Naive and sophisticated action theories

Similar documents
Thompson on naive action theory

Stout s teleological theory of action

Ayer on the argument from illusion

2.3. Failed proofs and counterexamples

Thomas Reid on personal identity

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

Act individuation and basic acts

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Aboutness and Justification

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

The normativity of content and the Frege point

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

DISCUSSION NOTES A RESOLUTION OF A PARADOX OF PROMISING WALTER SINNOTT-ARMSTRONG

Belief as the Power to Judge

Entity Grounding and Truthmaking

Russellianism and Explanation. David Braun. University of Rochester

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

For the definitive version of this article, see Philosophical Studies. Normative Reasons as Good Bases

Presuppositions (Ch. 6, pp )

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Martin s case for disjunctivism

Reasons for action, acting for reasons, and rationality

Shieva Kleinschmidt [This is a draft I completed while at Rutgers. Please do not cite without permission.] Conditional Desires.

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

Skepticism and Internalism

From Grounding to Truth-Making: Some Thoughts

Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2

Theories of propositions

(A fully correct plan is again one that is not constrained by ignorance or uncertainty (pp ); which seems to be just the same as an ideal plan.

Lecture One: The Aspiration for a Natural Science of the Social

Social mechanisms and explaining how: A reply to Kimberly Chuang Johannes Persson, Lund University

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

New Chapter: Epistemology: The Theory and Nature of Knowledge

A guide to Anscombe s Intention, 1-31

Instrumental Normativity: In Defense of the Transmission Principle Benjamin Kiesewetter

THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1. Dana K. Nelkin. I. Introduction. abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory.

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

GROUNDING AND LOGICAL BASING PERMISSIONS

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1

Julius & Aleks 03/27/2014

Informational Models in Deontic Logic: A Comment on Ifs and Oughts by Kolodny and MacFarlane

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

The view that all of our actions are done in self-interest is called psychological egoism.

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Scanlon on Double Effect

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Normative Transmission and Necessary Means

International Phenomenological Society

Moore on External Relations

Practical reasoning and enkrasia. Abstract

Proofs of Non-existence

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Rationality in Action. By John Searle. Cambridge: MIT Press, pages, ISBN Hardback $35.00.

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

3.3. Negations as premises Overview

How and How Not to Take on Brueckner s Sceptic. Christoph Kelp Institute of Philosophy, KU Leuven

How Many Kinds of Reasons? (Pre-print November 2008) Introduction

THE SCOPE OF INSTRUMENTAL REASON. Mark Schroeder Princeton University

SKEPTICISM, ABDUCTIVISM, AND THE EXPLANATORY GAP. Ram Neta University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

Edinburgh Research Explorer

Could have done otherwise, action sentences and anaphora

Cottingham s On the Meaning of Life and Aronson s Gratitude

CHECKING THE NEIGHBORHOOD: A REPLY TO DIPAOLO AND BEHRENDS ON PROMOTION

Luminosity in the stream of consciousness

Excerpts from Aristotle

The ground of ground, essence, and explanation

NOTES ON WILLIAMSON: CHAPTER 11 ASSERTION Constitutive Rules

HOW TO BE (AND HOW NOT TO BE) A NORMATIVE REALIST:

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Kripke on the distinctness of the mind from the body

Naturalist Cognitivism: The Open Question Argument; Subjectivism

Reply to Robert Koons

Week of Prayer. Prayer: Preparing for Battle

NORMATIVE PRACTICAL REASONING. by John Broome and Christian Piller. II Christian Piller

Moral dilemmas. Digital Lingnan University. Lingnan University. Gopal Shyam NAIR

Today we begin our discussion of the existence of God.

Faith and Philosophy, April (2006), DE SE KNOWLEDGE AND THE POSSIBILITY OF AN OMNISCIENT BEING Stephan Torre

Here s a very dumbed down way to understand why Gödel is no threat at all to A.I..

