H U M a N I M A L I A 2:2

Similar documents
Use the following checklist to make sure you have revised everything.

Superior Human. Wong Tsz Yan Chinese Medicine, New Asia College

Meat Logic: Why Do We Eat Animals? By Charles Horn READ ONLINE

Format for ONE Paragraph

Questions for Critically Reading an Argument

Philosophical approaches to animal ethics

H U M a N I M A L I A 3:2

STUDY GUIDE ARE HUMANS MORE VALUABLE THAN ANIMALS? KEY TERMS:

THE GREATEST SCANDAL NEVER EXPOSED

Analysis of American Indian Environmental Ethics as Described by Ojibwa Narratives

THE ESSAY. Some tips for writing good introductions Strategies for writing good introductions

A Responsible Steward Eats No Meatballs: A Reading Experience of Jonathan Foer s Eating Animals Gijsbert Korevaar 1

Cultural Relativism 1

PAPER CODE : EN TEST PAPER FOR ENGLISH

The Road to Nirvana Is Paved with Skillful Intentions Excerpt from Noble Strategy by Thanissaro Bhikkhu Chinese Translation by Cheng Chen-huang There

H U M a N I M A L I A 3:1

Annotated Bibliography. seeking to keep the possibility of dualism alive in academic study. In this book,


ANIMAL RIGHTS Text: Deuteronomy 25:4

Disvalue in nature and intervention *

Researching Choreography: In Search of Stories of the Making

Introduction. In light of these facts, we will ask, is killing animals for human benefit morally permissible?

Gary Francione Interview on WTJS

Roads to the Heart. Order the complete book from. Booklocker.com.

PROBLEM PASSAGES FOR SECURITY

Fort Belknap Buffalo Survey Frequencies and Marginal Percentages

Review of Jean Kazez's Animalkind: What We Owe to Animals

We recommend you cite the published version. The publisher s URL is:

Critical Thinking Questions

PAGLORY COLLEGE OF EDUCATION

WhaT does it mean To Be an animal? about 600 million years ago, CerTain

From They Say/I Say: The Moves that Matter in Academic Writing Gerald Graff and Cathy Birkenstein Prediction:

Animal Rights Planet Earth Prejudice Early Life War and Peace Young People

The Philosophy of Animal Activism

Philosophical Perspectives on Ethics

Book Review: Nature Ethics: An Ecofeminist Perspective, Kheel, Marti (Rowman Littlefield 2008) Lynda Birke 1

H U M a N I M A L I A 1:1

Withholding or Withdrawing of Artificial Nutrition and Hydration

The Great Compassion: Buddhism and Animal Rights

RE Religion and Life 2012 Exam Paper

Review of Science and Ethics. Bernard Rollin Cambridge University Press pp., paper

"Dogs ARE Persons!" (The Other Side of the Debate)

Suffering of Chickens in the Kaporos Ritual: The Facts

JOYFUL, COMPASSIONATE EATING

God s Word and Spiritual Discernment (#11 ) Text : Hebrews 5: 11-6: 12

Environmental Ethics. Espen Gamlund, PhD Associate Professor of Philosophy University of Bergen

OCR YEAR 11 MOCK EXAMS REVISION BOOKLET

Region of Inexactness and Related Concepts

in terms of us being generally more health-conscious than average, but because we support freedom of lifestyle as well as freedom of religious

H U M a N I M A L I A 6:2. Reviews

The Pharisee and Tax Collector

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

Interview with Lori Marino By OUR HEN HOUSE Published February 22, 2014

-1 Peter 3:15-16 (NSRV)

VIEWING PERSPECTIVES

Story Versus Essay: The Particular Feud of Universal Virtue. As Plato once cogitated, If particulars are to have meaning, there must be universals.

Kevin Scharp, Replacing Truth, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013, At 300-some pages, with narrow margins and small print, the work

by scientists in social choices and in the dialogue leading to decision-making.

Didn t he know that it was likely to be a person, not an animal, who came out of his house first?

Noah Could He Eat All Things?

Antigone plays with the notion that we often want our systems of

The Rights of. Animals. in Islam

Introduction Questions to Ask in Judging Whether A Really Causes B

Why does the Bible care about what consenting adults do in private?

In this set of essays spanning much of his career at Calvin College,

Sermon Let s Be Honest (week 2)

2014 Examination Report 2014 Extended Investigation GA 2: Critical Thinking Test GENERAL COMMENTS

Ask Yourself: Which points have the best supporting information? For which points can I make the best case? In which points am I most interested?

Reasons Community. May 7, 2017

Bible Witness Script Cornelius Servant Based on Peter s visit to the household of Cornelius (Acts 10)

Dworkin on the Rufie of Recognition

Christian Discernment

Bart Streumer, Unbelievable Errors, Oxford: Oxford University Press, ISBN

Holy Curiosity. Mark 12: Preached by Dr. Robert F. Browning, Pastor. First Baptist Church. Frankfort, Kentucky.

