When we think that if the square root of two is rational then one equals zero, we think, The

Similar documents
A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports. Stephen Schiffer New York University

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

On possibly nonexistent propositions

Coordination Problems

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

On Possibly Nonexistent Propositions

KAPLAN RIGIDITY, TIME, A ND MODALITY. Gilbert PLUMER

Mathematics in and behind Russell s logicism, and its

17. Tying it up: thoughts and intentionality

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

15. Russell on definite descriptions

Is anything knowable on the basis of understanding alone?

Theories of propositions

1. Introduction. Against GMR: The Incredulous Stare (Lewis 1986: 133 5).

Lecture 4. Before beginning the present lecture, I should give the solution to the homework problem

Definite Descriptions and the Argument from Inference

Williamson s proof of the primeness of mental states

Some proposals for understanding narrow content

Fictionalism, Theft, and the Story of Mathematics. 1. Introduction. Philosophia Mathematica (III) 17 (2009),

Quine: Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes

Understanding Belief Reports. David Braun. In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection.

Russell on Denoting. G. J. Mattey. Fall, 2005 / Philosophy 156. The concept any finite number is not odd, nor is it even.

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Intentionality and Method. John R. Searle

(1) A phrase may be denoting, and yet not denote anything; e.g., 'the present King of France'.

book-length treatments of the subject have been scarce. 1 of Zimmerman s book quite welcome. Zimmerman takes up several of the themes Moore

Propositions as Cambridge properties

IN his paper, 'Does Tense Logic Rest Upon a Mistake?' (to appear

Privilege in the Construction Industry. Shamik Dasgupta Draft of February 2018

Nathaniel Goldberg. McTAGGART ON TIME

Philosophy of Mind. Introduction to the Mind-Body Problem

Craig on the Experience of Tense

5 A Modal Version of the

Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions. David Braun. University of Rochester

Interpretation: Keeping in Touch with Reality. Gilead Bar-Elli. 1. In a narrow sense a theory of meaning (for a language) is basically a Tarski-like

A Review of Neil Feit s Belief about the Self

What is Good Reasoning?

Critical Study of Michael Jubien, Ontology, Modality, and the Fallacy of Reference

On Truth At Jeffrey C. King Rutgers University

BonJour Against Materialism. Just an intellectual bandwagon?

Necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pp. i-ix, 379. ISBN $35.00.

Revelation, Humility, and the Structure of the World. David J. Chalmers

Constructing the World

Phil 435: Philosophy of Language. [Handout 7] W. V. Quine, Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes (1956)

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Why there is no such thing as a motivating reason

(1) a phrase may be denoting, and yet not denote anything e.g. the present King of France

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

Russell: On Denoting

proper construal of Davidson s principle of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St.

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

The distinction between truth-functional and non-truth-functional logical and linguistic

PULP NATURALISM. Il Cannocchiale, Rivista di Studi Filosofici, 2 [special issue on Philosophy of Mind and Cognitive Science], 1997:

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

Stout s teleological theory of action

Is mental content prior to linguistic meaning?

Is phenomenal character out there in the world?

Skepticism and Internalism

Knocked Out Senseless: Naturalism and Analyticity. Takashi Yagisawa. [The Maribor Papers: Essays on Semantic Naturalism, D. Jutric (ed.

12. A Theistic Argument against Platonism (and in Support of Truthmakers and Divine Simplicity)

Constructing the World

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information

ON NONSENSE IN THE TRACTATUS LOGICO-PHILOSOPHICUS: A DEFENSE OF THE AUSTERE CONCEPTION

Comments on Ontological Anti-Realism

Frode Bjørdal ON BELIEFS. 1. Introduction

10 CERTAINTY G.E. MOORE: SELECTED WRITINGS

Nature of Necessity Chapter IV

Content and Modality: Themes from the Philosophy of Robert Stalnaker, edited by

Aboutness and Justification

Ling 98a: The Meaning of Negation (Week 1)

Primitive Concepts. David J. Chalmers

Defending Existentialism?

Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

How Gödelian Ontological Arguments Fail

sentences in which they occur, thus giving us singular propositions that contain the object

Humean Supervenience: Lewis (1986, Introduction) 7 October 2010: J. Butterfield

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

Two Kinds of Moral Relativism

Objections to the two-dimensionalism of The Conscious Mind

ON DEGREE ACTUALISM ALEXANDRA LECLAIR 1 INTRODUCTION

Nominalism III: Austere Nominalism 1. Philosophy 125 Day 7: Overview. Nominalism IV: Austere Nominalism 2

Response. Paul Johnson University of Illinois, Urbana-Champaign

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Lecture 3 Arguments Jim Pryor What is an Argument? Jim Pryor Vocabulary Describing Arguments

356 THE MONIST all Cretans were liars. It can be put more simply in the form: if a man makes the statement I am lying, is he lying or not? If he is, t

ELEMENTS OF LOGIC. 1.1 What is Logic? Arguments and Propositions

Postscript to Plenitude of Possible Structures (2016)

2017 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

Future Contingents, Non-Contradiction and the Law of Excluded Middle Muddle

A Model of Decidable Introspective Reasoning with Quantifying-In

To appear in Philosophical Studies 150 (3): (2010).

Transcription:

Meaning, Expression, and Thought. WAYNE A. DAVIS. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003. Pp. xvii, 654. When we think that if the square root of two is rational then one equals zero, we think, The square root of two is rational, that is, the thought that the square root of two is rational occurs to us. The occurrence of the thought does not entail that we believe the thought true, or desire it true, or have any other attitude toward it. On the other hand, belief entails an occurrence of the thought. If Jane, a novice math student, believes that the square root of two is rational, the thought that the square root of two is rational occurs to her, or at least has occurred to her and can occur to her. Likewise with all other propositional attitudes. Or so says Wayne Davis. Thoughts are the basic building blocks of his ambitious theory of meaning. Davis defines speaker meaning, communication, word meaning, speaker reference, word reference, and many other related notions to be included in any comprehensive theory of meaning, in terms ultimately of thoughts and their occurrence. For example: By (the expression) e, S means iff S directly expresses the idea or thought that by producing e. (p. 32) S expresses iff S preforms an observable act as an indication of occurrent without thereby covertly simulating an unintentional indication of. (p. 59) Here is a substitutional variable to be replaced with any term denoting a mental state.

S communicates M to A iff S does something by which S expresses M and from which A recognizes that S is expressing M. (p. 94) This thick book is extensively researched and contains a large number of arguments, many of which are convincing and most of those which are not are provocative and worth close scrutiny. Davis presents a comprehensive picture of language based on the conviction that a language is a conventional system of expressing thoughts and their component parts (ideas). The most consistently plausible part of this admirable book is Part One, in which he argues relentlessly against what might be termed the doxastic fallacy, namely, the view that linguistic meaning is ultimately a matter of transmission of belief as such. I shall mainly confine myself to two critical remarks on the rest of the book, which is still quite strong. Even though Davis declares his notions of thought and its occurrence primitive, he says a great deal about them. The thought that the square root of two is rational is a structured mental event type. It occurs to Jane by being instantiated in her. The mental event token in Jane is a spatiotemporal object, whereas the type is an abstract object, which could exist without being instantiated by any token. Davis identifies the proposition that P with the thought that P. Propositions are thus mental event types with internal structure. The thought, or proposition, that the square root of two is rational is composed of its constituent parts, main ones of which are the idea square root, the idea two, and the idea rational. Such parts are the objects of expression by words and phrases the way propositions are the objects of expression by sentences. The phrase square root expresses the idea square root and the word rational expresses the idea rational. As events, propositions are demystified. They are no longer murky objects of darkness the 2

nature of which is mysterious except their contentfulness. They are just events, and while a satisfactory theory of events is yet to be formulated, they are made more mundane. At the same time, as types, propositions retain their aloof independence from the realm of particulars. Countless types exist without being tokened. Propositions thus keep their comfortable abstractness intact. Davis thus manages to have his cake and eat it too. Or does he? A proposition has its content essentially. So, if a proposition is a mental event type, that mental event type has its content essentially. But given physicalism, which Davis favors, some mental event (e.g., every mental event in a human being) is a neurophysiological event. Therefore, some neurophysiological event has a content and has it essentially. But neurophysiological events are not essentially contentful; a fortiori they do not have a specific content essentially. A contradiction. Davis s reaction to this reductio argument is to bite the bullet and say that since propositions have a content and have it essentially and they are (empirically likely to be) neurophysiological events, neurophysiological events have a content and have it essentially. Davis also thinks that the content of a contentful neurophysiological event is intrinsic to the event. It seems to me that this reaction to the objection is too hasty. What the version of physicalism Davis favors offers is token identity. So, for the objection to go through, it must be assumed that if a type has a feature intrinsically and essentially, so do its tokens. But this is an implausible assumption. Davis is only committed to locating the intrinsic essential contentfulness in the types. The mental event type, the proposition that the square root of two is rational, has the content, the square root of two is rational, intrinsically and essentially. This is plausible, and this seems to be a cleaner response Davis can make to the objection. The price for this, however, is that the proposed definition of proposition becomes rather uninformative. If 3

