Realism and Idealism Internal realism

Similar documents
The Externalist and the Structuralist Responses To Skepticism. David Chalmers

Tuomas E. Tahko (University of Helsinki)

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism

Putnam, Languages and Worlds

Magic, semantics, and Putnam s vat brains

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

Semanticism and Realism

Relativism and Indeterminacy of Meaning (Quine) Indeterminacy of Translation

Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology* Oxford University Press, 2009

Ontological Justification: From Appearance to Reality Anna-Sofia Maurin (PhD 2002)

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Against Vague and Unnatural Existence: Reply to Liebesman

1 Why should you care about metametaphysics?

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

Metaontological Deflationism in the Aftermath of the Quine-Carnap Debate

A Logical Approach to Metametaphysics

Chapter Six. Putnam's Anti-Realism

Questions about Internal and External Questions about God

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Comments on Ontological Anti-Realism

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

Metametametaphysics and Dialetheism

Interpretation: Keeping in Touch with Reality. Gilead Bar-Elli. 1. In a narrow sense a theory of meaning (for a language) is basically a Tarski-like

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

Metametaphysics, edited by David Chalmers, David Manley, and Ryan Wasserman. Oxford University Press, 2009, 544 pp.

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first.

Ks exist, but they take their disagreement to be a standard, first- order metaphysical

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

Metametametaphysics and Dialetheism

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE

Retrospective Remarks on Events (Kim, Davidson, Quine) Philosophy 125 Day 20: Overview. The Possible & The Actual I: Intensionality of Modality 2

Semantic Pragmatism and A Priori Knowledge (or Yes we could all be brains in a vat ) *

Logic is Metaphysics

Chance, Chaos and the Principle of Sufficient Reason

BonJour Against Materialism. Just an intellectual bandwagon?

CRITICAL NOTICE. Much Ado About Something JESSICA WILSON. 1. Introduction

Neo- Carnapian Quietism:

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

a0rxh/ On Van Inwagen s Argument Against the Doctrine of Arbitrary Undetached Parts WESLEY H. BRONSON Princeton University

Orthodox truthmaker theory cannot be defended by cost/benefit analysis

Could i conceive being a brain in a vat? John D. Collier a a

Is Content Holism Incoherent? 1. Kirk A. Ludwig Department of Philosophy University of Florida Gainesville, FL

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7c The World

Mereological Ontological Arguments and Pantheism 1. which draw on the resources of mereology, i.e. the theory of the part-whole relation.

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

Reactions & Debate. Non-Convergent Truth

Philosophy Courses in English

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

Minerva Access is the Institutional Repository of The University of Melbourne

The Illusion of Scientific Realism: An Argument for Scientific Soft Antirealism

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

The Inscrutability of Reference and the Scrutability of Truth

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

Structuralism as a Response to Skepticism

Quantificational logic and empty names

Grounding and Analyticity. David Chalmers

A Priori Skepticism and the KK Thesis

From Meaning is Use to the Rejection of Transcendent Truth

TRANSCENDENTAL ARGUMENTS: VERIPICATIONISM OR PARASITISM? Douglas Ehring

CONCRETE UNIVERSALS AND SPATIAL RELATIONS* ANTTI KESKINEN University of Tampere. MARKKU KAINÄNEN University of Helsinki

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE OVERVIEW LOGICAL CONSTANTS WEEK 5: MODEL-THEORETIC CONSEQUENCE JONNY MCINTOSH

Reply to Florio and Shapiro

Idealism and the Harmony of Thought and Reality

Truth and Realism. EDITED BY PATRICK GREENOUGH AND MICHAEL P. LYNCH. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. ix Price h/b, p/b.

The Objectivity of the Past

Postmodal Metaphysics

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

SAMPLE. Religious Language, Reference, and Autonomy

Logical Realism and the Metaphysics of Logic Michaela McSweeney Draft please do not cite without permission

Lynch s Metaphysical Pluralism

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

There is no need to explain who Hilary Putnam is in light of the sheer number of books and articles on his work that have appeared over the past

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Epistemology for Naturalists and Non-Naturalists: What s the Difference?

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY FALL 2013 COURSE DESCRIPTIONS

Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010).

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

Biola University: An Ontology of Knowledge Course Points discussed 5/27/97

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

appearance is often different from reality, and it s reality that counts.

On Quine s Ontology: quantification, extensionality and naturalism (from commitment to indifference)

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

The Metaphysical Interpretation of Logical Truth

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp.

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

TRUTH-MAKERS AND CONVENTION T

Armstrongian Particulars with Necessary Properties

Can logical consequence be deflated?

