METHODENSTREIT WHY CARL MENGER WAS, AND IS, RIGHT

Similar documents
145 Philosophy of Science

The Human Science Debate: Positivist, Anti-Positivist, and Postpositivist Inquiry. By Rebecca Joy Norlander. November 20, 2007

Understanding How we Come to Experience Purposive. Behavior. Jacob Roundtree. Colby College Mayflower Hill, Waterville, ME USA

PHI2391: Logical Empiricism I 8.0

1/9. The First Analogy

Logic, Truth & Epistemology. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Reason Papers. Steven Yates, Center for Economic Personalism, The Acton Institute, Grand Rapids, MI 49503

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

Revista Economică 66:3 (2014) THE USE OF INDUCTIVE, DEDUCTIVE OR ABDUCTIVE RESONING IN ECONOMICS

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Revision Guide (all topics)

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

PHILOSOPHICAL RAMIFICATIONS: THEORY, EXPERIMENT, & EMPIRICAL TRUTH

Key definitions Action Ad hominem argument Analytic A priori Axiom Bayes s theorem

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

PHIL 155: The Scientific Method, Part 1: Naïve Inductivism. January 14, 2013

Sydenham College of Commerce & Economics. * Dr. Sunil S. Shete. * Associate Professor

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

HAYEK AND THE DEPARTURE FROM PRAXEOLOGY

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

Ilija Barukčić Causality. New Statistical Methods. ISBN X Discussion with the reader.

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Immanuel Kant and the scientific method of economics

Epistemology. Diogenes: Master Cynic. The Ancient Greek Skeptics 4/6/2011. But is it really possible to claim knowledge of anything?

5: Preliminaries to the Argument

In Defense of Extreme Rationalism: Thoughts on Donald McCloskey's The Rhetoric of Economics

Excerpt from J. Garvey, The Twenty Greatest Philosophy Books (Continuum, 2007): Immanuel Kant s Critique of Pure Reason

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

In his celebrated article Toward a Reconstruction of Utility and Welfare Economics,

Business Research: Principles and Processes MGMT6791 Workshop 1A: The Nature of Research & Scientific Method

1/12. The A Paralogisms

WHY SHOULD ANYONE BELIEVE ANYTHING AT ALL?

IDHEF Chapter 2 Why Should Anyone Believe Anything At All?

Peace, Prosperity & Freedom

WHAT IS HUME S FORK? Certainty does not exist in science.

Chapter Summaries: Introduction to Christian Philosophy by Clark, Chapter 1

Module 1: Science as Culture Demarcation, Autonomy and Cognitive Authority of Science

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES

THE CRISIS OF THE SCmNCES AS EXPRESSION OF THE RADICAL LIFE-CRISIS OF EUROPEAN HUMANITY

Arguing with Libertarianism without Argument : Critical Rationalism and how it applies to Libertarianism

PHILOSOPHIES OF SCIENTIFIC TESTING

Philosophy 3100: Ethical Theory

Kant & Transcendental Idealism

William James described pragmatism as a method of approaching

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

THE ROLE OF APRIORI, EMPIRICAL, ANALYTIC AND SYNTHETIC IN PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS.

CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC

Is Innate Foreknowledge Possible to a Temporal God?

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

The CopernicanRevolution

Falsification or Confirmation: From Logic to Psychology

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Ch V: The Vienna Circle (Moritz Schlick, Rudolf Carnap, and Otto Neurath)[title crossed out?]

The Coherence of Kant s Synthetic A Priori

The Construction of Empirical Concepts and the Establishment of the Real Possibility of Empirical Lawlikeness in Kant's Philosophy of Science

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

Unit. Science and Hypothesis. Downloaded from Downloaded from Why Hypothesis? What is a Hypothesis?

Scientific Method and Research Ethics

A Critique of Friedman s Critics Lawrence A. Boland

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism

Thursday, November 30, 17. Hegel s Idealism

Introduction to Philosophy PHL 221, York College Revised, Spring 2017

Aristotle, Menger, Mises: An Essay in the Metaphysics of Economics

Rationalist-Irrationalist Dialectic in Buddhism:

Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010).

