c:=} up over the question of a "Christian philosophy." Since it

Similar documents
Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica. Translated by The Fathers of the English Dominican Province [Benziger Bros. edition, 1947].

CHRISTIAN MORALITY: A MORALITY OF THE DMNE GOOD SUPREMELY LOVED ACCORDING TO jacques MARITAIN AND john PAUL II

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination

The Names of God. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 12-13) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006)

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII

Henry of Ghent on Divine Illumination

Nature and Grace in the First Question of the Summa

The Divine Nature. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 3-11) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian J.

The Evangelical Turn of John Paul II and Veritatis Splendor

A Brief Comparison between the Study of the Shroud and the Philosophical Inquiry on God

Alexander of Hales, The Sum of Theology 1 (translated by Oleg Bychkov) Introduction, Question One On the discipline of theology

The Nature and Extent of Sacred Doctrine Thomas Aquinas

In the Collège de France there is a lecture room whose seats. descend in rows to a desk on which a podium is flanked by two green

Peter L.P. Simpson December, 2012

Self-Evidence in Finnis Natural Law Theory: A Reply to Sayers

Anthony P. Andres. The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic. Anthony P. Andres

DICTIONARY OF SCHOLASTIC PHILOSOPHY BY BERNARD WUELLNER

QUESTION 54. An Angel s Cognition

Peter L.P. Simpson January, 2015

1/5. The Critique of Theology

REVIEW. St. Thomas Aquinas. By RALPH MCINERNY. The University of Notre Dame Press 1982 (reprint of Twayne Publishers 1977). Pp $5.95.

QUESTION 44. The Procession of Creatures from God, and the First Cause of All Beings

Introduction to Philosophy

Reading a Philosophy Text Philosophy 22 Fall, 2019

Since Michael so neatly summarized his objections in the form of three questions, all I need to do now is to answer these questions.

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION AND ARISTOTELIAN THEOLOGY TODAY

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

The Creation of the World in Time According to Fakhr al-razi

Scholasticism I INTRODUCTION

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

Thomas Aquinas on the World s Duration. Summa Theologiae Ia Q46: The Beginning of the Duration of Created Things

WHAT ARISTOTLE TAUGHT

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

2013 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved. 1

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY

IDOLATRY AND RELIGIOUS LANGUAGE

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

On the Relation of Philosophy to the Theology Conference Seward 11/24/98

Association of Hebrew Catholics Lecture Series The Mystery of Israel and the Church

On Truth Thomas Aquinas

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Nearly everyone, at one time or another, has an incredible

Chapter Six. Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality

The Catholic Moment in the Political Philosophy of. Leo Strauss. Copyright 2007 James R. Stoner, Jr.

ON EFFICIENT CAUSALITY: METAPHYSICAL DISPUTATIONS 17,18, AND 19. By FRANCISCO SUAREZ. Translated By ALFRED J. FREDDOSO. New Haven:

THE ANAL YTICO-SYNTHETIC METHOD IN THE THEODICY OF ST. THOMAS

MOTIVES OF CREDIBILITY

A Studying of Limitation of Epistemology as Basis of Toleration with Special Reference to John Locke

15 Does God have a Nature?

Sophia Perennis. by Frithjof Schuon

PHILOSOPHY 111: HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY EARLY MODERN Winter 2012

Page 6 WHAT IS GOD? 1A NATURE OF GOD: ABSOLUTE GOOD. "There is but one Presence and one Power in all the universe: God, the Good, Omnipotent"

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

St. Thomas Aquinas Excerpt from Summa Theologica

EUTHYPHRO, GOD S NATURE, AND THE QUESTION OF DIVINE ATTRIBUTES. An Analysis of the Very Complicated Doctrine of Divine Simplicity.

270 Now that we have settled these issues, we should answer the first question [n.

William Ockham on Universals

PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE LET THOMAS AQUINAS TEACH IT. Joseph Kenny, O.P. St. Thomas Aquinas Priory Ibadan, Nigeria

Aristotle and Aquinas

Peter L.P. Simpson December, 2012

THE INTERNAL TESTIMONY OF THE HOLY SPIRIT: HOW DO YOU KNOW THAT THE BIBLE IS GOD S WORD?