In Defense of The Wide-Scope Instrumental Principle. Simon Rippon

Acting on a Ground Reasons, Rational Motivation, and Explanation

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

CLIMBING THE MOUNTAIN SUMMARY CHAPTER 1 REASONS. 1 Practical Reasons

Imprint. Giving Practical Reasons. David Enoch. Philosophers. The Hebrew University. volume 11, no. 4 march 2011

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

Internalism Re-explained

The Skeptic and the Dogmatist

Naïve Action Theory Michael Thompson

Perceiving Abstract Objects

Internalism Re-explained 1. Ralph Wedgwood

Logic -type questions

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

1/12. The A Paralogisms

What should I believe? Only what I have evidence for.

The Necessity of Moral Judgments

Transcription:

Naive and sophisticated action theories phil 43503 Jeff Speaks February 18, 2009 1 The distinction between naive and sophisticated explanations of action..... 1 2 Different forms of action-explanation and their relations............. 1 3 What intentional actions have in common..................... 2 4 Sophisticated action theory and the argument from illusion........... 3 1 The distinction between naive and sophisticated explanations of action Thompson draws a contrast between naive and sophisticated explanations of action. Naive explanations of action explain one action in terms of another, as in I m breaking those eggs because I m making an omelette. Sophisticated explanations of action are the ones with which we are by now very familiar, which offer an explanation of an action in terms of an agent s wants, intentions, or other mental states. It is very natural, as Thompson notes, to think that naive action explanation is a kind of dispensable way of talking, and that every case of naive action explanation is underwritten by a sophisticated action explanation. Thompson opposes the idea that naive action explanations are underwritten by more fundamental sophisticated explanations. The principle aim of the paper is to show that, in the end, we have to recognize naive action explanations as a more fundamental class of explanations of action than sophisticated action explanations. If this is right, then a plausible moral is that to understand the nature of intentional action, we should focus not on the relationship between mental states and actions expressed by sophisticated action explanations, but rather on the relationship between one action and another expressed by naive action explanations. 2 Different forms of action-explanation and their relations The explanations with which we are concerned are of the form

X because Y The thing filled in for X the thing which gets explained is the explanandum. The thing filled in for Y the thing which does the explaining is the explanans. Thompson considers four different sorts of sentences which might play the role of explanans and explanandum in an explanation of the sort that we are interested in: I am doing X I am trying to do X I intend to do X I want to do X So far we have focused on explanations which let things with the form of the first of these be explained by things with the form of one of the bottom two. Thompson points out that we can construct ordinary sounding explanations with any combination of these four as explanans and explanandum. This gives us sixteen possible forms of because sentence. Thompson suggests that these four sorts of claims stand in a certain interesting relation: on the list above, each of these sentences entails the truth of each sentence below it, but is not entailed by any below it. One might object along the following lines: if intention implies belief, then trying cannot entail intention, since one can clearly try to do something that one does not believe that one will do. Thompson s reply (103) seems to be that these sorts of objections rest on ambiguities in words like intend, and that there is one good use of the term on which it does not imply belief. (Maybe this is a use some might express by decided to rather than intended to. ) He makes the same reply to the objection that one may intend to do something which one does not want to do; want must be ambiguous, as is shown by the acceptability of sentences like I don t want to do what I want to do I want to do what I ought to do. This system of entailments will become important later when we turn to discussion of Thompson s treatment of sophisticated action explanations, and an objection to his own prioritizing of naive action explanations. 3 What intentional actions have in common Thompson makes the following claim about the scope of naive action explanations: wherever a completed individual action is intentional... it will be possible to find a true naive rationalization in which that description appears in the explanans. 2