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 7 : E P I S T E M O L O G Y - K A N T

ECONOMETRIC METHODOLOGY AND THE STATUS OF ECONOMICS. Cormac O Dea. Junior Sophister

Tuesday, November 11, Hegel s Idealism

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

Hoong Juan Ru. St Joseph s Institution International. Candidate Number Date: April 25, Theory of Knowledge Essay

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

Chapter Summaries: Three Types of Religious Philosophy by Clark, Chapter 1

Kant s Misrepresentations of Hume s Philosophy of Mathematics in the Prolegomena

1/9. The Second Analogy (1)

The British Empiricism

Kant and his Successors

Hume. Hume the Empiricist. Judgments about the World. Impressions as Content of the Mind. The Problem of Induction & Knowledge of the External World

HISTORY AND TRUTH: A STUDY OF THE AXIOM OF LESSING

Toward an A Priori Theory of International Relations Mark R. Crovelli

INVESTIGATING THE PRESUPPOSITIONAL REALM OF BIBLICAL-THEOLOGICAL METHODOLOGY, PART II: CANALE ON REASON

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins

Kant Lecture 4 Review Synthetic a priori knowledge

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

THE RELATION BETWEEN THE GENERAL MAXIM OF CAUSALITY AND THE PRINCIPLE OF UNIFORMITY IN HUME S THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE

An Epistemological Assessment of Moral Worth in Kant s Moral Theory. Immanuel Kant s moral theory outlined in The Grounding for the Metaphysics of

FACULTY OF ARTS B.A. Part II Examination,

Hume s An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding

THE TRINITY REVIEW. The Failure of Secular Economics. by John W. Robbins

Basic Considerations on Epistemology (1937) Paul Bernays

On the futility of criticizing the neoclassical maximization hypothesis

What is Formal in Husserl s Logical Investigations?

Higher National Unit Specification. General information for centres. Unit title: Philosophy C: An Introduction to Analytic Philosophy

Transcription:

METHODENSTREIT WHY CARL MENGER WAS, AND IS, RIGHT BY THORSTEN POLLEIT* PRESENTED AT THE SPRING CONFERENCE RESEARCH ON MONEY IN THE ECONOMY (ROME) FRANKFURT, 20 MAY 2011 *FRANKFURT SCHOOL OF FINANCE & MANAGEMENT SONNEMANNSTRAßE 9-11 60314 FRANKFURT AM MAIN TEL.: +49 (0) 69 154008-0 E-MAIL: INFO@FRANKFURT-SCHOOL.DE

The (Older and Younger) Historical School Older Historical School Wilhelm Georg Friedrich Roscher (1817 1894), Grundriss zu Vorlesungen über die Staatswirtschaft nach geschichtlicher Methode (1843) Bruno Hildebrand (1812 1878) Karl Knies (1821 1898) Younger Historical School Gustav von Schmoller (1838 1917) Georg Friedrich Knapp (1842 1926) Karl Wilhelm Bücher (1847 1930) The methodological position of the Younger Historical School: The representatives of the Younger Historical School rejected economic theory for its advocacy of universally valid economic laws. It was argued that economic laws could only be as universal as the conditions to which they referred. Since history was a process of constant transformation of 2

the conditions of human existence, there could be no such thing as an economic law. At best, there could be "laws" describing the economy of a more or less unique period and, all insights about this economy had to be derived from studies of concrete historical episodes. In fact, the Younger Historical School advocated (radical) positivismempiricism, inductivism and relativism ( anything goes ): One can never definitely establish whether a hypothesized relationship between two or more economic variables exists or not. 3