What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age

The Nazi Research Data: Should We Use It?

We Are Made of Meat. An Interview with Matthew Calarco. Leonardo Caffo

Tara Smith s Ayn Rand s Normative Ethics: A Positive Contribution to the Literature on Objectivism?

In his book Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, J. L. Mackie agues against

RECLAIMING FOOD AS SACRED MEDICINE: SPIRITUAL DIMENSIONS OF TRADITIONAL DIETS JoAnne Dodgson, Ed.D.

Conceptual Levels: Bringing It Home to

Chapter 3 Disputes and Definitions

The Harvest, the Kill

The Great Questions of Life What is the Meaning of Life? Kevin Haah John 1:1-4. February 4, 2018

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

The Moral Philosophy of John Steinbeck (review)

Logical (formal) fallacies

Israel Kirzner is a name familiar to all readers of the Review of

Taylor Chapter 9. An Iron Cage. Thursday, March 22, 12

Philippians 3:

1. What is Philosophy?

Take Home Exam #1. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

Beliefs Versus Knowledge: A Necessary Distinction for Explaining, Predicting, and Assessing Conceptual Change

I am truly honored and blessed to share my experiences of sustainability on the student panel this afternoon

x Philosophic Thoughts: Essays on Logic and Philosophy

Dr. John Hamre President and Chief Executive Officer Center for Strategic and International Studies Washington, D.C.

INDUCTIVE VS. DEDUCTIVE WRITING ADAPTED PARTIALLY FROM DR. TAMARA FUDGE, KAPLAN UNIVERSITY

Shamans, Healing, and Mental Health

William B. Provine. February 19, 1942 September 8, 2015

The Paradox of Democracy

Transcription:

H U M a N I M A L I A 2:2 Lynda Birke Eat, Love, Hate Hal Herzog. Some We Love, Some We Hate, Some We Eat: Why It s So Hard To Think Straight About Animals. New York: HarperCollins, 2010. 336pp. $25.99 pb. Why is it so hard to think about animals? asks Herzog in the introduction to the book. We are, as he cogently argues, highly inconsistent in our dealings with animals as the title of the book makes plain. There are indeed some animals we love, with whom we share our lives and affections; there are others we hate, or fear, and try to exterminate; there are still others destined for food. And this is not only a distinction of how we use different species: individuals of one species may be treated quite differently by humans in various contexts. Think, for example, of horses, who are pets as well as partners in competition in my household, but are seen as a primary source of food in other places. Or mice, who can become our saviors when they bear our diseases in medical research, or perhaps in the same lab can be pests bringing in unwanted diseases. Herzog explores the myriad paradoxes in human dealings with animals, from cockerels to cats to cows. Our dealings with other species often (perhaps usually) defy logic. In his introduction, he tells the stories of people who choose to eat some animals and not others, making apparently arbitrary decisions; of the colleague who woke up one day and released his caged cockatiel, as he now felt it to be wrong (and despite realizing that she would probably not survive), of the implications for his own family keeping a pet snake who would need to eat. Herzog faced this dilemma when an animal rights activist asked him about his pet boa constrictor, saying that she had heard that he was feeding kittens to his snake. That provocative question made him sit up and think hard about how we make ethical distinctions with regard to animals. What, he asks, is morally preferable keeping a predator who eats canned meat or one who eats small animal carcasses? To some, it might seem preferable to feed the bodies of kittens that had been killed by the local animal shelter, than to give the snake other pet animals (such as the mice some snake owners might buy from the pet shop). But how and why do we decide what is ethical? Herzog is, undeniably, right that we are morally inconsistent in our thinking about other animals even (or perhaps especially) those of us who work in animal studies or activism. I do not deny that I live with predators I share the house with three dogs and if they do manage to kill a rabbit or a hare I am upset. Yet I also know that two of them are hunters one is a greyhound, and one a lurcher (the third one is a border

