World View, Metaphysics, and Epistemology

Similar documents
Worldview Theory and Conceptual Change in Science Education

Education Research Will Not Profit From Radical Constructivism

Objectivism and Education: A Response to David Elkind s The Problem with Constructivism

The Human Science Debate: Positivist, Anti-Positivist, and Postpositivist Inquiry. By Rebecca Joy Norlander. November 20, 2007

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

ELEMENTS OF LOGIC. 1.1 What is Logic? Arguments and Propositions

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Areas of Specialization and Competence Philosophy of Language, History of Analytic Philosophy

Craig on the Experience of Tense

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence

On the hard problem of consciousness: Why is physics not enough?

ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

POLI 343 Introduction to Political Research

A Review of Norm Geisler's Prolegomena

It s time to stop believing scientists about evolution

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Between the Actual and the Trivial World

The ontology of human rights and obligations

Zurich Open Repository and Archive

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

The Question of Metaphysics

Holtzman Spring Philosophy and the Integration of Knowledge

Introduction to Philosophy. Daniel von Wachter

Research Methods. Selecting a topic.

6 February Dr. Cindy Ausec

Institute of Social Sciences Regional Centre Puducherry. A Brief Report of the

Introducing Our New Faculty

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT

RECENT WORK THE MINIMAL DEFINITION AND METHODOLOGY OF COMPARATIVE PHILOSOPHY: A REPORT FROM A CONFERENCE STEPHEN C. ANGLE

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

PHILOSOPHY (413) Chairperson: David Braden-Johnson, Ph.D.

A Logical Approach to Metametaphysics

Leonard F. Jacuzzo 316 W. Utica Buffalo, NY, (716)

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Computer Ethics. Normative Ethics and Normative Argumentation. Viola Schiaffonati October 10 th 2017

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

EXISTENTIALISM EXISTENTIALISM - METAPHYSICS EXISTENTIALISM - METAPHYSICS

Philosophica 67 (2001, 1) pp. 5-9 INTRODUCTION

Philosophy 780: After Empiricism: Experience and Reality in Kant, Hegel, and Sellars

A Wesleyan Approach to Knowledge

IDHEF Chapter 2 Why Should Anyone Believe Anything At All?

Full file at

Epistemology Naturalized

Important dates. PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since David Hume ( )

The linguistic-cultural nature of scientific truth 1

Lessons of Jung's Encounter with Native Americans

THEOLOGICAL METHOD AND INERRANCY: A REPLY TO PROFESSOR HOLMES

Of All Professions, Prostitution is the Oldest (Except Possibly for Teaching)

THE HISTORIC ALLIANCE OF CHRISTIANITY AND SCIENCE

Lifelong Learning Is a Moral Imperative

SOCIAL CONSTRUCTIVISM AS A PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS: RADICAL CONSTRUCTIVISM REHABILITATED? Paul Ernest University of Exeter

Keywords: Knowledge Organization. Discourse Community. Dimension of Knowledge. 1 What is epistemology in knowledge organization?

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

PROSPECTIVE TEACHERS UNDERSTANDING OF PROOF: WHAT IF THE TRUTH SET OF AN OPEN SENTENCE IS BROADER THAN THAT COVERED BY THE PROOF?

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Review of Who Rules in Science?, by James Robert Brown

Naturalism and is Opponents

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

ONTOLOGICAL PROBLEMS OF PLURALIST RESEARCH METHODOLOGIES

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

Truth and Evidence in Validity Theory

Teachur Philosophy Degree 2018

THE REFUTATION OF PHENOMENALISM

Epistemic Utility and Theory-Choice in Science: Comments on Hempel

Logic and Artificial Intelligence Lecture 26

PHIL 445 / PHIL 510B / AAAS 482P: Buddhist Metaphysics Fall 2017

The deepest and most formidable presentation to date of the reductionist interpretation

Courses providing assessment data PHL 202. Semester/Year

Writing Module Three: Five Essential Parts of Argument Cain Project (2008)

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

Rationalist-Irrationalist Dialectic in Buddhism:

The Nature of Enquiry

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

Proof in mathematics education: research, learning and teaching

CURRICULUM VITAE STEPHEN JACOBSON. (Title: What's Wrong With Reliability Theories of Justification?)

