Philosophy 125 Day 8: Overview

Similar documents
Nominalism III: Austere Nominalism 1. Philosophy 125 Day 7: Overview. Nominalism IV: Austere Nominalism 2

Philosophy 125 Day 13: Overview

Philosophy 125 Day 4: Overview

Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview

Lecture 3: Properties II Nominalism & Reductive Realism. Lecture 3: Properties II Nominalism & Reductive Realism

Philosophy 125 Day 12: Overview

Retrospective Remarks on Events (Kim, Davidson, Quine) Philosophy 125 Day 20: Overview. The Possible & The Actual I: Intensionality of Modality 2

A Logical Approach to Metametaphysics

Nominalism. From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Michael J. Loux. Philosophical Concept

Deflationary Nominalism s Commitment to Meinongianism

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

Phil/Ling 375: Meaning and Mind [Handout #10]

Tuomas E. Tahko (University of Helsinki)

Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism

Comments on Ontological Anti-Realism

Pure Pragmatics and the Transcendence of Belief

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa

OBJECTIVITY WITHOUT THE PHILOSOPHER S SPECIAL OBJECTS: A PRIORIAN PROGRAM. James Van Cleve, University of Southern California

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

Privilege in the Construction Industry. Shamik Dasgupta Draft of February 2018

Fundamentals of Metaphysics

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Russell on Plurality

To Appear in Philosophical Studies symposium of Hartry Field s Truth and the Absence of Fact

Propositions as Cambridge properties

On possibly nonexistent propositions

Introduction: Belief vs Degrees of Belief

Philosophy 148 Announcements & Such. Inverse Probability and Bayes s Theorem II. Inverse Probability and Bayes s Theorem III

Quine: Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes

The Summa Lamberti on the Properties of Terms

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

2 Why Truthmakers GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA 1. INTRODUCTION

5 The necessary and the possible

Phil 435: Philosophy of Language. P. F. Strawson: On Referring

Analyticity and reference determiners

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Early Russell on Philosophical Grammar

Ontological Justification: From Appearance to Reality Anna-Sofia Maurin (PhD 2002)

Armstrongian Particulars with Necessary Properties

Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory.

Understanding Belief Reports. David Braun. In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection.

Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010).

Russell on Descriptions

Possibility and Necessity

Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames. sentence, or the content of a representational mental state, involves knowing which

A Nominalist s Dilemma and its Solution

Overview of Today s Lecture

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Ryle on Systematically Misleading Expresssions

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

ARMSTRONGIAN PARTICULARS WITH NECESSARY PROPERTIES *

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

On Possibly Nonexistent Propositions

REFERENCE AND MODALITY. An Introduction to Naming and Necessity

Primitive Concepts. David J. Chalmers

9.1 Intro to Predicate Logic Practice with symbolizations. Today s Lecture 3/30/10

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

Realism and instrumentalism

It turns out that there is an important class of sentences that we have so far pretty much avoided mentioning: modal sentences.

Abstract Abstraction Abundant ontology Abundant theory of universals (or properties) Actualism A-features Agent causal libertarianism

Universals. If no: Then it seems that they could not really be similar. If yes: Then properties like redness are THINGS.

Class 33 - November 13 Philosophy Friday #6: Quine and Ontological Commitment Fisher 59-69; Quine, On What There Is

Imprint. A Quinean Critique of Ostrich Nominalism. Bryan Pickel. Nicholas Mantegani. Philosophers. University of Barcelona

Realism and Idealism Internal realism

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pp. i-ix, 379. ISBN $35.00.

Russell: On Denoting

Varieties of Apriority

Tom Vinci. Dalhousie University

15 Does God have a Nature?

All philosophical debates not due to ignorance of base truths or our imperfect rationality are indeterminate.

