The Problem of Evil. Prof. Eden Lin The Ohio State University

Similar documents
The free will defense

The problem of evil & the free will defense

Does God exist? The argument from evil

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments

What God Could Have Made

A CRITIQUE OF THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. A Paper. Presented to. Dr. Douglas Blount. Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary. In Partial Fulfillment

PLANTINGA ON THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. Hugh LAFoLLETTE East Tennessee State University

How do Christians respond to the problem of evil? R Calvert, Colton Hills Community School 1

Introductory Matters

Proofs of Non-existence

Prompt: Explain van Inwagen s consequence argument. Describe what you think is the best response

TWO NO, THREE DOGMAS OF PHILOSOPHICAL THEOLOGY

David E. Alexander and Daniel Johnson, eds. Calvinism and the Problem of Evil.

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

Swinburne: The Problem of Evil

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Whence Evil? M. Andorf. Presented to the Fermi Society of Philosophy. December

The Problem of Evil. 1. Introduction to the Problem of Evil: Imagine that someone had told you that I was all of the following:

Why does a supposedly powerful and good God allow natural and moral evil to occur?

The belief in the existence of an omniscient, omnipotent and benevolent God is inconsistent with the existence of human suffering. Discuss.

I will briefly summarize each of the 11 chapters and then offer a few critical comments.

Camino Santa Maria, St. Mary s University, San Antonio, TX 78228, USA;

Pain, Suffering, and a Benevolent God. Topic: The Problem of Good and Evil

The Metaphysics of Perfect Beings, by Michael Almeida. New York: Routledge, Pp $105.00

IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?''

Creation & necessity

The Evidential Argument from Evil

Philosophy of Religion 21: (1987).,, 9 Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht - Printed in the Nethenanas

The Paradox of Free Will

How Gödelian Ontological Arguments Fail

Puzzles for Divine Omnipotence & Divine Freedom

Trinity & contradiction

The Rationality of Religious Beliefs

Simplicity and Why the Universe Exists

Free will and foreknowledge

Permissible tinkering with the concept of God

5 A Modal Version of the

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

12. A Theistic Argument against Platonism (and in Support of Truthmakers and Divine Simplicity)

On A New Cosmological Argument

The Problem of Divine Foreknowledge and Human Freedom

Comments on Van Inwagen s Inside and Outside the Ontology Room. Trenton Merricks

Today s Lecture. Preliminary comments on the Problem of Evil J.L Mackie

The Problem of Evil. Why would a good God create a world where bad things happen?

Does God exist? The argument from evil

NON-MORAL EVIL AND THE FREE WILL DEFENSE

Is#God s#benevolence#impartial?#!! Robert#K.#Garcia# Texas&A&M&University&!!

In Defense of The Wide-Scope Instrumental Principle. Simon Rippon

God and Gratuitous Evil

New Chapter: Philosophy of Religion

The Argument from Evil. Why doesn t God do something?

Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview

Logical Problem of Evil

the absence of good and the impulse to seek our own desires at the expense of the good of others which often results in suffering.

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

The Logical Problem of Evil and the Limited God Defense

WHY PLANTINGA FAILS TO RECONCILE DIVINE FOREKNOWLEDGE

Fatalism. 1. Fatalism: Fatalism is often distinguished from determinism as follows: Determinism: All events are wholly determined by their causes.

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

MEGILL S MULTIVERSE META-ARGUMENT. Klaas J. Kraay Ryerson University

Philosophical Perspectives, 14, Action and Freedom, 2000 TRANSFER PRINCIPLES AND MORAL RESPONSIBILITY. Eleonore Stump Saint Louis University

Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011.

Augustine, On Free Choice of the Will,

100 SATANIC QUESTIONS

Is God Good By Definition?

On the Metaphysical Necessity of Suffering from Natural Evil

Defusing the Common Sense Problem of Evil

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

Free Will Theodicies for Theological Determinists

Either God wants to abolish evil and cannot, or he can but does not want to, or he cannot and does not want to, or lastly he can and wants to.

NO GOD SUFFERING DOES NOT PROVE THERE IS SCOTT M. SULLIVAN WHY INTRODUCTORY COURSES IN CHRISTIAN APOLOGETICS

PHIL Philosophy of Religion

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

Evil and Omnipotence

Free will & divine foreknowledge

What would be so bad about not having libertarian free will?

The Consequence Argument

Am I free? Freedom vs. Fate

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

And if Christ has not been raised, your faith is futile and you are still in your sins. 1 Corinthians 15:17

A Note on a Remark of Evans *

Paley s Inductive Inference to Design

The Coherence and Correspondence Theories of Truth

Tracing and heavenly freedom

In a widely discussed piece entitled "Evil and Omnipotence" John Mackie repeats this claim:

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

(1) If God exists, he would only create a world if there is no better world that he could have created instead.