That is: Thompson s conjecture A is φing intentionally ψ (A is ψing because A is φing) This raises an immediate problem. If it is true that A is ψing because A is φing, then it seems that A is ψing for a reason, which means that A s ψing is an intentional action. But then, if Thompson s conjecture is true, it follows that it too must appear in the explanans of a naive action explanation, which means that there must be some other action which A is doing because she is doing this action. But this leads to the conclusion that one whenever one performs a single intentional action, one performs infinitely many intentional actions. Thompson accepts this conclusion, and suggests that the impression that it is unacceptable depends on a requirement that for an act to be intentional it must be cognized in advance of the action. A separate worry: does Thompson s acceptance of this conclusion put some pressure on his views about the entailment from doing something intentionally to intending to do it, or wanting to do it? So far this is only presented as a necessary condition on acting intentionally. But it is clear (112) that Thompson also thinks that it is a sufficient condition, so that we have: A naive theory of intentional action A is φing intentionally df ψ (A is ψing because A is φing) Thompson does not claim that this is an account of the nature of intentional action; but he says some things fairly close to this. In any case, a plausible reading of what he s up to takes its role as explanans in a naive action explanation to explain what makes some acts intentional. Thompson next considers some objections to this sort of view. 4 Sophisticated action theory and the argument from illusion Here s one sort of argument for sophisticated action theory (i.e., a theory which explains intentional action in terms of its relation to mental states like intentions or desires): There are some cases in which an agent would give a naive explanation of her action, but in which that explanation would be false, because the agent is not doing what she thinks she is doing. ( I am getting a knife because I am making a peanut butter and jelly sandwich, said before the discovery that there is no jelly.) But even in these cases, the action is intentional, and done for a reason so there must be some other, sophisticated explanation of the action. ( I 3

am getting a knife because I want top make a PB & J sandwich. ) But surely the kinds of explanation which really give one s reasons for action cannot be different in kind depending on whether the attempted action is successful; so sophisticated explanations must give one s real or fundamental reason even in the case in which the the naive explanation could be true (when one really is making the sandwich). As Thompson says, this shares a structure with the argument from illusion, which aims to show that in perception we are never directly aware of material things. One simple version of that argument might be laid out as follows: 1. In hallucinations, I am not directly aware of a material thing. 2. In veridical experiences, one is only aware of the same sorts of things as in hallucinations. C. In veridical experiences, I am not directly aware of material things. In the case of action, cases in which I am trying to do something which I do not succeed in doing are the analogue of hallucinations. One might then construct the following argument to show that naive action explanations can never really give my reasons for action: 1. If I am not successfully φing, it is false to say that I am ψing because I am φing (because I m not φing). 2. But one s reason for ψing must be the same whether or not it eventually turns out that one is successfully φing. C. Even in the case in which I successfully φ, the fact that I am φing can t give the reason for my ψing my reason must be the fact that I want to φ, or something else which is present in both the successful and the unsuccessful case. Thompson gives two main replies to this argument for sophisticated action theory. The first is a sort of bad company argument, which might be put as follows: Imagine a case in which I say I am getting a knife because I am making a peanut butter and jelly sandwich but in which I fail to get the knife perhaps all the knives are dirty. Then in this case the naive action explanation is again false but in this case it is false because the statement in the explanandum position turns out to be false. Nonetheless, one might think that what I am up too still must have some explanation even though my getting a knife doesn t have an explanation since, as it turns out, I am not getting a knife. So what does have an explanation is something like the fact that I am trying to get a knife. But surely what I have reason to do can t depend on whether my action turns out to be successful; so, even in cases in which I do succeed in getting the knife, I only really ever have a reason for trying to get the knife. One might construct this argument by parallel with the above: 4

1. If I am not successfully φing, it is false to say that I am ψing because X (because I m not φing). 2. But what one has a reason for doing must be the same whether or not it eventually turns out that one is successfully φing. C. Even in the case in which I successfully φ, what I have a reason to do cannot be φing it must be something else, like wanting, or trying, to φ which is present in both the successful and the unsuccessful case. Thompson thinks that this conclusion is absurd: if there are never really reasons for action, then there are no actions done for a reason, and there are no intentional actions. One sometimes has reason to do things, as well as reason to try to do them. Is this really absurd? But let s suppose that Thompson is right. That indicates that something must be wrong with the above argument for sophisticated action theory; but it doesn t show what is wrong with it. And it does nothing to show what is wrong with the following plausible-sounding thought: Cases in which I successfully φ can be, from the agent s point of view, very much like cases in which one tries to φ but is unsuccessful. So how could the agent s reasons for action be fundamentally different between the two cases actions in one case, and states of mind like desires and intentions in the other? Thompson s reply to this argument is that wanting and intending are not states of mind of the same sort as beliefs and judgements, and that there are not, in the end, that fundamentally different from actions. This is the burden of the discussion of aspect in Chapter 8. 5