Medieval theories of consequence

Similar documents
Consequence. Gyula Klima. 1. The limitations of Aristotelian syllogistic, and the need for non-syllogistic consequences

Self-Reference and Validity revisited. in Medieval Formal Logic: Obligations, Insolubles and Consequences, ed. M. Yrjönsuuri, Kluwer 2001, pp.

Durham Research Online

This is an electronic reprint of the original article. This reprint may differ from the original in pagination and typographic detail.

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5

Niels Jørgen Green-Pedersen in memoriam by Sten Ebbesen

Truth, Signification and Paradox. Stephen Read. The Real Proposition. Bradwardine s Theory Buridan s Principle 1 / 28. Truth, Paradox.

Why Don't Mediaeval Logicians Ever Tell Us What They re Doing? Or, What Is This, A Conspiracy? 1

Artificial Intelligence: Valid Arguments and Proof Systems. Prof. Deepak Khemani. Department of Computer Science and Engineering

LOGICINTHE14 th CENTURY AFTER OCKHAM

William Ockham on Universals

John Buridan. Summulae de Dialectica IX Sophismata

FORMALIZING MEDIEVAL LOGICAL THEORIES

University of St Andrews, Reino Unido. Resumen. Abstract

A Judgmental Formulation of Modal Logic

A Medieval Solution to the Liar Paradox. Stephen Read. Solution Postulate 2 Bradwardine s Theses Bradwardine s Proof Truth and Signification 1 / 20

SYLLOGISTIC LOGIC CATEGORICAL PROPOSITIONS

MCQ IN TRADITIONAL LOGIC. 1. Logic is the science of A) Thought. B) Beauty. C) Mind. D) Goodness

G. H. von Wright Deontic Logic

Aquinas' Third Way Modalized

How Gödelian Ontological Arguments Fail

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER IX CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE

THREE LOGICIANS: ARISTOTLE, SACCHERI, FREGE

Modality in Medieval Philosophy. Stephen Read

An alternative understanding of interpretations: Incompatibility Semantics

c Peter King, 1987; all rights reserved. WILLIAM OF OCKHAM: ORDINATIO 1 d. 2 q. 6

The Appeal to Reason. Introductory Logic pt. 1

1 Concerning distinction 39 I ask first whether God immutably foreknows future

History of Logic: Medieval

Keywords: logica utens, logica docens, token-symbols, conventional representation, natural representation

Chapter 9- Sentential Proofs

Prior on an insolubilium of Jean Buridan

Anthony P. Andres. The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic. Anthony P. Andres

UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016

The Modal Ontological Argument

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice

How Ockham Recast the Topical Tradition

Revisiting the Socrates Example

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

FORMALIZING MEDIEVAL LOGICAL THEORIES

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

A Liar Paradox. Richard G. Heck, Jr. Brown University

A Generalization of Hume s Thesis

LOGIC ANTHONY KAPOLKA FYF 101-9/3/2010

Reply to Bronstein, Leunissen, and Beere

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

Early Franciscan Theology: an Outline. Relationship between scripture and tradition; theology as interpretation of scripture and tradition

Can Negation be Defined in Terms of Incompatibility?

A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports. Stephen Schiffer New York University

Situations in Which Disjunctive Syllogism Can Lead from True Premises to a False Conclusion

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

THE FORM OF REDUCTIO AD ABSURDUM J. M. LEE. A recent discussion of this topic by Donald Scherer in [6], pp , begins thus:

Language, Meaning, and Information: A Case Study on the Path from Philosophy to Science Scott Soames

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

SOME RADICAL CONSEQUENCES OF GEACH'S LOGICAL THEORIES

Syllogisms in Aristotle and Boethius

WHY PLANTINGA FAILS TO RECONCILE DIVINE FOREKNOWLEDGE

Automated Reasoning Project. Research School of Information Sciences and Engineering. and Centre for Information Science Research

Chapter 6. Fate. (F) Fatalism is the belief that whatever happens is unavoidable. (55)

Peter L.P. Simpson January, 2015

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

Scope Fallacies and the "Decisive Objection" Against Endurance

In this section you will learn three basic aspects of logic. When you are done, you will understand the following:

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak.