Logic I or Moving in on the Monkey & Bananas Problem

Joshua Blanchard University of Michigan

Phenomenal Conservatism and Skeptical Theism

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

DORE CLEMENT DO THEISTS NEED TO SOLVE THE PROBLEM OF EVIL?

SUPPOSITIONAL REASONING AND PERCEPTUAL JUSTIFICATION

Augustine, On Free Choice of the Will,

THE FREGE-GEACH PROBLEM AND KALDERON S MORAL FICTIONALISM. Matti Eklund Cornell University

Philosophical Approaches to Religion

IS IT IMMORAL TO BELIEVE IN GOD?

Today we begin our discussion of the existence of God.

Transcription:

The Problem of Evil Prof. Eden Lin The Ohio State University

Where We Are You have considered some questions about the nature of God: What does it mean for God to be omnipotent? Does God s omniscience imply that we don t have free will? While these were not explicitly presented as arguments for or against the existence of God, they could perhaps be the basis for such arguments. How this might be? We will now consider a problem the problem of evil which more directly suggests an argument against the existence of God.

The Problem of Evil In its simplest form, the problem is this: God is omnipotent; God is wholly good; and yet evil exists. There seems to be some contradiction between these three propositions, so that if any two of them were true the third would be false. [T]he contradiction does not arise immediately; to show it we need some additional premises... connecting the terms good, evil, and omnipotent. These additional principles are that good is opposed to evil, in such a way that a good thing always eliminates evil as far as it can, and that there are no limits to what an omnipotent thing can do. From these it follows that a good omnipotent thing eliminates evil completely, and then the propositions that a good omnipotent thing exists, and that evil exists, are incompatible. (Mackie, p. 119)

The Problem of Evil The problem arises for those who believe all of the following claims: (i) God exists. (ii) God, if he exists, is omnipotent. (iii) God, if he exists, is wholly good. (iv) A wholly good being eliminates evil as far as it can. (v) There are no limits to what an omnipotent being can do. (vi) Evil exists. This set of claims is inconsistent. The fourth and fifth claims entail that an omnipotent, wholly good being eliminates all evil. When combined with the first three claims, this entails that all evil has been eliminated by God. This contradicts the last claim: that evil exists. The problem of evil is the problem of deciding which of these claims is false.

The Problem of Evil (i) God exists. (ii) God, if he exists, is omnipotent. (iii) God, if he exists, is wholly good. Any theist must accept (i), and any theist who conceives of God in the traditional, monotheistic way will also accept (ii) and (iii). After all, on that conception, God is by definition an omnipotent, omniscient, and perfectly good being.

The Problem of Evil (vi) Evil exists. Normally, we reserve the term evil to describe people with especially bad characters. Here, we are using it more broadly to refer to all really bad things. There are enormously many really bad things in the world: painful illnesses, deadly natural disasters, terrorist attacks, murders, evil people, etc. All such things count as evil, in our sense. So each of these things would, by itself, suffice to establish (vi).

The Problem of Evil (iv) A wholly good being eliminates evil as far as it can. This is plausible. Presumably, a good being must at least attempt to eliminate some evil: otherwise, it would not count as good. If a being is wholly or perfectly good, then it is plausible that it will eliminate as much evil as it can. Indeed, it is equally plausible that it will prevent as much evil as it can. We can strengthen this claim accordingly. (v) There are no limits to what an omnipotent being can do. Something like this is surely correct, but as it stands, this claim may be too strong. Even an omnipotent being couldn t make 2 + 2 = 5, or violate the laws of logic. To avoid this problem, we should appeal to a weaker variant on this principle: there is no limit to how much evil an omnipotent being can eliminate or prevent.

The Problem of Evil The Problem of Evil, with (iv) and (v) modified: (i) God exists. (ii) God, if he exists, is omnipotent. (iii) God, if he exists, is wholly good. (iv) A wholly good being prevents and eliminates evil as far as it can. (v) There are no limits to how much evil an omnipotent being can prevent or eliminate. (vi) Evil exists. This set of claims is inconsistent. If we were to remove any claim in the set, the resulting set would be consistent. Which claim should we reject? Many believe that (i) is the least credible claim in the set. In their view, the problem of evil suggests the following argument against the existence of God.

An Atheistic Argument from Evil (1) God, if he exists, is omnipotent. [premise] (2) God, if he exists, is wholly good. [premise] (3) A wholly good being prevents and eliminates evil as far as it can. [premise] (4) There are no limits to how much evil an omnipotent being can prevent or eliminate. [premise] (5) If a wholly good and omnipotent being exists, then there is no evil. [3, 4] (6) If God exists, then there is no evil. [1, 2, 5] (7) There is evil. [premise] (8) God does not exist. [6, 7] (3) and (4) seem like the only doubtful premises. Can you think of any objections to them?