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

Philosophy 57 Day 10

Metaphysics. A contemporary introduction. Michael J. Loux. Third edition

Evaluating Classical Identity and Its Alternatives by Tamoghna Sarkar

An Introduction to. Formal Logic. Second edition. Peter Smith, February 27, 2019

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Andrei Marmor: Social Conventions

Structural realism and metametaphysics

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

(Published in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63:3 (2001), )

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Russell s Problems of Philosophy

1 ReplytoMcGinnLong 21 December 2010 Language and Society: Reply to McGinn. In his review of my book, Making the Social World: The Structure of Human

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Theoretical Virtues in Science

5: Preliminaries to the Argument

How to Handle Relationship Rifts Philippians 4:2-3. Pastor Troy Dobbs Grace Church of Eden Prairie. November 8, 2015

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

Language, Meaning, and Information: A Case Study on the Path from Philosophy to Science Scott Soames

A. Problem set #3 it has been posted and is due Tuesday, 15 November

This paper is about avoiding commitment to an ontology of possible worlds with two primitives:

On Truth At Jeffrey C. King Rutgers University

CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC

Primary and Secondary Qualities. John Locke s distinction between primary and secondary qualities of bodies has

Why are Events, Facts, and States of Affairs Different?

Philosophy 57 Day 10. Chapter 4: Categorical Statements Conversion, Obversion & Contraposition II

Transcription:

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 1 Trope Theory Y yellow[0pt]c Philosophy 125 Day 8: Overview Administrative Stuff First Paper Topics and S.Q.s announced today (see email & website) Three study questions (do all) Five paper topics (choose one) Both due four weeks hence (10/16/03) Josh s Handout on Regresses (see homepage for link) Philosophy Colloquium Today (4pm, Howison Library, 3rd Floor Moses): Intelligent Design is Untestable. What about Natural Selection? Elliott Sober, Stanford University, Philosophy Department Guest Lecture next Thursday: Ed Zalta on Nonexistent/Abstract Objects Agenda: Nominalism A Few More Remarks on Austere Nominalism & on Quine Metalingusitc Nominalism Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 3 Nominalism XIII: A Puzzle Concerning Nominalistic Discourse 6 Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 2 A Few Remarks on Austere Nominalism (On a Nice Suggestion Made Last Time) We have seen the following paraphrase strategies for the Austere Nominalist: (1) Courage is a virtue. Ceteris paribus, courageous persons are virtuous. (2) John s eyes are the same color as his hair. John s eyes and John s hair agree color-wise. A nice suggestion was made last time by a student in lecture. Why not think of (2) as a case of attribute agreement, and then (as Quine suggests) take the agreement as explanatorily primitive (i.e., say no paraphrase is needed)? The only difference (assuming John s Hair and John s eyes are indeed particulars, which seems OK) between (2) and standard AA cases seems to be that the color in question is not specified in (2). But, why should that matter? Turn this on its head: Why not account for attribute agreement using adverbial expressions? I.e., a... n are each F a... n agree F-wise. Taking this to its extreme: Why not think of (1) as a case of attribute agreement? Ceteris paribus, courageous persons agree virtue-wise. Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 4 Nominalism XIV: A Puzzle Concerning Nominalistic Discourse 7 Abstract Reference: What would Quine say about Courage is a virtue? Descriptionizing gives: The thing which is-courage is a virtue. But, on Quine s account, this becomes Something uniquely couragizes, and that thing is a virtue, which is false for a Courage-nominalist. But, courage is a virtue! This seems to make it impossible for a Courage-nominalist to affirm claims like Courage is a virtue, which seem to express truths about courage. Other versions of nominalism (metalinguistic, austere) allow the Courage-nominalist to affirm the (intuitively true) claim Courage is a virtue. Quine talks about abstract reference elsewhere, and he suggests (where possible) the paraphrase strategies (above) adopted by austere nominalism. For (Q2), Quine goes meta-linguistic: nominalists can t (consistently) say There are things the realist has in his ontology but I do not ; they can talk about the realist s sentences & what to do with them (i.e., debate their usage). Quine s view seems to be that one s ontological commitments are determined by the ineliminable bound variable expressions in one s best theory of the world i.e., the entities (ineliminably) quantified over in one s best theory. We may say... that some dogs are white and not thereby commit ourselves to recognizing either doghood or whiteness as entities. Some dogs are white says that some things that are dogs are white; and, in order that this statement be true, the things over which the bound variable something ranges must include some white dogs, but need not include doghood or whiteness. On the other hand, when we say that some zoological species are cross-fertile we are committing ourselves to recognizing as entities the several species themselves, abstract though they are. We remain so committed at least until we devise some way of so paraphrasing the statement as to show that the seeming reference to species on the part of our bound variable was an avoidable manner of speaking. Quine says classical mathematics is committed to various abstract entities (e.g., sets), and he says science is too (sets are indispensible to best science).

