

Chapter 9- Sentential Proofs

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

THE PROBLEM OF INDUCTION: AN EPISTEMOLOGICAL AND METHODOLOGICAL RESPONSE. Alan Robert Rhoda. BA, University of Nevada, Las Vegas, 1993

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

HIGH CONFIRMATION AND INDUCTIVE VALIDITY

ISSA Proceedings 1998 Wilson On Circular Arguments

The Problem of Induction

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS

Business Research: Principles and Processes MGMT6791 Workshop 1A: The Nature of Research & Scientific Method

THE NORMATIVITY OF ARGUMENTATION AS A JUSTIFICATORY AND AS A PERSUASIVE DEVICE

Analogy and Pursuitworthiness

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

Transcription:

Logic: Inductive Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of premises and a conclusion. The quality of an argument depends on at least two factors: the truth of the premises, and the strength with which the premises confirm the conclusion. The truth of the premises is a contingent factor that depends on the state of the world. The strength with which the premises confirm the conclusion is supposed to be independent of the state of the world. Logic is only concerned with this second, logical factor of the quality of arguments. Deductive logic classifies arguments into two kinds: those where the truth of the premises guarantees the truth of the conclusion, and those where they do not. The former are called deductively valid, and the premises are said to logically imply the conclusion. The latter arguments are called deductively invalid. So the deductive-logical explication of the logical factor of the quality of an argument is the qualitative yes-or-no concept of deductive validity. Inductive logic aims at a more lenient explication of the logical factor of the quality of an argument. It comprises deductive validity as a special case. The reason is that the conclusions we are normally interested in are too informative to be logically implied by premises we can know. For instance, no set of premises about the past and present logically implies a conclusion about the future. Inductive logic usually aims at a quantitative explication of the logical factor of the quality of an argument, viz. the degree to which the premises confirm the conclusion. Hempel (1945) made one of the earliest attempts to develop a formal logic of qualitative confirmation. His goal of constructing a purely syntactical definition of confirmation is shared by Carnap (1962), who goes beyond Hempel by aiming at a quantitative concept of degree of confirmation. Carnap bases his inductive logic on the theory

of probability (Kolmogorov 1956). Due to Goodman s (1983) new riddle of induction there is consensus nowadays that a purely syntactical definition of (degree of) confirmation cannot be adequate. However, the use of probability theory has been a central feature of inductive logic ever since. A probability measure is a real-valued function on a language or field of propositions that is (i) non-negative, (ii) normalized, and (iii) additive. So every proposition receives a non-negative probability; the tautological proposition receives probability 1; and the probability of the union or disjunction of two disjoint or incompatible propositions is the sum of the probabilities of the two propositions. The conditional probability of one proposition given another proposition is defined as the ratio of the probability of the intersection or conjunction of the two propositions divided by the probability of the second proposition. Obviously this makes only sense if the second proposition receives positive probability. In inductive logic conditional probability is usually put to use in the following way (Carnap 1962, Hawthorne 2005, Skyrms 2000). The degree of absolute confirmation of a conclusion by a set of premises relative to a probability measure on a field of propositions is defined as the conditional probability of the conclusion given the (conjunction of the) premises. For more see Huber (2006). It is important to note that this definition renders degree of confirmation relative to a probability measure on a language or field of propositions that include the premises and the conclusion. The difference between the Carnapian approach (Carnap 1962) and more modern approaches (Hawthorne 2005, Skyrms 2000) now can be put as follows. Carnap sought to come up with one single logical probability measure, whereas modern writers consider (almost) any probability measure as admissible from a purely logical point of view. The notion of deductive validity is a three-place relation between a set of premises, a conclusion, and a language that includes the premises and the conclusion. By trying to define a unique logical probability measure for each language, Carnap in effect tried to define degree

of confirmation in a similar fashion as a three-place relation between a set of premises, a conclusion, and a language. Modern theories of confirmation differ in this respect, because they construe confirmation as a four-place relation, thus making explicit the probability measure. Fitelson (2005) still considers this to be a logical relation. Carnap (1962) also proposed a definition of qualitative confirmation, where the idea is that premises confirm a conclusion if they raise the probability of the conclusion. A conclusion is incrementally confirmed by a set of premises relative to a probability measure on a field of propositions if and only if the conditional probability of the conclusion given the premises is higher than the unconditional probability of the conclusion. As indicated by the qualifiers absolute and incremental, we have here two different concepts of confirmation. The quantitative concept of absolute confirmation is explicated by the conditional probability of the conclusion given the premises. Absolute confirmation thus consists in high conditional probability, and the qualitative concept of absolute confirmation is to be defined as follows. A conclusion is absolutely confirmed by a set of premises relative to a probability measure on a field of propositions if and only if its degree of absolute confirmation is sufficiently high. Incremental confirmation, on the other hand, focuses on increase in probability. Therefore the quantitative concept of incremental confirmation is to be defined as the degree to which the premises increase the probability of the conclusion, i.e. the difference between the unconditional probability of the conclusion and the conditional probability of the conclusion given the premises. As noted by Fitelson (1999), there are many non-equivalent ways to measure degree of incremental confirmation. Earman (1992) discusses the distance measure, which subtracts the unconditional probability of the conclusion from its conditional probability given the premises. Joyce (1999) and Christensen (1999) propose a measure which subtracts the conditional probability of the conclusion given the negation of the premises from its conditional probability given the premises.