some human neurophysiological event token and some Martian inner-hydrodynamic event token both count as tokens of the same type, say, the proposition that the square root of two is rational, what unifies them into the same type except that they are tokens of that proposition, i.e., that type? It would not help to try the Kripkean theoretical identity gambit here. If the proposition that the square root of two is rational is identical with the human neurophysiological event type à la Water is identical with H 2 O, then the same proposition is also identical with the imagined Martian inner-hydrodynamic event type. It then follows that the human neurophysiological event type and the Martian inner-hydrodynamic event type are identical with each other, which they are not. Davis says: Suppose that Peter believes that there are two famous Americans named Ronald W. Reagan... When watching a movie, Peter says Reagan is nothing but a two-bit actor. When watching a presidential address, he says Reagan is one of the greatest Americans who has ever lived.... But clearly, Peter is expressing different ideas on the two occasions. As a result, he is not contradicting himself. Yet there are no words in the English language (or in any idiolect that we share with Peter) that express those ideas. (P. 113) Clearly, different mental event tokens occur in Peter on the two occasions. This does not mean, however, that he is not contradicting himself. If I say The square root of two is rational on Monday and say The square root of two is not rational on Friday, I am contradicting myself, even though two different mental event tokens are involved. Why does Davis say that clearly 4

Peter expresses different ideas of Reagan on the two occasions? The following passages seem to offer some help: S is thinking of (about) iff the idea of is occurring to S. (P. 318) S is thinking of and is the object of S s thought should not be treated as expressing a relation between and S or his thought. They should be treated only as descriptions of S and what S is thinking. (P. 320) This means that when we say that Peter thinks about Reagan, we are not expressing any relation between Peter, or a mental event token in Peter, and Reagan. But then, it is not clear what it means to say that Peter think about Reagan. When we say pretheoretically, Peter thinks about Reagan, we clearly seem to express a relation between the two men. Davis uses the words idea and concept interchangeably as meaning part of thought. Thus, when he says, Since we can think about Socrates, we have to have a concept of Socrates (p. 409), we naturally understand him as saying that since mental event types about Socrates are tokened in us, there are parts of mental event types that are tokened in us that are about Socrates. When two people think about Socrates, two different mental-event-part tokens occur which are of the same type, the idea of Socrates. So, possession of the idea of Socrates is guaranteed by the ability to think about Socrates. According to Davis, it is unintelligible to speak of a--as opposed 5

to the--belief that P, for any specific P. So we should speak of the belief that Socrates is wise, not a belief that Socrates is wise. Likewise Davis should say that we should speak of the idea of Socrates, not an idea of Socrates. There is a word in English that expresses that idea, namely, the word Socrates ; cf. 7.9 Definition: The idea of = the idea (p. 149). So, Peter s idea on either occasion is the idea of Ronald W. Reagan, viz., the idea Ronald W. Reagan. What more can we say about this idea? It is tempting to say that it is the thought-part type whose tokens are unified by means of bearing a certain specific external (perhaps causal-historical) relation to Reagan. Furthermore, consider:... word reference is transparent and fully relational, subject to both existential instantiation and the substitutivity of identity.... we can say that e refers to iff (i) exists and (ii) for some =, e verbally expresses the idea of. Thus Roosevelt refers to Franklin Delano Roosevelt in English because it is a word that expresses the idea of Franklin Delano Roosevelt, who was a real person. (P. 151) Davis here speaks of the idea of Franklin Delano Roosevelt. Even though he is speaking of word expression rather than speaker expression, of which he was speaking in the earlier passage about Peter and Ronald W. Reagan, the two passages are about ideas of particular individuals and there is some tension between them. If Peter has two different ideas of Reagan, it is hard to see how there can be such a thing as the idea of Franklin Delano Roosevelt, whether it is or is not expressed by some word or speaker. Furthermore, the context the idea of ( ) must be transparent and relational, for otherwise, the relative clause who was a real person in the last 6

quoted sentence would be nonsensical. This makes it hard to fathom how there could be two distinct mental types that are both properly called idea of Ronald W. Reagan. This also seems to make the current passage go against the two earlier passages quoted from pp. 318 and 320 taken together. Some may notice a small number of howlers in this rich and otherwise well-researched and carefully-reasoned book. For example, on p. 362, Davis says: Salmon presents an interesting variant of the Mates problem, in an effort to show that even the clearest synonyms are not substitutable. Nathan Salmon s effort is exactly to the opposite end. Such infelicities are rare and should not deter anyone from finishing this rewarding tome. TAKASHI YAGISAWA California State University, Northridge 7