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 5 Nominalism XV: Epilogue on Quine Let us by all means see how much of the physicalistic conceptual scheme can be reduced to a phenomenalistic one... physics also... demands pursuing, irreducible in toto though it be. Let us see... to what degree, natural science may be rendered independent of platonistic mathematics; but let us also pursue mathematics and... its platonistic foundations. Here, Quine hints that realism about some physical universals (e.g., species) and some mathematical universals (e.g., sets) may be ineliminable. Provided merely that [the nominalist s] ontology countenances linguistic forms, or at least concrete inscriptions and utterances, [she] can talk about [the realist s] sentences. Here, Quine suggests that the nominalist go meta-linguistic in their reconstruction (or paraphrase ) of realist discourse. Interesting. More? BUT... we must not jump to the conclusion that what there is depends on words. Translatability of a question into semantical terms is no indication that the question is linguistic. Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 6 Here, Quine clearly says that ontological debates are not about language (even if we can reconstruct the discourse semantically). But, it s not clear they are about matters of fact either. They re about which overall scientific theory of the world is best given our interests, and what that theory quantifies over. Ontological questions, under this view, are on a par with questions in natural science. consider the question whether to countenance classes as entities. This, as I have argued elsewhere [in On What There Is ], is the question whether to quantify with respect to variables which take classes as values. Now Carnap has maintained that this is a question not of matters of fact but of choosing a convenient language form, a convenient conceptual scheme or framework for science. With this I agree, but only on the proviso that the same be conceded regarding hypotheses generally. Carnap has... preserve[d] a double standard for ontological questions and scientific hypotheses... which I reject.... I espouse a more thorough pragmatism. Each man is given a scientific heritage plus a continuing barrage of sensory stimulation; and the considerations which guide him in warping his scientific heritage to fit his continuing sensory promptings are, where rational, pragmatic. What are the consequences of this view? Is there really disagreement here? Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 7 Nominalism XVI: Metalinguistic Nominalism 1 Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 8 Nominalism XVII: Metalinguistic Nominalism 2 Metalinguistic nominalism has only recently been carefully worked out (20th centuty: Carnap and Sellars), but its roots are in medieval philosophy, in the work of Roscelin, Abelard, and William of Ockahm. Roscelin (1050 1125): talk about universals is really talk about those linguistic expressions that can be predicatively ascribed to many individuals. a And, linguistic expressions are physical vocalizations (mere breaths of air). Abelard (1079 1142): universals are meaningful linguistic expressions (not mere vocalizations). The challenge is to explain how predicable expressions can be meaningful in the absence of multiply exemplifiable entities. William of Ockham (1285 1349): Abelard is right, but the meaningfulness of written or spoken language requires an inner language of the soul/thought. All agree that the notion of universality itself is to be explained in terms of the linguistic activity of predication (this turns realism s scheme on its head!). a Only names that are general terms (nomina) can have universality the origin of nominalism. Metalinguistic nominalists think that realists and austere nominalists make the same kind of mistake: thinking that there must be some non-lingusitic entities to which terms like courage (in, e.g., Courage is a virtue ) refer. For realists, these entities are universals, for austere nominalists, the entities are concrete particulars (e.g., courageous persons). The metalingustic nominalist thinks both the realist and the austere nominalist are incorrect. Carnap sketches how a systematic and precise metalinguistic nominalistic theory might be worked out. Carnap proposes (roughly) that claims like Courage is a virtue get unpacked as claims about predicates in languages: Courage is a virtue Courageous is a virtue predicate. Trangularity is a shape Triangular is a shape predicate. Problems: (1) Linguistic types vs linguistic tokens (trading new universals for old ones?), (2) Language relativity (abs. claims don t seem language relative).