Carl Menger and the Methodenstreit Carl Menger (1840 1921), in his Untersuchungen über die Methode der Sozialwissenschaften und der politischen Ökonomie insbesondere (1883) refuted the methodology of the Younger Historical School. His Investigations led to the Methodenstreit, the battle of method: It pitted the emerging Austrian School against the Historical School over a critically important question: what is the proper way to do social science? Menger explained that there are economic laws in the sense of exact laws of reality, and that the method of historical research was unable to discover these laws. Example of an exact laws of reality : A rise (decline) in the amount of money (in the economy) necessarily leads to a fall (rise) in the purchasing 4

power of a money unit (compared to a situation in which the money supply had remained unchanged). Mises (1984 [1969], p. 12) saw the Methodenstreit being about epistemology: The term Methodenstreit is, of course, misleading. For the issue was not to discover the most appropriate procedure for the treatment of the problems commonly considered as economic problems. The matter in dispute was essentially whether there could be such a thing as a science, other than history, dealing with aspects of human action. 5

The realistic-empirical orientation of theoretical research, as we saw, offers us in all realms of the world of phenomena results which are formally imperfect, however important and valuable they may be for human knowledge and practical life. They are theories which give us only a deficient understanding of the phenomena, only an uncertain prediction of them, and by no means an assured control of them. From the very beginning, too, the human mind has followed another orientation of theoretical research beside the one discussed above. It is different from the latter both in its aims and in its approaches to cognition. The aim of this orientation, which in the future we will call the exact one, an aim which research pursues in the same way in all realms of the world of phenomena, is the determination of strict laws of phenomena, of regularities in the succession of phenomena which do not present themselves to us as absolute, but which in respect to the approaches to cognition by which we attain to them simply bear within themselves the guarantee of absoluteness. It is the determination of laws of phenomena which commonly are called "laws of nature," but more correctly should be designated by the expression "exact laws." Carl Menger, (1985 [1883]), Investigations, p. 59. 6

Refuting positivism-empiricism Positivism is a philosophy of science, based on the ideas of Henri de Saint Simon (1760 1825) and Auguste Comte (1798 1857). It rests on the assertion that theology and metaphysics are earlier imperfect sources of knowledge, and that positive knowledge is based on natural phenomena, with its properties and relations verified by the empirical sciences. Positivism holds that: (1) sense experience is the only (and measurable) source of human knowledge; (2) that knowledge can come only from affirmation of theories through strict scientific method; and (3) the validity of metaphysical speculation must be rejected. Empiricism (as applied in the field of social sciences) considers natural sciences to be its model and can be characterised as follows: Empiricism maintains that economic propositions have the same logical status as laws of nature, and it states hypothetical relationships between two or more events, essentially in the form of if-then statements. 7

It maintains that economic propositions require continual testing vis-à-vis experience. They can never be validated once and for all with certainty, as the economic hypothesis is forever subject to the outcome of contingent, future experience. If data testing confirms the hypothesis, empiricism would say that it is not validated (once and for all), as there remains the possibility that the relationship(s) under review might be falsified by future experience (using new data and/or including explanatory variables which were hitherto uncontrolled ). If, however, data testing suggests a rejection of the hypothesis, it would not prove that the hypothesised relationship could never be observed through future testing, so it is not falsified either. Empiricism is actually expressive of scepticism, which can be formulated as: nothing can be known with certainty, and anything might be possible in the realm of economics; it leads to a philosophy of social and economic relativism (Hoppe (2007a, b [1995]). 8

Perhaps most prominently, David Hume (1711 1776) rejected the notion of causality (which is, in terms of praxeology, a category of human action). Hume stated that even if we observe one event continually following another, we cannot conclude a necessary connection between the two (post hoc, ergo propter hoc fallacy). However, upon closer examination it can be shown that empiricism (as well as historicism (as will be shown below)) is in fact a self-contradictory doctrine (Hoppe (2007a, b [1995]): The empiricist statement that all economic events are only hypothetically related is contradicted by the message of the basic empiricist proposition itself. If this proposition is regarded as itself being merely hypothetically true, it would not qualify as an epistemological pronouncement. Empiricism would not provide any justification whatsoever for its claim that economic propositions are not, and cannot, be categorically, or a priori, true. 9