A First Objection to (3) and/or (4) Evil is necessary as a means to good. The idea here is that bringing about evil things is the only way to bring about good things or, at least, that some good things are such that they can only be brought about by evil means. Is this a good objection to (4)? (4) There are no limits to how much evil an omnipotent being can prevent or eliminate. It seems not. Even if some good things can only be brought about by evil means, an omnipotent being could prevent or eliminate all evil by choosing not to bring about those good things. After all, an omnipotent being need not bring about any good things.

A First Objection to (3) and/or (4) Evil is necessary as a means to good. Is this a good objection to (3)? (3) A wholly good being prevents and eliminates evil as far as it can. This objection does have some potential against (3). Suppose it s true that some good things can only be brought about by evil means. Suppose that a wholly good being will always bring about those good things. Then the following will be true: although a wholly good being can prevent more evil by refraining from bringing about those good things, it won t do this. Thus, it won t prevent and eliminate evil as far as it can. But this objection to (3) has serious problems: It s not clear that a wholly good being will always bring about good things whose necessary means are evil. Why not just bring about the good things whose necessary means aren t evil? It s not clear that any good things really do have evil necessary means. There may be good things that we can t bring about except by evil means, but that s because our power is limited. That doesn t mean that these things couldn t be brought about by any being (however powerful) without evil means.

A Second Objection to (3) and/or (4) Evil is necessary as a counterpart to good. The idea here is that good and evil are essentially comparative notions (like bigger than and smaller than ), so that nothing would count as good if nothing were evil, just as nothing can be bigger than anything unless something is smaller than it. Is this a good objection to (4)? (4) There are no limits to how much evil an omnipotent being can prevent or eliminate. It seems not. Once again, an omnipotent being need not create anything good. So even if evil is a necessary counterpart to goodness, an omnipotent being could prevent or eliminate all evil by refraining from creating anything good.

A Second Objection to (3) and/or (4) Evil is necessary as a counterpart to good. Is this a good objection to (3)? (3) A wholly good being prevents and eliminates evil as far as it can. As with the previous objection, there is at least some potential here. Perhaps a wholly good being will always create something good. If evil is necessary as a counterpart to good, then a wholly good being will thereby create something evil too even though it can prevent this evil by refraining from creating anything good. Thus, a wholly good being will not prevent and eliminate as much evil as it can. But this objection has a serious problem: it is false that evil is necessary as a counterpart to good. Good and evil are not essentially comparative notions. For example, kindness, friendship, and happiness would still be good even if there were no evil.

A Third Objection to (3) The universe is better with some evil in it than it could be if there were no evil. The idea here is that there are certain good things that logically require the existence of evil things, and are more good than these things are evil. Examples may include courage in the face of deadly danger, a desire to alleviate suffering, or bringing an evildoer to justice. Is this a good objection to (3)? (3) A wholly good being prevents and eliminates evil as far as it can. Maybe. If it s true that the universe is better with some evil in it than it could be if there were no evil, then perhaps (3) is false because a wholly good being will want the universe to be as good as it can be overall, and will therefore refrain from preventing or eliminating some evil that it can prevent or eliminate.

A Third Objection to (3) Some responses to the objection: There are good things that logically require the existence of evil things (e.g., the bringing to justice of an evildoer), and it is true that these good things couldn t exist if there were no evil. But in order for the universe to be better overall on account of containing evil, these good things must be more good than the necessary evil things are evil. Is this plausible? Suppose that Smith commits a murder, and that he is then brought to justice. Is it plausible that the universe is better overall than it would be if Smith had not committed the murder? If you think that such second-order goods are better than the first-order evils that they require, then you have another problem: first-order evils make possible second-order evils (e.g., delight in someone s suffering), and these are surely as evil as the second-order goods are good. So, it is unclear that universe really is better overall on account of containing evil than it would be if it didn t contain evil.

The Free Will Defense Evil is due to human free will. The idea here is that evil cannot be eliminated unless free will is eliminated. Since it is good that humans have free will, God grants them free will even though this means that there will be some evil. This is an objection to (3): since free will is so good, and since there must be some evil if there is free will, it s false that a wholly good being prevents and eliminates evil as far as it can. Such a being refrains from preventing or eliminating evil as far as it can, because it would have to prevent or eliminate free will to do so, and a wholly good being wouldn t want to prevent or eliminate something as good as free will. This objection has its own name: the free will defense.