SEMINAR ON NINETEENTH CENTURY THEOLOGY

VIEWING MATHEMATICS TEACHERS BELIEFS AS SENSIBLE SYSTEMS*

The Advancement: A Book Review

King and Kitchener Packet 3 King and Kitchener: The Reflective Judgment Model

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp.

On the Rationality of Metaphysical Commitments in Immature Science

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Phil/Ling 375: Meaning and Mind [Handout #10]

Physics Faculty Publications and Presentations

TRUTH IN MATHEMATICS. H.G. Dales and G. Oliveri (eds.) (Clarendon: Oxford. 1998, pp. xv, 376, ISBN X) Reviewed by Mark Colyvan

Critical Thinking: Present, Past and Future 5 April, 2015

Transcription:

Western Michigan University ScholarWorks at WMU Scientific Literacy and Cultural Studies Project Mallinson Institute for Science Education 1993 World View, Metaphysics, and Epistemology William W. Cobern Western Michigan University, bill.cobern@wmich.edu Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarworks.wmich.edu/science_slcsp Part of the Science and Mathematics Education Commons WMU ScholarWorks Citation Cobern, William W., "World View, Metaphysics, and Epistemology" (1993). Scientific Literacy and Cultural Studies Project. 7. http://scholarworks.wmich.edu/science_slcsp/7 This Presentation is brought to you for free and open access by the Mallinson Institute for Science Education at ScholarWorks at WMU. It has been accepted for inclusion in Scientific Literacy and Cultural Studies Project by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks at WMU. For more information, please contact maira.bundza@wmich.edu.

Page 1 of 10 World View, Metaphysics, and Epistemology A paper presented at the 1993 annual meeting of the National Association for Research in Science Teaching. Scientific Literacy and Cultural Studies Project Working Paper No. 106 William W. Cobern, Ph.D. Associate Professor of Science Education Arizona State University West Phoenix, Arizona 85069-7100 602/543-6334 E-Mail: ICWWC@ASUACAD.Bitnet NOTE: Bill Cobern s current address is bill.cobern@wmich.edu. In this paper, I used the convention world view. Since writing this paper, I have changed to worldview, which I consider to be more consistent with the original German from which the concept is taken.

Page 1 of 10 Abstract WORLD VIEW, METAPHYSICS, AND EPISTEMOLOGY William W. Cobern, Arizona State University West It has been argued from world view theory that fundamental beliefs about the world exert a powerful influence on how sense is made of events in the world. However, the nature of that influence has remained enigmatic. Hannah Arendt's distinction between thinking and comprehension, and knowing and apprehension provides a clarification. Thinking is the epistemological path to conceptual comprehension. Knowing is the metaphysical path to apprehension - to the acceptance of a concept as true or valid. Comprehension does not necessitate apprehension. One may reject a fully understood concept. The recent discussion in science education about world view is essentially a discussion about metaphysics. The importance to educational practice is this. Science educators are often at a loss to understand why some students fail to develop orthodox scientific conceptions even after the best of instruction. The argument from world view is that in some cases, it is not that the students fail to understand what is being taught (comprehension). They simply do not believe (apprehension). There are, thus, occasions when the careful epistemological explication of a concept is not sufficient to bring about learning. Instruction must also include a discussion of the metaphysical foundations that support epistemology.