Illustrating Deduction. A Didactic Sequence for Secondary School

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

Gregory T. Doolan Associate Professor of Philosophy The Catholic University of America 620 Michigan Avenue, N.E. Washington, DC 20064

Intuitive evidence and formal evidence in proof-formation

Treatise I,iii,14: Hume offers an account of all five causes: matter, form, efficient, exemplary, and final cause.

Powerful Arguments: Logical Argument Mapping

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

Reductio ad Absurdum, Modulation, and Logical Forms. Miguel López-Astorga 1

Overview of Today s Lecture

Inference versus Consequence *

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Study Guides. Chapter 1 - Basic Training

Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview

Can Gödel s Incompleteness Theorem be a Ground for Dialetheism? *

Critical Thinking is:

Some Logical Paradoxes from Jean Buridan

Courses providing assessment data PHL 202. Semester/Year

Ethical Consistency and the Logic of Ought

A. Problem set #3 it has been posted and is due Tuesday, 15 November

prohibition, moral commitment and other normative matters. Although often described as a branch

What is an Argument? Validity vs. Soundess of Arguments

CHAPTER 2 THE LARGER LOGICAL LANDSCAPE NOVEMBER 2017

270 Now that we have settled these issues, we should answer the first question [n.

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

A Puzzle about Knowing Conditionals i. (final draft) Daniel Rothschild University College London. and. Levi Spectre The Open University of Israel

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

ON CAUSAL AND CONSTRUCTIVE MODELLING OF BELIEF CHANGE

Instructor s Manual 1

INTERMEDIATE LOGIC Glossary of key terms

The Philosophy of Logic

A Hexagon of Opposition for the Theism/Atheism Debate. Lorenz Demey

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

Free will and foreknowledge

CURRICULUM VITAE. Matthew W. McKeon

Transcription:

Medieval theories of consequence A genuine medieval invention. Medieval theories of consequence present a level of systematization not to be found in previous investigations (with the possible exception of Stoic logic). Some see in them the forerunners of the propositional turn in logic, as opposed to term logic. But the logic of terms also occupies a prominent place in 14 th century theories of consequence.

14 th century logicians were probably the first to attempt a systematization of the propositional rules of inference such as contraposition, ex falso, the behavior of conjunctions, disjunctions etc. Medieval logicians sought not only to establish the validity of such basic rules; they also made inquiries on the very nature of logical consequence and inference. In this sense, their investigations overlap not only with modern proof theory, but also with modern philosophy of logic.

Historical development Controversy: how come treatises with titles such as De consequentiis began to appear at the very beginning of the 14 th century? The very term consequentia was in use in exactly this sense since Boethius (5 th -6 th Century): the topic itself occupied a prominent position in earlier traditions (cf. Abelard). But no treatises or chapters with this name seem to have been written before the 14 th Century.

Possible sources (See N. Green-Pedersen 1984, The Tradition of the Topics in the Middle Ages) Commentaries on the Topics. Treatises on syncategoremata, especially si (if then). Commentaries on the Prior Analytics. Hypothetical syllogisms.

Development in the 14 th Century Very early, rather primitive treatises: two anonymous and Burley s De consequentiis. Second stage more elaborate treatises, but external validation for consequences (middles, reworked Topics): Ockham s Summa Logicae, Burley s De Puritate Artis Logicae. Continental tradition sophisticated treatises, where formal consequences are defined substitutionally: Buridan, Albert of Saxony, Pseudo-Scotus, Marsilius of Inghen. British tradition characterized by the definition of formal consequence in terms of containment of the consequent in the antecedent: Richard Billingham, Ralph Strode, Richard Lavenham.

What is a consequentia? A conditional sentence? No. A consequence, i.e. a logical relation between contents? Yes/no. An inference, i.e. the act performed by somebody of drawing a conclusion from premises? Yes/no.