THE BELIEF IN GOD AND IMMORTALITY A Psychological, Anthropological and Statistical Study

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

Peter L.P. Simpson March, 2016

THE PREPARATION OE A LAY APOSTLE

Wisdom in Aristotle and Aquinas From Metaphysics to Mysticism Edmond Eh University of Saint Joseph, Macau

GREAT PHILOSOPHERS: Thomas Reid ( ) Peter West 25/09/18

Rationalist-Irrationalist Dialectic in Buddhism:

On Being and Essence (DE ENTE Et ESSENTIA)

The question is concerning truth and it is inquired first what truth is. Now

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

QUESTION 3. God s Simplicity

The Church: Teacher and Mother

Medieval Thought February Medieval Thought

Book Reviews. Rahim Acar, Marmara University

From Physics, by Aristotle

Introduction A CERTAIN LIGHTNESS IN EXISTENCE

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to

Who Has the Burden of Proof? Must the Christian Provide Adequate Reasons for Christian Beliefs?

Two Approaches to Natural Law;Note

Descartes: A Guide for the Perplexed

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

THE CHALLENGES FOR EARLY MODERN PHILOSOPHY: EDITORIAL INTRODUCTION 1. Steffen Ducheyne

RAHNER AND DEMYTHOLOGIZATION 555

Faith and Reason Thomas Aquinas

Today I would like to bring together a number of different questions into a single whole. We don't have

REFLECTIONS ON SPACE AND TIME

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Pope Francis presented the following reflection in his homily

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

Intellect and Faith in Tanya: The Never-Ending Circle. us to question, to doubt, to re-examine. Our faith causes us to do the exact opposite to

Creation & necessity

Predicate logic. Miguel Palomino Dpto. Sistemas Informáticos y Computación (UCM) Madrid Spain

Hume s An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding

- 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance

Sep. 1 Wed Introduction to the Middle Ages Dates; major thinkers; and historical context The nature of scripture (Revelation) and reason

ON JESUS, DERRIDA, AND DAWKINS: REJOINDER TO JOSHUA HARRIS

Transcription:

THE CHRISTIAN AND PHILOSOPHY The Problem (JOME twenty-five or thirty years ago a controversy flared c:=} up over the question of a "Christian philosophy." Since it had historical origins, the debate centered around two main issues: whether there ever was a philosophy that deserved the title "Christian," and whether such a designation is really ever valid. As is evident enough, once more the thorny problem of the relationship between faith and reason was resurrected. Philosophy is commonly known to be reason's pursuit of the knowledge of reality through its causes, while the name "Christian" implies faith in Christ or the Christian revelation. The difficulty shows itself immediately: how can philosophy be called "Christian" without compromising its very nature? Is not the interplay of faith and reason the domain of theology? The scholar at the center of the historical aspect of the controversy was Etienne Gilson. He maintained that Christianity did de facto develop a distinctively Christian philosophy. Anyone in the least familiar with M. Gilson's monumental works on the philosophy of the Middle Ages will realize with what dedication and erudition he defends this thesis. Even today he works zealously for a restoration of this "Christian" philosophy. For his labors Anton C. Pegis has called him the "disciple of Christian philosophy"; the "apostle of Christian philosophy" would not be unmerited. Just as M. Gilson was and is the historian of Christian philosophy, Jacques 1\faritain was and is its theoretician. In many books and articles he has analyzed and defended the possibility of a truly Christian philosophy. Indeed, he insists that not only can there be but there must be a Christian philosophy. Many other eminent scholars have taken sides in this debate. Yet we have explicitly cited only Messrs. Gilson and Maritain for a purpose. Of all the contemporary Thomist philosophers, these

The Christian and Philosophy 57 two are probably the most widely read and respected. From the point of view of popularity alone, it would seem that these defenders of Christian philosophy have won the day. But the fact is that this very widespread diffusion of their ideas calls for a reappraisal of the fundamentals of the question. This is what we shall attempt in this article. However, two things should be noted in the beginning. First of all, the question has many ramifications and side issues too numerous even to mention here. Therefore we shall consider mainly the validity of the term "Christian philosophy." Secondly, it should be borne in mind that this is a theological and not a philosophical problem. This seems odd in light of the fact that the dispute has chiefly concerned philosophers. Yet it pertains to philosophy, or rather that part of philosophy which is natural wisdom or metaphysics to determine only its own nature and the nature of the other rational sciences inferior to it. \Vhen a question of the rapport of faith and reason arises, as is this, natural wisdom is not capable of judging such matters. Rather it pertains to a higher wisdom, sacred theology. Theology has the right and duty to judge, order and use all rational sciences since they are inferior to it. 1 In other words, to determine how Christian philosophy can be pertains to that wisdom which has competency both in the area of reason and revelation, the wisdom that is theology. Towards a Solution Before attempting to arrive at a balanced judgment, we should first line up some necessary distinctions. First, we know by faith, especially as it was clearly expounded at the Vatican Council, that God in His mercy chose to reveal both truths about Himself of the supernatural order completely beyond the natural capacities of man, such as the mystery of the Trinity, and also truths of the natural order which can be attained by reason alone, as the fact of divine Providence. Obviously we are not concerned here with revealed supernatural truths because with these philosophy as such has no competency at all. However, in the realm of revealed natural truths the domains of faith and reason overlap. In short, there is an area of truth which can be the object of faith or the object of philosophical speculation. Also, we might make use of a distinction proposed by 11. Maritain between philosophy according to its nature and philosophy according to its state or condition of existence. 2 Philosophy according to its nature would be an abstract consideration of phi-