116 collie, bred to chase sheep instead). I am a lifelong vegetarian, yet I know that if the doctor prescribes any medicines for me, they will have been tested on animals. Herzog has also long been working in animal studies, and tells us of how he became increasingly fascinated by these moral inconsistencies. How, he ponders, can so many people (he cites 60 % of Americans) believe both that animals have the right to live and also that people have the right to eat them? He explores a wide variety of issues and data from purported connections between cruelty to animals and violence to people, to the paradox of Nazi animal protectionism, to our relationships with dogs, to hunting and cockfighting just about all our dealings with other species are profoundly complex. Our behavior toward other species, and the language we use to describe them, betray our deep ambivalences. Herzog notes the extensive euphemisms we use we talk about culling or sacrifice, rather than killing lab animals, for example. Take one example from the many that Herzog examines cockfighting. Illegal both here in Britain and in many states of the US, it persists underground. It is also loathed by many people, who consider the bloody practice of pitting cocks against each other to be abhorrent. Driving on a very hot day to a meeting with someone who keeps fighting cocks, Herzog passes a large truck, stacked with crates packed to the brim with live chickens, bound for the slaughterhouse. Working out the cage numbers, he calculates that s over 1000 animals on each truck, the chickens crammed together like anchovies packed in a jar of oil. And however gruesome the cockfight might be, he realizes, many, many more chickens end their lives in this kind of transportation misery (and often inhumane slaughter), to contribute to the six-piece McNugget Happy Meal just down the road (150). Herzog recounts how he managed to befriend people who were cockfighters, and was trusted enough to be allowed to attend. Cockfighting is taken very seriously by practitioners; they maintain bloodlines as carefully as the horse racing industry, and run the fights according to strict protocol. More relevant, though, is that they do not consider what they do to be cruel. They emphasize that the fight is only the culmination of a long period of caring for the animal. One fighter told Herzog: You will never find a nicer group of people. Where else can you go where that much money changes hands on a nod without any controversy? Cockers are gentlemen (163-64). And these are men who claim to love their chickens. They provide them with the best food, the best housing, and daily care. Humanimalia: a journal of human/animal interface studies Volume 2, Number 2 (Spring 2011)

117 Cockfighting illustrates well the complex relationships we have with other animals. It may indeed end in a vicious bloodbath, but the life of the gamecock until that time is, Herzog notes, rather more comfortable than that of the average broiler chicken who lives and dies in unimaginable squalor and discomfort. This is not to exonerate the fights; rather, it is to emphasize that how we require animals to live matters, perhaps as much as how we impose their manner and time of death. Cockfighting is, moreover, an example of how human relationships with animals play out within the context of human social divisions gender and social class, for instance. Not only are cockers almost entirely men, but cockfighting is seen by many to epitomize poor, rural, working-class communities unlike some other sports using animals. Like cockfighting, notes Herzog, horse racing represents a confluence of gambling and suffering. But unlike cockfighting, thoroughbreds are the passtime (sic) of the rich (172). Some we Love, Some we Hate, Some we Eat ranges widely, drawing on many different examples of our bewildering ambiguities about other animals. The style of writing is friendly, drawing on many anecdotes: Herzog often recounts tales of animals who helped him to unravel human stories, or of particular people he has met whose beliefs about animals illustrate the paradoxes. He tells, for example, of how his Labrador, Molly, inadvertently allowed him to discover the clandestine world of cockfighting; deciding to cure Molly of chasing chickens, he sought some of his own, and met a breeder of game cocks in the process. Or he tells contrasting stories of people living with animals: the bond may work well, and provide person (and perhaps the animal) with companionship and quality of life or it may fail. Sarah, an administrator at a veterinary hospital, for instance, wanted a dog, but when she and her husband acquired two animals, they rapidly became the dogs from hell ; eventually, the marriage could not take the strain. The many anecdotes make for a good read ; they bring a personal touch. To read about Sarah, or Nancy, or Molly, is to contemplate real people, and real animals and the dilemmas of real-life decisions. The easygoing style means that the book will have popular appeal even while it engages with a set of really thorny issues. Herzog weaves between the paradoxes well, forcing us to confront ambivalences we probably knew we had, and to realize others we did not know about. And he connects these moral inconsistencies to other, wider, questions. One example is his discussion of gender (a theme he has written about also in the research literature in human-animal Lynda Birke Eat, Love, Hate