General definition of consequence All medieval authors accept as a necessary condition for the validity of a consequence the incompatibility (modal) criterion: It is impossible for the antecedent to be true while the consequent is false. Whether this is a sufficient condition is a matter of contention. Adjustments of the general formulation of this condition are often necessary.

Buridan s definition of consequence A proposition is antecedent to another when it is related to it [the other] in such a way that it is impossible for things to be in whatever way the first signifies them to be without their being in whatever way the other signifies them to be, when these propositions are put forward together. (Buridan 1976, 22) No proposition is negative, therefore no donkey is running. Buridan is committed to proposition-tokens.

Formal vs. Material Consequences This distinction is probably one of the most important aspects of medieval theories of consequences. The terms were introduced by Ockham in the Summa Logicae, but his criterion to separate formal from material consequences did not move forward (based on weird middles ).

With Buridan (Pseudo-Scotus, Albert of Saxony), substitutional criterion: Formal consequence means that [the consequence] holds for all terms, retaining the form common to all. (Buridan 1976, 22/23). In the British school, formal consequences are defined as those where the consequent is contained in the antecedent: A consequence is formal when the consequent necessary belongs to the understanding of the antecedent, as it is in the case of syllogistic consequence, and in many enthymematic consequences. (Lavenham)

These two notions of formal consequences disagree not only with respect to the intension of the concept of formal consequence, but also with respect to its extension. Enthymemes are formal consequences according to the British school, but not according to Buridan. Every man is an animal. Thus Socrates is an animal. What s missing?

Simple vs. as-of-now consequences Absolute consequences hold always and necessarily, while as-of-now consequences hold at a specific time or under specific assumptions. Pseudo-Scotus: the absolute vs. as-of-now distinction applies only to material consequences and amounts to the modal value of the missing premise that can be added in order to turn the (enthymematic) consequence into a formal one:

- If the missing premise is a necessary truth, then it is a simple consequence; if it is a contingent truth, then it is an as-of-now consequence. Peter of Mantua presents the absolute vs. as-of-now distinction as primary: the formal vs. material distinction applies only to absolute consequences (as-of-now consequences are always material consequences). For him, an as-of-now consequence is a consequence in which the contradictory of the consequent can indeed be true at the same time as the antecedent, but not at the time indicated by the copula or verb in question.

Rules of inference recognized by medieval authors Whatever follows from a consequent follows from the antecedent, or alternatively, whatever is antecedent to the antecedent is antecedent to the consequent (Burley 2000, 4). A => B B => C Rule 2 ------------------------------------ A => C

Two derived rules: (2 ) Whatever follows from a consequent and from its antecedent follows from the antecedent by itself (Burley 2000, 6). A => B A, B => C Rule 2 ------------------------------------------ A => C

(2 ) Whatever follows from a consequent with something added follows from the antecedent with the same thing added (Burley 2000, 7). A => B B, C => D Rule 2 ------------------------------------------- A, C => D

Derivations of the auxiliary rules: Burley derives (2 ) from Rule 2 plus what he takes to be a logical fact, which the modern reader may recognize as a special case of right-weakening: every proposition implies itself together with its consequent (2 ) A => B WR --------------------- A => A, B A, B => C (hyp.) Rule 2 ------------------------------------------------- A => C

Similarly, he derives (2 ) from Rule 2 plus simultaneous applications of special cases of right-weakening and leftweakening: an antecedent together with something added implies the consequent with the same thing added. (2 ) A => B WR, LR ---------------------- A, C => B, C B, C => D (hyp.) Rule 2 -------------------------------------------------- A, C => D

Other rules (from Pozzi 1978) From the impossible anything follows. If the antecedent must be conceded, so must be the consequent. If the consequent must be denied, so must be the antecedent. From the contradictory of the consequent the contradictory of the antecedent follows : contraposition.

Whatever follows from the contradictory of the antecedent follows from the contradictory of the consequent. Whatever is antecedent to the contradictory of the consequent is antecedent to the contradictory of the antecedent. From a conjunction to one of its parts constitutes a valid consequence. From one of its parts to the whole disjunction constitutes a valid consequence.