Page 2 of 10 Introduction In other papers on world view theory (1991; 1993; in press), I have argued the importance of fundamental beliefs with respect to learning science and the development of scientific attitudes. The argument is both intuitively and rationally strong that fundamental beliefs about the world exert a powerful influence on how sense is made of events in the world. However, the nature of that influence has remained enigmatic, thus limiting the application of world view theory to educational practice. Hannah Arendt's (1978) distinction between thinking and comprehension, on the one hand, and knowing and apprehension on the other, provides the basis of a possible clarification. In this presentation, I will briefly discuss how the linkage between world view (the level of metaphysics) and conceptual change (the level of epistemology) can be developed from Arendt's work on metaphysics and epistemology. I am not so naive as to think that this will settle the linkage issue once and for all. I claim only to be making a thoughtful contribution to the discussion. The Problem The 1991 NARST monograph on world view theory (Cobern, 1991) provided a much needed clarification of the concept of world view. The monograph contributed to the discussion on how culture relates to science learning (e.g., Gallard, 1992). It provided a theoretical framework from which researchers can derive questions for study (Cobern, in press; Lassiter, 1992). The monograph, however, did not offer an adequate explication of the linkage between world view and conceptual change. Figures 1 and 2 illustrate a general relationship between world view and conceptual levels of thought (Figures 1-3 are from the monograph). Figure 1 is Gowen's Knowledge Vee which Novak has successfully used to show that epistemology has levels, the most general of which is world view. The purpose of Figure 2 is to emphasize the role world view has as a foundation for epistemology, whether it is the epistemology of informal commonsense or of formal scientific thinking. Figure 3 is an attempt to show more specifically the relationship between the alternative conceptions and misconceptions of science, and world view. The thrust is that a scientifically invalid conception can be valid on other grounds. The critical factor is how one chooses to make sense of the world. But, the question remains, "what do the lines connecting world view with the conceptual level of thought actually mean?" Moreover, and since research is supposed to support the improvement of science education (Yeany, 1992), what can this vague connection mean for the classroom practitioner? Seeking to offer further clarification, I borrowed Berger's (1979) notion of "plausibility structure," that is, a world view is what makes things plausible to a person (see Cobern, 1991, pp. 113-116). However, this too is an insufficiently answer. After all, what does it mean - in practical terms - to make something plausible? We must know more about the nature of the working relationship between world view and scientific knowledge (or for that matter, any knowledge) if we are to realize the full potential of world view theory.

Page 3 of 10 The Solution Science educators have long assumed that the case for the importance and validity of scientific knowledge was prima facie. This assumption rested on the philosophy of logical positivism which essentially claimed that only scientific knowledge was true knowledge. Smolicz & Nunan (1975) refered to this as the mythology of school science. Nevertheless, virtually all science teachers have had the unsettling experience of explaining a scientific concept with great care and skill only to have a student dismiss the concept virtually out of hand. At best, the positivist science teacher reacted by saying there must be yet a better way to teach the concept. At worst, the teacher assumed the student was either very foolish or had been indoctrinated by purveyors of anti-science. After all, the teacher is presenting

Page 4 of 10

Page 5 of 10

Page 6 of 10 scientific facts. The community of science educators is now painfully aware of how very few laypeople ever accepted the positivistic faith. In recent years, constructivist thought has elbowed aside positivism. A consistent constructivist teacher cannot react in the same way to the recalcitrant learner. The constructivist teacher knows that all knowledge entails ambiguity. There are no unambiguous facts. There are no determined theories. So, if scientific concepts do not have an inherent certainty, the consistent constructivist must eventually ask what are the principles on which validity or truth is decided. Some constructivists eschew metaphysical questions (von Glasersfeld, 1989). In doing so they show themselves to be trivial constructivists because they do not follow the constructivist argument to its natural conclusion - why do we believe what we do? Constructivism has resurrected the ancient idea that knowledge is valid or true belief, and it is with this idea that we can begin to understand how world view directly influences conceptual development and change. Hannah Arendt (1978) noted that an argument can be rationally flawless. The interpretation of data can be epistemologically perfect. And yet, some will reject the conclusions. The reason, she argued, is the fundamental difference between thinking and knowing (see Figure 4). Thinking is necessary for knowledge, but not sufficient. Thinking is the epistemological process by which one comes to conceptual comprehension. Knowing is the metaphysical process by which one comes to apprehend, that is to accept as true or valid, that concept one has come to comprehend. However, comprehension does to necessitate apprehension. One may well reject a concept that is fully understood. Moreover, in many situations the metaphysical process occurs reflexively. In philosophy, metaphysical debate has long been out of fashion, but in education, the recent discussion about world view is essentially a discussion about metaphysics. Science educators need not be at a loss to understand why some students fail to develop orthodox scientific conceptions even after the best of instruction. The argument from world view is that in some cases, it is not that the students fail to comprehend what is being taught - it is that they simply do not believe it. Therefore, there are occasions when the careful epistemological explication of a concept is not sufficient to bring about learning. The instruction must also include a discussion of the metaphysical foundations that support the epistemology. Significance Once again scientific literacy is at the forefront of national discussions on education. Project 2061 is about scientific literacy. It and other reform movements are a response to international studies showing science education in the USA lagging behind other countries. However, as Olson recently noted,