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives

WHY RELATIVISM IS NOT SELF-REFUTING IN ANY INTERESTING WAY

Part One. On Being Alienated

BOOK REVIEWS. The Philosophical Review, Vol. 111, No. 4 (October 2002)

Transcription:

Realism and Idealism Internal realism Owen Griffiths oeg21@cam.ac.uk St John s College, Cambridge 12/11/15

Easy answers Last week, we considered the metaontological debate between Quine and Carnap. Quine put forward a methodology for approaching ontology and Carnap sought to undermine it with his toolkit of linguistic frameworks and internal/ external questions. A Carnapian approach can, and often is, applied to the realism/ antirealism debate more generally. It can be used to show that there is no real disagreement: the two agree about contentious statements read internally and, externally, the statements are meaningless. I ended by warning caution against such apparently easy answers. Today we think about why.

The Cartesianism principle Perhaps Carnapian methods can be used to deflate the Independence and Correspondence principles, but how about the Cartesianism principle? Cartesianism Even an ideal theory might be radically false. Carnap would have rejected this principle. When we are discussing the truth or falsity of a theory, we are asking an external question. This is either nonsensical or, more charitably, pragmatic. If we take it as a pragmatic question, it amounts to: should we endorse this theory? It is confused, then, to say that a theory is ideal (and so, surely, worthy of endorsement) but false. Such sceptical hypotheses are ruled out by Carnap, largely because talk of the truth of a theory has been ruled out.

Internal realism Putnam too considered the rejection of the Cartesianism principle in response to the model-theoretic argument. He first presented the model-theoretic argument in his Realism and Reason (1977) and, in the same paper, introduced a position called internal realism. As Tim Button (The Limits of Realism, Part B) is careful to present, there is no one position that Putnam calls internal realism throughout his career. Button distinguishes three positions in particular. What the three all have in common, however, is the rejection of the Cartesianism principle. It is understandable that Putnam would reject this principle: recall it was the Catresianism principle that landed external realism in trouble by entailing incoherent semantic scepticism.

Scepticism Internal realism accepts Independence and Correspondence, but rejects Cartesianism. But what exactly does it mean to reject the Cartesianism principle, and how does the internal realist justify their rejection? There are many forms of scepticism. We can be sceptics about meaning, reference, the external world, etc. Different internal realist positions can therefore be generated by varying the amount of scepticism they are willing to tolerate. The external realist entertains all forms of scepticism. But we saw that they can t possibly be right, since semantic scepticism is self-refuting: it cannot even be formulated.

Putnam s BIVs Recall Putnam s response to BIV scepticism. The BIV hypothesis is that everyone, always and everywhere, is a permanently envatted brain. He argues against this scenario as follows: 1 The BIV word brain doesn t refer to brains. 2 My word brain refers to brains. 3 I am not a BIV Premise 1 is defended by a modest semantic externalism. And the sceptic needs premise 2 to be true, otherwise they cannot formulate their position.

A BIV variant Putnam s argument here seems sound, as far as it goes. But it doesn t go all that far. We can easily vary the case so that the same argument is no longer sound. Consider this scenario: a few seconds ago, everyone on Earth became an envatted brain.

A BIV variant Now consider the argument again: 1 The BIV word brain doesn t refer to brains. 2 My word brain refers to brains. 3 I am not a BIV After the envatting, it doesn t seem like 1 is likely to be true. After all, the BIV will have spent most of its life interacting with brains normally, so the causal links do seem to be in place. Putnam s argument can, therefore, show that we are not eternally envatted brains, or that we have not been recently envatted.

BIVs more generally We can clearly generate infinitely many sceptical scenarios. For example, consider the case where everyone was envatted x seconds ago, for all values of x. Some of these sceptical scenarios we can probably solve, e.g. when we were envatted so long ago that the majority of our information about brains really is from brains-in-the-image. Some of these sceptical scenarios we probably cannot solve, e.g. when we were envatted very recently. It s not at all clear where the cut-off is, and it seems arbitrary indeed to assume that there is one.

Internal and external realism This is, of course, only a brief overview of the range of sceptical hypotheses that we can cook up. There is enough here, however, to see that the extent to which we should accept, and the extent to which we should reject, Cartesianism is unclear. We shouldn t accept Cartesianism outright, as the external realist does, since many sceptical hypotheses can be refuted. But then we shouldn t reject it outright, as the internal realist does, since some sceptical hypothesese cannot be refuted. If we are a realist, then, it seems we should place ourselves somewhere between the poles of internal and external realism.

Back to Carnap Carnap, we have seen, rules out scepticism: it makes no sense to ask whether an ideal theory could be false. And neo-carnapians tend to characterise their position in response to scepticism. In effect, they rule out all sceptical hypotheses: we are not misled, since to be misled would be to speak nonsense. But what does it mean to rule out sceptical hypotheses? We can rule out some, but certainly not all. Carnapians are, then, internal realists.

Conceptual relativism At around the same time that Putnam began to subscribe to internal realism, he began to endorse conceptual relativism. Quine endorsed a similar view, ontological relativity, which can be considered a version of conceptual relativism. Considering this view will round off our discussion of Putnam s internal realism.