58 Dominicana losophy as such. So taken, there is no problem of a philosophy that is Christian or not for philosophy essentially and as pure philosophy is solely a work of human reason; it includes nothing of divine faith or revelation in its essence. But philosophy does not grow up in a pure and abstract state. It is realized in certain conditions of existence, in this or that milieu. In this latter sense we can quite validly speak of philosophy in a Christian or pre-christian setting, much as we speak of medieval and Greek philosophy. Now our quest focuses on this: should philosophy in a Christian setting be so influenced by the natural truths obtained from reve~ lation as to be validly called Christian philosophy? To deny any and all influence of revelation on philosophy would be an extreme and somewhat impossible position. It would amount to an overstatement of the autonomy of philosophy and a confession of blindness to historical reality. Neither does it seem doctrinally sound in the light of Pius IX's condemnation of the proposition that "philosophy is to be treated without any regard to supernatural revelation." 3 Yet to submit philosophy to an unlimited influence would destroy the very nature of philosophy. The same Pope defended the autonomy and independence of philosophy with regard to these revealed truths in a letter to the Archbishop of Munich, Gravissimas inter, in 1862: Moreover, philosophy's task is to ascertain the object of rational knowledge and many truths, to understand them well and to look to their progress. By means of arguments sought from reason's own principles, philosophy should demonstrate, vindicate, and defend a large number of these truths which faith also proposes for belief ; such as the existence of God, His nature, and His attributes.4 The important phrase to note is "by means of arguments sought from reason's own principles." Thus philosophy, even in its concrete realization in a Christian setting, can and must proceed according to its proper method and principles. No influence can be such that philosophy is forced to abandon these, for in so doing it would cease to exist. Now we can ask about the possible extent of Christian influence, safeguarding at the same time the very existence of philosophy. St. Thomas, in considering the fittingness of the revelation of truths of the natural order, states that without such a revelation these truths would be attained unaided only by a certain few, after a long time, and with much error involved. 5 History is witness to the veracity of this. Especially in order to avoid error, faith in these truths should serve at least as a negative guide for the philosopher. Should there arise any conflict between what an

The Christian and Philosophy 59 all-knowing God has revealed and fallible human reason has attained, the cause evidently is faulty reasoning which is false philosophy. To deny faith such a negative influence on philosophy would be absurdly unrealistic. But what of any positive influence? Can the revealed natural truths be received into philosophy as objective data? If philosophy incorporated such data into its development solely because it was revealed by God, it would be acting contrary to its own principles and method and thus not be philosophy at all. A truth can be the object of faith or the object of science. But it cannot be both at the same time for the same person. We cannot at the same time believe and know a thing scientifically. Faith, as is stated in the Epistle to the Hebrews, is "the evidence of things that are not seen." Because a thing is "not seen" we can assent to it on someone's authority, or to use a common expression, "take someone's word for it." Once this is seen, once we prove its existence, faith ceases with regard to it for the truth has become evident in itself and recourse to authority is no longer the motive of our assent. So, to assent to a truth on divine authority is quite simply an act of divine faith; to "philosophize'' about a truth so accepted is really to theologize. Yet there is no valid objection against such truths being positive, objective guides for philosophy. Let us exemplify what we mean. In his consideration of the knowledge of God in the Metaphysics, Aristotle reasons that the object of divine thought must be God Himself, that "it must be of itself that the divine thought thinks" (XII, 9, 1074b 34). But he hesitates to say that God knows things other than himself. "Are there not some things about which it is incredible that it (the divine thought) should think?" (1074b 25) For a Christian, it is manifest in Scripture that God knows all things. "And there is no creature hidden from his sight; but all things are naked and open to the eyes of him to whom we have to give an account" (Heb. 4 :13). So, in following Aristotle's development of metaphysics, we should have to deny the incredibility of God's knowing some things other than himself and search out the fallacy behind such a statement-here, the negative influence of faith. Then we might consider philosophically the omniscience of God by showing how God in knowing himself must know all other things, depending for our proof on the principles set out by Aristotle-here, the positive influence of faith. Faith in this truth can and did serve as a positive guide for the assimilation of it into Aristotelian metaphysics in a rationally demonstra-