118 studies). Gender undoubtedly has an impact on our behavior toward animals: women outnumber men in animal activism, and are more likely to become animal hoarders. Sadistic abusers of animals, on the other hand, are more likely to be men. Yet there is also plenty of overlap; some women shoot animals to death in hunting (seen as a masculine endeavor); many men work hard in animal protection (sometimes seen as a female preserve). And despite gender stereotypes, there is actually little scientific evidence to differentiate women and men in terms of attitudes, he suggests. It is just those abilities to make connections while appealing to a wider public and at the same time asking awkward questions that make this a noteworthy book. It poses many questions that are not asked often enough. Take one example, from an issue I am particularly interested in what happens in animal labs. Herzog points out the contrast between good mice (those intended for research) and bad mice (those, usually escapees, who run wild and are seen as pests). He explores, too, the (considerable) variability of judgments from different institutional ethical committees on the same experimental protocols. And he discusses in detail the legal framework in the United States, which makes a distinction that is completely incomprehensible to anyone living in the United Kingdom: in US law controlling animal research, rats, mice and birds don t count as animals. That attention to fine details of our moral distinctions is a strength of this book. It is one thing to be an advocate for animals, or an animal rights activist; it is quite another to think through and confront the incoherency of many of our ethical positions. I found Hal Herzog s discussions of his own personal ambivalences about our use of animals refreshing. He does not shy away from admitting his own unease and difficulties so exposing himself to criticism for precisely the inconsistency that forms the focus of the book. The easygoing style of writing, too, introduces readers to many complex philosophical and scientific issues. The book has evidently been widely picked up and its issues discussed in the media, so that it reaches a wider public than many of our academic journals can. Its accessibility makes it appealing to many people outside the narrow frames of human-animal studies or animal activism, and its many anecdotes of our inconsistent behavior provides a good base for teaching and discussing questions of moral ambiguity and decision-making. That said, I have some reservations. First, the style is certainly easygoing. Yet it is precisely that quality that I sometimes found difficult. Of course, that is partly because it is not intended to be academic, and I am a university professor: I always want to check sources, and find it frustrating when they are not supplied except as generalized Humanimalia: a journal of human/animal interface studies Volume 2, Number 2 (Spring 2011)

119 further reading (as is the case here). But I also felt that the style did not quite work for readers outside North America. Any references to American baseball or popular culture go right over my head, and the particular kind of culturally specific, jokey, writing sometimes fall flat for me. Perhaps I am alone in this, and I d be interested to see how my students in the UK react. It would be a pity if they were to miss the point of the debate because they couldn t quite get the text. I also had reservations about the discussions of vegetarianism and I have no doubt that Hal Herzog will smile when he reads this. As a vegetarian, I have had many times to confront the challenges: you can t get enough protein; the diet is bland; you are hypocritical because you don t eat animals but you do live with dogs... etc. etc. etc. I refuse to be intimidated by them. But I did feel that the several discussions of vegetarians who had given up and begun to love raw steak, or who had become ill or anorexic, a little irritating. To be sure, I ve met ex-vegetarians who tell me they didn t feel healthy enough: then I find out they are lousy (or lazy) cooks who paid no heed to a balanced diet. It was, I think, the references to vegetarianism that made me wonder if there was an underlying question that assumed that we can arrive at a morally consistent positioning. Certainly, these are good examples of our confusions; yet I ended up feeling that there was a subtext why be veggie? which I found at odds with the open-mindedness Herzog displays in his approach to so many of the issues raised here. Too often, it seemed, the book was emphasizing ways in which vegetarianism falls short of some ideal. Yet can we ever achieve an ethically pure stance? I doubt it. I know full well that taking any moral position cannot be done absolutely, and that almost everything that we do means compromise. That does not, however, mean that I want to take no moral position. Inconsistent? Hypocritical? Perhaps, but maybe a pragmatic and partial position is the best we can do. My second problem is that, while Herzog notes that species differences matter, at least some of our collective ambivalence arise precisely because of our ingrained habit of generalizing to animals. One reason why it s hard to think straight about animals is that animals is such a catch-all word. Sometimes, and for some species or individuals, we move the animal into our human family whether that is dogs living literally within our family home, or primates who we come to realize have cognitive abilities like ours. Some of the dilemmas Herzog documents arise when we disagree, or Lynda Birke Eat, Love, Hate

120 cannot make up our minds, about where (or if) boundaries might be drawn; it is practically impossible to be consistent about animals when we often make decisions about particular individuals or species, or in relation to specific (human) uses. One example: Herzog suggests that [i]f you really want to know how people feel about the treatment of animals, follow the money (40). He then goes on to note the large sums of money given to animal protection organizations, but notes that far more money is put into killing animals buying hunting supplies, the meat industry, pest control, and so on. We are inconsistent about animals in part because we make distinctions between them. It is almost impossible to avoid collapsing species variation into the generic animal in Herzog s book, or, indeed, in this review. But it is an issue which human-animal studies needs to grapple with more explicitly and which I would like to have seen brought out more in this book, if only to clarify when we are being inconsistent about animals or about specific species or types. What is being accomplished when we use the animal word? Quibbles aside, what the book acknowledges is how so many of us feel a deep need and connection to the nonhumans around us. Herzog s book will no doubt have popular appeal for that very reason: but, as he notes, what we also learn from these studies is the very complexity of our attitudes towards others (be they others of any species, including our own). The anomalies and contradictions are, he concludes, inevitable, and they reveal that...our relationships with the animals in our lives the ones we love, the ones we hate, and the ones we eat are.more complicated than we thought (279). There is plenty of work, then, to be done in animal studies and animal activism if we are to understand those contradictions. Humanimalia: a journal of human/animal interface studies Volume 2, Number 2 (Spring 2011)