In a different context, Carnap & Bar-Hillel (1952) propose to measure the informativeness of a conclusion by the probability of its negation. Hempel & Oppenheim (1948) suggest measuring the extent to which the conclusion informs us about the premises by the conditional probability of the negation of the conclusion given the negation of the premises. This is relevant since it turns out that the above mentioned measures of incremental confirmation are aggregates of the degree of absolute confirmation and the informativeness in the respective senses. More precisely, incremental confirmation is proportional to expected informativeness. Different measures of incremental confirmation differ in the way they measure informativeness. We have thus detected a third factor of the quality of an argument: the informativeness of the conclusion. This is not surprising. After all, the informativeness of the conclusion was the very reason why we were considering more lenient standards than deductive validity in the first place. Note also that the informativeness of the conclusion is as much a logical factor as is the degree to which the premises confirm the conclusion. For both factors are determined once the premises, the conlusion, and the probability measure on the field of propositions are specified. In fact, this opens the door to render all factors of the quality of an argument to be logical; for we can now also consider the probability that the premises are true. So far we have been engaged in conceptual analysis, where we appeal to intuitions as the data against which to test various proposals for a definition of confirmation. The assumption is, of course, that the concept we are explicating is important. Surely it is a good thing for a hypothesis to be confirmed by the available data. Surely we should strive to list premises that confirm the conclusion we are arguing for. Inductive logic is important, because it is a normative theory. Yet conceptual analysis does not provide the resources to justify a normative theory. Appeals to intuitions do not show why we should prefer well confirmed hypotheses to other hypotheses, and why we should provide inductively strong rather than any other arguments.

The analogy to deductive logic again proves helpful. The rules of deductive logic are norms that tell us how we should argue deductively. As any other set of norms, it needs to be justified. Contrary to Goodman (1983), the rules of deductive logic are not justified, because they adequately describe our deductive practices. They do not. The rules of deductive logic are justified relative to the goal of arguing truth preservingly, i.e. in such a way that the truth of the premises guarantees the truth of the conclusion. The results that provide the justification are known as soundness and completeness. Soundness says that every argument we obtain from the rules of deductive logic is such that truth is preserved when we go from the premises to the conclusion. Completeness states the converse. Every argument that has this property of truth preservation can be obtained from the rules of deductive logic. So the rules of deductive logic are justified relative to the goal of truth preservation. The reason is that they further this goal insofar as all and only deductively valid arguments are truth preserving. What is the goal inductive logic is supposed to further relative to which it can be justified? Surely it includes truth. However, as Hume (1739) argues, it is impossible to justify induction relative to the goal of truth. His argument assumes that justifying induction means providing a deductively valid or an inductively strong argument with knowable premises for the conclusion that induction will always lead to true conclusions. As noted by Reichenbach (1938), there are deductively valid arguments for other conclusions that may show that induction furthers the goal of truth to the extent this is possible. Similar results obtain for absolute confirmation, where it can be shown that the conditional probability of a conclusion given the premises converges to its truth value when more and more premises are learned. However, if obtaining true conclusions were the only goal induction is supposed to further, induction could be replaced by deduction. All that is logically implied by what we know is guaranteed to be true. We do not need to go beyond the premises to satisfy the goal of truth. The reason we nevertheless do go beyond what is logically implied by the premises is

that we aim at more than mere truth: we aim at informative truth. It is this very feature that makes us strive for a more lenient explication of the logical factor of the quality of arguments in the first place; and without it Hume s problem of the justification of induction would not even get off the ground. Thus, the important question is whether and in which sense inductive logic can be justified relative to the goal of informative truth. One answer is given by Huber (2005). There it is shown that incremental confirmation in the sense of the above mentioned measures converges to the most informative among all true conclusions when more and more premises are learned. References and Further Reading Carnap, Rudolf (1950/1962), Logical Foundations of Probability. 2 nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Carnap, Rudolf & Bar-Hillel, Yehoshua (1953), An Outline of a Theory of Semantic Information. Technical Report 247. Research Laboratory of Electronics, MIT. Christensen, David (1999), Measuring Confirmation. Journal of Philosophy 96, 437-461. Earman, John (1992), Bayes or Bust? A Critical Examination of Bayesian Confirmation Theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Fitelson, Branden (1999), The Plurality of Bayesian Measures of Confirmation and the Problem of Measure Sensitivity. Philosophy of Science 66 (Proceedings), S362-S378. Fitelson, Branden (2005), Inductive Logic. In J. Pfeifer & S. Sarkar (eds.), The Philosophy of Science. An Encyclopedia. Oxford: Routledge. Goodman, Nelson (1983), Fact, Fiction, and Forecast. 4 th ed. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Hawthorne, James (2005), Inductive Logic. In E.N. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Hempel, Carl Gustav (1945), Studies in the Logic of Confirmation. Mind 54, 1-26, 97-121.

Hempel, Carl Gustav & Oppenheim, Paul (1948), Studies in the Logic of Explanation. Philosophy of Science 15, 135-175. Huber, Franz (2005), What Is the Point of Confirmation? Philosophy of Science (Proceedings). Huber, Franz (2006), Confirmation. In J. Fieser & B. Dowden (eds.), Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Hume, David (1739/2000), A Treatise of Human Nature. Ed. by D.F. Norton & M.J. Norton. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Joyce, James F. (1999), The Foundations of Causal Decision Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Kolmogorov, Andrej N. (1956), Foundations of the Theory of Probability, 2 nd ed. New York: Chelsea Publishing Company. Reichenbach, Hans (1938), Experience and Prediction. An Analysis of the Foundations and the Structure of Knowledge. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Skyrms, Brian (2000), Choice and Chance. An Introduction to Inductive Logic. 4 th ed. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth Thomson Learning. Franz Huber The author is grateful to James Hawthorne for helpful comments on an earlier version of this entry.