60 Dominieana tive way. But this truth and all such revealed natural truths, once assimilated, are no longer objects of faith but philosophical truths known as conclusions of rational proofs. Also, it is important to note that this negative and positive influence upon philosophy is an extrinsic influence. In other words, the truths precisely as revealed, or as objects of faith, remain outside the pale of philosophical progress. They enter properly into philosophy only when established according to th.e order and method proper to philosophy ; then they cease to be objects of faith. Thus it should be evident that these truths, precisely as revealed or as objects of faith, cannot properly exert an intrinsic influence on philosophy itself if the latter is to remain philosophy. Now what of the term "Christian philosophy"? \Ve must admit that all that has been said so far of the legitimate impact of faith upon philosophy is rather the influence of faith upon the philosopher. Christianity could leave no mark upon the philosophy, or rather the philosophical writings of Plato and Aristotle simply because they were not Christians and lived in pre-christian times. There is a Christian influence in the scholastic development of Plato and Aristotle precisely because the scholastics were believers. Thus they could correct and perfect Greek philosophy. Also, faith exercises a negative influence on philosophers rather than on philosophy since any error in reasoning to be corrected by faith cannot be ascribed to philosophy but to the philosopher. The revealed natural truths are a positive guide for the philosopher and not philosophy since it is not because of the deficiency of philosophy to arrive at these truths that they were fittingly revealed, but rather because of the "weakness of our intellect in judging."6 In short, the distinction between philosophy according to its nature and philosophy according to its state or conditions of existence should rather be a distinction between philosophy and philosopher. The uniting of philosophy and Christianity in the concrete is the union of the Christian and the philosopher. As such it is an accidental union. There are Christian mathematicians but they are not Christian because they are mathematicians. Nor are they mathematicians because they are Christians. The same is also true of Christian philosophers. Yet it is possible, all things being equal, to be better philosophers because we are Christians since a Christian should have all the advantages of a life of grace and virtue, no small aid in philosophizing. By the same token, we should also be better mathematicians and anything else that re-

The Christi n and Philosophy 61 quires intense effort and dedication. However, in the last analysis, it is more precise, and thus more philosophical, to speak of philosophy and Christian philosophers rather than Christian philosophy. Summary and Review It is an undeniable fact that Christianity influenced greatly the historical evolution of philosophy, but this influence was extrinsic to philosophy itself and thus indirect. Because of the revelation of certain natural truths, it was possible for the Christian thinkers to correct false philosophical notions handed down to them and also to expand the philosophy of their antecedents by "\vorking certain revealed natural truths into the philosophical synthesis according to philosophy's own method and principles. Christianity also made better men, and thus better thinkers, of philosophers. Yet, great as this influence "\vas and is, it does not so affect the philosopher that he elaborates a Christian philosophy in any formal sense. Rather, it helps his philosophy to be true. Because of all the necessary distinctions and reservations involved, it is far more precise and exact to speak of Christian philosophers; Christian philosophy is a deceptive term that is open to much misunderstanding. In this context, it would be more than rash for us to contest the veracity of M. Gilson's historical studies. He is undoubtedly a great scholar and his works are deservedly well-respected. However, we might question his interpretation of the facts. In short, we might question his definition of 01ristian philosophy. In The Spirit of Medieval Philosophy he tells us, "Thus I call Christian every philosophy which although keeping the two orders (natural and supernatural) formally distinct, nevertheless considers the Christian revelation as an indispensable auxiliary to reason" (p. 37). Such a definition has manifest theological overtones. Philosophy has no capacity for even considering the supernatural order let alone distinguishing it from the natural order. Again it is not equipped to deal with Christian revelation as such ; hence it is unable to analyze it and see it as an indispensable auxiliary to reason. Nor is this criticism a minimizing of philosophy. It is a safeguarding of a very valid and necessary system of thought. M. Gilson will quote St. Paul, non erubesco evangelium, as he advises a restoration of the "several scholastic philosophies to their natural places-namely, their natal theologies... "At this point the Christian philosopher might also quote St. Paul. "For since the creation of the world his invisible attributes are clearly seen

62 Dominicana -his everlasting power also and divinity-being understood through the things that are made" (Rom. 1 :20). No Christian should be "ashamed of the gospel"; neither should he scorn the God-given gift of reason. -Justin M. Cunningham, O.P. FOOTNOTES 1 cf. In I Sent., q. I, Prolog. a. I; Summa. Theol., I, q. 1, a. 5, ad 2; In Boet. De Trinitate, q. 2, a. 3, ad 7. 2 cf. Science and Wisdom, p. 79. 3 Denzinger, Enchiridion Symbolomm, 1714: Philosophia tractanda est JJ'Ulla supernaturalis revelationis habita ratione. 4 The Church Teaches No. 46. 5 cf. Summa Contra Gentes, I, 4. 6 Ibid.