If, however, we assume that the empiricist claim is categorically true, it would belie its own thesis, namely that empirical knowledge must invariably be hypothetical knowledge thereby making room for a discipline as economics claiming to produce a priori valid (empirical) knowledge. There is another important reason why empiricism is a self-contradictory, self-defeating, doctrine, because it tacitly assumes the existence of nonempirical knowledge as real knowledge. This becomes obvious as the prerequisite of being able to falsify or confirm a theory on the basis of experience necessarily assumes the constancy principle. Experience only reveals that two or more observations regarding the temporal sequence of events can be classified as repetition or as nonrepetition. Such reasoning, however, implicitly assumes that there are constant causes which operate in time-invariant ways. Without assuming the constancy principle, the observations are and remain non-repetitive registered experiences, not in any way related events; contingency does not play any part in the way causes operate. 10

However, the constancy principle is not based on, or derived from, experience. There is no observable link connecting events. Even if such a link were observable, one could not say whether or not it was timeinvariant. The constancy principle cannot be disproved by experience. Any event which might appear to disprove it (such as a failure to duplicate some experience) could be interpreted as if experience had shown here that merely one particular type of event was not the cause of another (otherwise the experience would have been successfully repeated). However, to the extent that experience cannot exclude the possibility that another set of events might be found which would turn out to be time-invariant in its way of operating, the validity of the constancy principle cannot be disproved. Historicism suggests that economic phenomena are not objective magnitudes that can be measured, but are subjective expressions and interpretations unfolding in history to be understood and interpreted by the economist just as a literary text unfolds before and is interpreted by its reader. 11

Note that historicism states that nothing in the literary text (historical account), and nothing in the historical sequence of historical events, is governed by constant relations; anything that happened had to happen in the way it did. The formation of human expressions (actions) and their interpretation are also not constrained by any kind of objective law. Economic events are whatever economists or historians (taking a subjective view) express or interpret them to be. If historicism claims that economic and historical events which are sequences of subjectively perceived events are not governed by any constant, time-invariable relations, then this proposition cannot claim to say anything constantly true about economics and history. In fact, historicism would lead to propositions with fleeting value. A certain historically observed economic relation may be true now, if we wish, on one occasion, yet it may possibly be false one another occasion. However, if this is the case, then historicism must be assumed to be constrained by something outside the realm of arbitrary subjective creations: 12

If the historicist proposition is assumed to be invariably true, then such a proposition about the constant nature of historical and economic phenomena would contradict its own doctrine which actually denies any such constant relationships. If, however, historicism holds that economic sequences are not governed by constant, time-invariable relations, then this very proposition also cannot claim to say anything constantly true about history and economics. As a result, historicism cannot claim anything if it were not for the fact that its expressions and interpretations are constrained by laws of logic as the very presuppositions of meaningful statements as such. 13

Economics as an a priori theoretical science Ludwig von Mises (1881 1973) re-constructed economics as an a priori theory. He identified economics as a sub-field of praxeology the logic of human action, resting on the axiom of human action. The axiom of human action represents a synthetic a priori judgement (in the Kantian sense) and as such it is irrefutably true. Identifying economics as a form of applied logic derives from the status of the axiom of human action, with the latter being an a priori-true synthetic proposition. 14

References Hoppe, H.-H. (2007 (1995]), Economic Science and the Austrian Method, Ludwig von Mises Institute, Auburn, US Alabama. Mises, L. v. (2003 [1960]), Epistemological Problems of Economics, 3 rd ed., Ludwig von Mises Institute, US Alabama. Mises, L. v. (1984 [1969]), The Historical Setting of the Austrian School of Economics, Ludwig von Mises Institute, Auburn, US Alabama. Mises, L. v. (1996), Human Action, 4 th ed., Fox & Wilkes, San Francisco. *** 15