Conceptual relativism Relativism is, roughly, the view that something has its properties only in virtue of a certain framework. Famously, moral relativism is the view that the moral properties of an act are only possessed relative to cultural standards. Conceptual relativism is a metaphysical doctrine. It is the view that the world is not in itself structured: human minds impose structure by applying their categories.

A mereological example Putnam s favourite example involves mereology: the study of parts and wholes. Putnam says that the example and the approach is inspired by Carnap. Consider a table with objects on it. Putnam argues that a commonsense view would count 3 objects on the table: A, B and C. A mereologist then comes along and argues that there are not 3 objects on the table but 7: A, B, C, A + B, A + C, B + C, A + B + C.

A mereological example what is (by commonsense standards) the same situation can be described in many different ways, depending on how we use the words. The situation does not itself legislate how words like object, entity, and exist must be used. What is wrong with the notion of objects existing independently of conceptual schemes is that there are no standards for the use of even the logical notions apart from conceptual choices. (Putnam, Representation and Reality, p. 114)

Counting Putnam concludes from this discussion that we should be tolerant of the commonsense and mereological views. In the Grundlagen, Frege notes that we can only count things under concepts: if I give a deck of playing cards with the words determine the number thereof, he does not thereby know, whether I want to find out the number of cards, or of complete games, or perhaps of the point cards in skat.... I must add a word: card, game, or point-card. ( 22) In this way, we may put the apparent disagreement between the commonsense theorist and the mereologist down to an ambiguous instruction.

Disagreement Of course, we don t want to say that they are both correct, since that would land us in contradiction. The commonsense theorist could offer the usual formalisation of there are exactly 3 things, the mereologist there are exactly 7 things, and those cannot both be true. Instead we should say that the commonsense theorist is correct relative to their conceptual scheme and the mereologist is correct relative to theirs. But now that we have relativized truth to conceptual schemes in this way, there is no longer any good sense in which the two sides disagree. And, as with Carnap s internal/ external distinction, if there s no disagreement, there s no real debate: we should reject mereology and other metaphysical questions.

Problems The problem with conceptual relativism as with many forms of relativism is how to formulate it in a way that is non-trivially true. Donald Davidson, in his well-known critique On the very idea of a conceptual scheme (1973), notes the following issue: We cannot attach a clear meaning to the notion of organizing a single object (the world, nature, etc.) unless that object is understood to contain or consist in other objects. Someone whos sets out to organize a closet arranges the things in it. (1973: 14)

Problems The thought is that not every notion can be scheme-relative. In particular, the world cannot be scheme-relative when we set about dissolving the commonsense/ mereological debate. To make sense of there being many ways to conceptualise the world (organize the closet), we must have a world (closet) and objects in it.

Cookie cutters A common metaphor is to think of the world as a lump of dough. To be an object in a conceptual scheme is to be a chunk of that dough, sliced out by a cookie cutter. The cookie cutter is a conceptual scheme. An object is clearly relativized to a conceptual scheme. But there is still just one piece of dough that transcends any conceptual scheme.

Quantifiers The mereologist says that there are more things than the commonsense theorist thinks. If the commonsense theorist thinks that they are speaking about all the objects, therefore, they are wrong. We could instead charitably think of the commonsense theorist as using restricted quantifiers. But then we hardly have relativization in any interesting sense. And we have no reason to reject the debate.

Formulating conceptual relativism The conceptual relativist wants to say something like the following: There is no real debate about mereology. Wherever the commonsense theorist finds objects, the mereologist finds more objects. But they don t really disagree: they are each correct relative to their conceptual scheme. But the conceptual relativist must formulate their position within a conceptual scheme. And that scheme had better countenance all of the objects: in this case, the sparse commonsense objects and the abundant mereological objects.

Formulating conceptual relativism The conceptual relativist s scheme, therefore, had better include in its domain all of the objects in the sub-domains discussed. And this is exactly the scheme-transcendent position that the conceptual relativist denies. The point generalises: give me a conceptual relativism R that says both A and B are correct relative to their schemes. R must be formulated in a scheme that transcends A and B. This transcendence is ruled out by R itself.

Conclusions That concludes our discussion of realism and antirealism. The commonsense position of external realism cannot be correct: the model-theoretic argument showed us that. Antirealism stands in direct opposition to external realism: it takes reality to be in part constructed by human minds, and so rejects bivalence. Its formulation is not easy and, especially when developed in an inferentialist direction, its cogency is unclear.

Conclusions Internal realism stands somewhere in between but it rejects Cartesianism and we have seen that this can be done in infinitely many ways. Alongside these views are various attempts to undermine metaphysics: Carnap s external/ internal questions and conceptual relativism being two major examples. These are not easy views to formulate, though. It s surprising, too, that the themes of semantics and scepticism have been so utterly central to these metametaphysical debates.