From a conditional with its antecedent to its consequent constitutes a valid consequence. (Notice the distinction between consequence and conditional). Dissident voices: some authors did not accept the ex impossibili and ad necessarium rules (Nicolaus Drukken of Dacia and Richard Ferrybridge). What they seem to be proposing is that the criterion of containment of the consequent in the antecedent be used as a necessary and sufficient criterion for all valid consequences, and not only for the formal ones (as in Billinham, Strode et al.).

References Primary texts: Albert of Saxony 1988, Perutilis logica, in the incunabular edition of Venice 1522, with a Spanish translation by A. Muñoz García, Univ. del Zulia, Maracaibo. John Buridan 1976, Iohannis Buridani tractatus de consequentiis. (ed. H. Hubien). Series Philosophes Médievaux Vol. XVI. Louvain, Université de Louvain. Pseudo-Scotus 2001, Questions on Aristotle s Prior Analytics: Question X. In Yrjönsuuri 2001 (ed.), 225-234. Richard Billingham 2003, Richard Billingham De Consequentiis mit Toledo- Kommentar (ed. S. Weber). Amsterdam, B.R. Grüner.

F. Schupp 1988, Logical problems of the medieval theory of consequences, with the edition of the Liber consequentiarum. Naples, Bibliopolis. W. Seaton 1973, An Edition and Translation of the Tractatus de Consequentiis by Ralph Strode, Fourteenth Century Logician and Friend of Geoffrey Chaucer. Ph.D. Dissertation, University of California, Berkeley. P.V. Spade 1974, "Five Logical Tracts by Richard Lavenham," in J. Reginald O'Donnell, ed., Essays in Honour of Anton Charles Pegis, Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1974, pp. 70 124. P.V. Spade 1976, "Robert Fland's Consequentiae: An Edition," Mediaeval Studies 38 (1976), pp. 54 84. Walter Burley 1980, De Consequentiis (ed. N.J. Green-Pederson). Fransciscan Studies 40, 102-166.

Walter Burley 2000, On the Purity of the Art of Logic the shorter and the longer treatises (transl. P.V. Spade). New Haven, Yale University Press. William of Ockham 1974, Opera Philosophica I. St. Bonaventure, The Franciscan Institute. Secondary texts: C. Dutilh Novaes 2005b, Buridan s consequentia: consequence and inference within a token-based semantics. History and Philosophy of Logic 26(4), 2005, 277-297. N.J. Green-Pedersen 1981, Walter Burley, De consequentiis and the origin of the theory of consequence. In H.A.G. Braakhuis, C.H. Kneepkens & L.M. de Rijk (eds.), English Logic and Semantics. Nijmegen, Ingenium, 279-301.

N.J. Green-Pedersen 1984, The Tradition of the Topics in the Middle Ages. München, Philosophia Verlag. N.J. Green-Pedersen 1985, Early British Treatises on Consequences. In P. Osmund Lewry O.P. (ed.), The Rise of British Logic. Papers in Mediaeval Studies 7. Toronto, Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 285-307. E. Karger 1993, A theory of immediate inferences contained in Buridan s logic, in K. Jacobi (ed.), Argumentationstheorie. Leiden, Brill, 407-429. M. Kaufmann 1993, Nochmals; Ockhams consequentiae und die materiale implikation. In Jacobi 1993, 223-232. P. King 2001, Medieval proof theory. In Yrjönsuuri 2001, 117-145. C.J. Martin 1986, William s Machine. The Journal of Philosophy 83 (10), 564-572.

L. Pozzi 1978, Le consequentiae nella logica medievale. Padova, Liviana. S. Read 1993, Formal and material consequence, disjunctive syllogism and Gamma. In Jacobi (ed.) 1993, 233-262. S. Read 2001, Self-reference and validity revisited. In Yrjönsuuri (ed.) 2001, 183-196. M. Yrjönsuuri (ed.) 2001, Medieval Formal Logic. Dordrecht, Kluwer.