Page 7 of 10

Page 1 of 10 those studies are not measuring literacy - they are measuring retention of pieces of scientific information whose utility is questionable. What we have to ask... is what we mean by literacy? [Rather], scientific literacy must mean the same as literacy itself: getting around in the world, making meaning, and deciding how to act. The science you learn has to work in situations of ambiguity, value conflict, change, corporate manipulation, and distraction. It is a tough world out there as they say. (1992, p. 7) Olson is supported by a recent study showing that after completing several college science courses, many of the students still had not integrated scientific knowledge into their views of what the natural world is really like (Cobern, in press). An adequate theory of world view gets one beyond simplistic views of scientific literacy. It gets the profession beyond the bureaucratic and social engineering ethos that says successful science teaching is a matter of having the right techniques. Technique can show an argument to be reasonable. It cannot convince anyone that the conclusion is plausible or meaningful. I concur with Lythcott (1991, p. 47, emphasis added), "In negotiating meaning a science teacher weights the conversation toward listening to the learners and enabling them to find their voices." As of now we have only poorly formed ideas of what these issues of world view and metaphysics mean for classroom practice. However, the theoretical work implies that for the majority of students, if they are not allowed to do metaphysics there appears to be little chance that long term conceptual change will take place. Students will learn for the exam, but in the long run they will revert to what makes sense to them - which, as we know, is not science. References AAAS (1989). Project 2061: Science for All Americans. Washington, DC: American Association for the Advancement of Science. Arendt, H. (1978). The life of the mind. New York, NY: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich. Berger, P. L. (1979). The heretical imperative: contemporary possibilities of religious affirmation. Garden City, NY: Anchor Press. Cobern, W. W. (1991). World view theory and science education research, NARST Monograph No. 3. Manhattan, KS: National Association for Research in Science Teaching. Cobern, W. W. (1993). Contextual constructivism: The impact of culture on the learning and teaching of science. In K. G. Tobin (editor), Constructivist perspectives on science and mathematics education, Washington, DC: American Association for the Advancement of Science. Cobern, W. W. (in press). College students' conceptualizations of nature: an interpretive world view

Page 2 of 10 analysis. Journal of the National Association for Research in Science Teaching. Gallard, A. J. (1992). Creating a multicultural learning environment in science classrooms. NARST NEWS, 34(14), 7-9. Hawkins, D. (1978). Critical barriers to science learning. Outlook, 3, 3-25. Hills, G. L. C. (1989). Students' "untutored" beliefs about natural phenomena: primitive science or commonsense? Science Education, 73(2), 155-186. Hills, G. L. C., & McAndrews, B. (1987). David Hawkins, critical barriers and the education of elementary school science teachers. In J. D. Novak (editor), Proceedings of the second international seminar on misconceptions in science and mathematics,ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Kearney, M. (1984). World view. Novato, CA: Chandler & Sharp Publishers, Inc. Lassiter, I. (1992). Ways of knowing among college nonscience majors: a world view analysis. Unpublished doctoral dissertation perspectice, The Georgia State University, Atlanta, GA. Lythcott, J. (1991). The nature of essential knowledge bases for science teachers. Teaching Education, 3(2), 41-55. McKenzie, L. (1987). Worldview construction and adult education. Adult Education Quarterly, 37(4), 230-236. Olson, J. (1992). Science goes for a check-up: an ironical diagnosis. SMKCC/SIG Newsletter, (17), 6-8. Smolicz, J. J., & Nunan, E. E. (1975). The philosophical and sociological foundations of science education: the demythologizing of school science. Studies in Science Education, 2, 101-143. Solomon, J. (1989). The Social Construction of School Science. In R. Millar (editor), Doing Science: Images of Science in Science Education, (pp. 126-136). Philadelphia, PA: The Falmer Press. Solomon, J. (1987). Social influences on the construction of pupils' understanding of science. Studies in Science Education, 14, 63-82. von Glasersfeld, E. (1989). Knowing Without Metaphysics: Aspects of the Radical Constructivist Position. ERIC #304 344. Yeany, R. H. (1991). Dissemination and implementation of research findings: impacting practice. NARST NEWS, 33(4), 1.