The Free Will Defense A response to the free will defense: It s not true that evil cannot be eliminated unless free will is eliminated. God could have created people who never do anything evil, not because they aren t free to do so, but just because they don t want to do so. (Lots of people go through life without eating insects. That doesn t mean they weren t free to do so: they could have done so if they wanted to, but they just didn t want to.) If there is no logical impossibility in a man s freely choosing the good on one, or on several occasions, there cannot be a logical impossibility in his freely choosing the good on every occasion. (Mackie, p. 124)

The Free Will Defense Van Inwagen s reply to that response: If God had ensured that no one ever does evil by ensuring that no one ever wants to do it, we would not have free will. We would be just like the lower class people in Brave New World, who do whatever they want but who only want what they ve been programmed to want. And those people don t have free will. Thus, the atheist s attempt to show that the story constitutes the free-will defense is false rests on a false theory about the nature of free will. (p. 131) Even if we can t be certain that the atheist s theory of free will is mistaken for these reasons, we should admit that it might be. So, for all we know, a wholly good being does not prevent or eliminate evil as far as it can because doing so would require preventing or eliminating free will.

The Free Will Defense A reply to Van Inwagen: What about angels? Do they lack free will because they never desire to do anything evil? Indeed, what about God himself? If theists are to be believed, then God never does anything evil, and he never desires to. Surely this doesn t mean that God lacks free will. So, just as God and angels have free will even though they never want to do anything evil, human beings could have had free will without ever wanting to do anything evil (and without ever doing any evil). Thus, the existence of free will does not require the existence of evil. Maybe the people in Brave New World have free will; there s just something else that s bad about their situation. Or maybe there is some as-yet unidentified difference that explains why they don t have free will even though God and angels do.

The Free Will Defense Another problem for the free will defense: even if it were true that free will cannot exist unless evil exists, we could run a variant on the argument against God s existence that focuses on the existence of natural evil (e.g., deadly natural disasters, natural diseases). After all, free will can exist even though natural evil doesn t exist. The argument would replace (3) with the following claim: A wholly good being prevents and eliminates natural evil as far as it can. And the rest of the argument would be modified accordingly.

An Atheistic Argument from Natural Evil (1) God, if he exists, is omnipotent. [premise] (2) God, if he exists, is wholly good. [premise] (3) A wholly good being prevents and eliminates natural evil as far as it can. [premise] (4) There are no limits to how much natural evil an omnipotent being can prevent or eliminate. [premise] (5) If a wholly good and omnipotent being exists, then there is no natural evil. [3, 4] (6) If God exists, then there is no natural evil. [1, 2, 5] (7) There is natural evil. [premise] (8) God does not exist. [6, 7]

An Atheistic Argument from Natural Evil Van Inwagen suggests an elaboration on the free-will defense that may be able to account for the existence of natural evil. He says that perhaps the following is true: When humans were first created (or first evolved), they were mystically united with God in such a way that they had paranormal abilities that protected them from natural evils (e.g., wild beasts, disease, natural disasters). But, somehow, in some way that must be mysterious to us, they were not content with this paradisal state. They abused the gift of free will and separated themselves from their union with God. The result was horrific: they now faced destruction by the random forces of nature and were subject to old age and natural death. (p. 133) God responded by setting in motion a rescue operation whose aim is to bring it about that human beings once more love God. For this to succeed, humans must know that what it is to be separated by God is to live in a world of horrors. This is why God doesn t use miracles to eliminate all evil now. (p. 134)

An Atheistic Argument from Natural Evil But even if Van Inwagen s story is true (and we have little reason to think that it is), does it answer the argument? The story assumes that when humans emerged, there already was natural evil (e.g., disease, natural disasters): it s just that humans were protected against them by the special powers they got from their mystical union with God. But why wouldn t God have already prevented all natural evil by then? If he s wholly good, why did he create a world in which there are diseases and earthquakes at all? If God just wants us to know that being separated from him is horrible, couldn t he achieve this aim simply by failing to eliminate the evil consequences of our free actions (e.g., murder, genocide, etc.)? Isn t it gratuitous for him to refrain from eliminating natural evil, which does not result in any way from free choices on our part?

An Atheistic Argument from Evil (1) God, if he exists, is omnipotent. [premise] (2) God, if he exists, is wholly good. [premise] (3) A wholly good being prevents and eliminates evil as far as it can. [premise] (4) There are no limits to how much evil an omnipotent being can prevent or eliminate. [premise] (5) If a wholly good and omnipotent being exists, then there is no evil. [3,4] (6) If God exists, then there is no evil. [1,2,5] (7) There is evil. [premise] (8) God does not exist. [6,7]

An Atheistic Argument from Natural Evil (1) God, if he exists, is omnipotent. [premise] (2) God, if he exists, is wholly good. [premise] (3) A wholly good being prevents and eliminates natural evil as far as it can. [premise] (4) There are no limits to how much natural evil an omnipotent being can prevent or eliminate. [premise] (5) If a wholly good and omnipotent being exists, then there is no natural evil. [3,4] (6) If God exists, then there is no natural evil. [1,2,5] (7) There is natural evil. [premise] (8) God does not exist. [6,7]