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 9 Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 10 Nominalism XVIII: Metalinguistic Nominalism 3 Nominalism XIX: Metalinguistic Nominalism 4 Object Language: quantifies over non-linguistic entities (particulars for the nominalist + universals for the realist). E.g., Socrates is courageous. Metalanguage: quantifies over linguistic entities (letters, words, sentences, predicates, etc.). E.g., Socrates is courageous is true. Linguistic Type: A linguistic form, instantiated by its tokens. E.g., the fifth letter of the English alphabet, of which E, E, E, etc. are all instances. Linguistic Token: A particular inscription, which instantiates a linguistic type. E.g., E, which is an instance of the fifth letter of the English alphabet. Intuitively, Courageous is a virtue predicate is not about the token inscription on its left hand side. It s about all tokens of the type Courageous. So, Carnap s approach seems to require linguistic types, which are themselves universals. But, he has eliminated almost all universals, and these types are not unexemplifed universals (indeed, they seem necessarily exemplified!). Sellars addresses this first problem (for nominalism) of linguistic types/tokens by introducing distributive singular terms. Here s an object language example: The lion is tawny. Sellars: a distributive singular term The K, K a proper noun appears to be a name of some abstract entity (the universal K), but is just a device for indicating that a general claim is being made about the various individual Ks. Argument: The lion is tawny is true, but it would be false if were to take The lion to denote an abstract entity, since abstract entities cannot exemplify colors [Zalta has an answer to this: exemplification vs. encoding]. This gives us a common noun use of metalinguistic expressions, as in Courageous is a virtue predicate Courageous s are virtue predicates. This is not as crazy as it may sound. We say things like: How many man s are there on page 100 of the text? Such common noun ML usage exists. Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 11 Nominalism XX: Metalinguistic Nominalism 5 Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 12 Nominalism XXI: Metalinguistic Nominalism 6 To address problem (2), Sellars introduces what he calls dot-quotation. Regular quotation marks pick-out expressions in particular languages. For instance, man picks out a word in English (either a type or its tokens). So, if we stick with regular quotation, we will end-up with language relative paraphrases of abstract referring sentences. But, this seems wrong. There seems to be something more general and language invariant going on here. Intuitively, the various ways of saying courageous in various languages (e.g., courageux, valiente ) are all just different ways of saying the same thing. That courage is a virtue is not relative to the language in which it is expressed. What we need is a way to pick-out expressions with the same functional behavior (same inferential role, same role in guiding behavior, etc.) across different languages. Sellars s dot notation is intended to do just that. Courageous s are virtue predicates Courageous s are virtue predicates Courageous s are virtue predicates says (in our English metalanguage) all words that are functionally equivalent (in their respective languages) to the English word courageous are virtue predicates (in their respective langs). Applying this idea, hombre, uomo, homme, and Mensch are all man s and rojo, rosso, rot, and rouge are all red s. Dot quotation provides us with the materials for metalinguistic discourse that cuts across languages. For instance, consider the following two sentences: (i) Red is a color. (i ) Rojo es un color. On Carnap s account, claims (i) and (i ) are about different things. For Carnap, (i) is about the English word Red, and (i ) is about the Spanish word Rojo. Accordingly, what the speaker of English says when assertively uttering (i) is precisely what the speaker of Spanish say when they assertively utter (i ).

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 13 Nominalism XXII: Metalinguistic Nominalism 7 Sellars theory (which includes a rich theory of metalinguistic quantification) can handle tricky sentences like Those species are cross-fertile. Indeed, Sellars account of abstract reference is very systematic, highly unified, and not ad hoc. It does require metalinguistic pronouns (primitives?). Two Criticisms of Sellars Theory (from Loux): 1. Some sentences seem to resist analysis in Sellars framework. E.g., The attribute most frequently ascribed to Socrates is a property. * Can t say: the attribute most frequently ascribed to Socrates s are adjectives, since they are noun phrases not adjectives. * Try Some dot quoted expression wise is the one most frequently predicated of Socrates, and that expression is an adjective. * What if wisdom is the attribute most frequently ascribed to Socrates, but some dot quoted expression that is not an adjective, say man, has been predicated of Socrates more frequently than any other? Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 14 * Problem: there are more ways of ascribing wisdom to Socrates than by predicating a wise of him. E.g., Socrates has the property that Quine is now thinking of. Sellarsizing this requires lots of sophistication. 2. Isn t Sellars just sneaking universals in the back door here? E.g., He talks anout linguistic roles, and functional equivalence, etc. * How are we to make sense out of such talk, nominalistically? * Sellars: linguistic roles can be analyzed by reference to linguistic rules and, the notion of a linguistic rule can be understood without reference to anything other than concrete particulars (i.e., persons). * So, we don t even need linguistic tokens, much less types! We can do everything in terms of linguistic rules, which are themselves reducible to talk only about persons using language (a là Quine). * Realist Retort: to give a satisfactory account of linguistic rules, we ll need to introduce talk about norms and standards; and such talk cannot be understood without reference to the ontology of realism. Interestingly, Loux does not claim that Sellars explanatory apparatus more complex than the realist s. Question: How do they compare on this score? Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 15 Nominalism XXII: Trope Theory 1 Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 16 Nominalism XXIII: Trope Theory 2 So far, the nominalists we have seen believe that there are only concrete particulars no properties or attributes of things, just the things themselves. Trope theorists are different. They believe that there are attributes as well as concrete particulars. But, they do not posit a separate ontological category for such things. According to trope theorists, these, too, are just particulars. Trope theorists think it is impossible for numerically distinct things to have numerically one and the same attribute (1st horn of Parmenides dilemma). Thus, a particular red ball has a color, but it is a color nothing else has or could have. It has a certain shape, but it is a shape nothing else has or could have. These shares of properties are called tropes. Examples: Socrates courage. Hercules strength. What about attribute agreement? It appears that things can share attributes. I.e., it seems that distinct particulars can both have one and the same attribute. According to trope theorists, this is loose talk. When we say things like this we are really just talking about exact similarity between distinct attributes. So, John and Jim are each white gets unpacked as John s whiteness is exactly similar to Jim s whiteness (both understood to be particulars). As Williams puts it: They do not have the same color in the sense in which two children have the same father or two streets have the same manhole in the middle of their intersections or two college students wear the same tuxedo (and so can t go to dances together). So attribute agreement is explained by trope theorists in terms of exact similarity between numerically distinct particulars (tropes). What is the motivation for trope theory (aside from Parmenides dilemma)?

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 17 Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 18 Nominalism XXIV: Trope Theory 3 Trope theorists appeal to considerations of selective attention to motivate their theory. When we experience particulars, we experience them in terms of their colors, shapes, etc., and not in terms of these attributes in a generic sense. For instance, when I focus on the color of the Taj Mahal, I am not experiencing pinkness generally, I am attending to the Taj Mahal s pinkness. In this way, the trope theorist can satisfy the realist s preference for the posit of a mind-independent thing in virture of which the Taj Mahal is pink. Moreover, the trope theorist s entity is something with which we are directly acquainted via experience of concrete particulars [no uninstantiated tropes!]. The trope theorist seems to enjoy all the benefits of realism, without its ontological commitment to universals, and with many of the epistemic advantages and the parsimoniousness of metaliguistic nominalism. But, how do they handle those pesky case of abstract reference? Nominalism XXV: Trope Theory 4 There are two main trope-theory approaches to abstract reference: 1. Medieval: Try to eliminate abstract singular terms as mere seeming names, by paraphrasing abstract claims into claims about tropes. E.g., Courage is a virtue becomes Courages (courage tropes) are virtues (virtue tropes). Similar to the eliminativist account of the austere nominalist, but it seems to have its advantages (Does it need CP clauses or adverbials?). Does seem to need similarity as an explanatory primitive. 2. Contemporary: Accept that abstract singular terms are genuine names. But, then, we need to say what the denotation of such terms is. The standard approach is that abstract singular terms denote sets of tropes. E.g., Courage denotes the set of courage tropes C and Virtue denotes the set of virtue tropes V. And, Courage is a virtue C V. Set theory is pretty powerful, and seems to come with ontological commitments decidedly non-nominalist. Need the relation?