Kripke s skeptical paradox

Similar documents
Now consider a verb - like is pretty. Does this also stand for something?

KRIPKE ON WITTGENSTEIN. Pippa Schwarzkopf

Hannah Ginsborg, University of California, Berkeley

The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World. In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages, Kripke expands upon a conclusion

A CRITIQUE OF KRIPKE S FINITUDE ARGUMENT. In Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language [WRPL], Kripke interprets Wittgenstein as

Kripke s Wittgenstein s Sceptical Solution and Donald Davidson s Philosophy of Language. Ali Hossein Khani

MEANING AND RULE-FOLLOWING. Richard Holton

WITTGENSTEIN S PRIVATE LANGUAGE ARGUMENT ACCORDING TO KRIPKE. Wittgenstein according to Kripke 1

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Wittgenstein and the Skeptical Paradoxes

Comments on Saul Kripke s Philosophical Troubles

The Indeterminacy of Translation: Fifty Years Later

A Priori Bootstrapping

Is mental content prior to linguistic meaning?

(Correctness) If S is following rule R, then S acts correctly relative to his acceptance if it is the case that C and he does A.

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Mathematics as we know it has been created and used by

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

2.1 Review. 2.2 Inference and justifications

Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames. sentence, or the content of a representational mental state, involves knowing which

In hiswittgenstein on Rules and Private Language, SaulKripkedevelops

15 Does God have a Nature?

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Normativity and Concepts. Hannah Ginsborg, U.C. Berkeley. June 2016

The Paradox of the Question

The normativity of content and the Frege point

The Problem of the External World

Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth

This is a longer version of the review that appeared in Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 47 (1997)

On Dispositional HOT Theories of Consciousness

Belief, Rationality and Psychophysical Laws. blurring the distinction between two of these ways. Indeed, it will be argued here that no

Book Reviews 1175 Oughts and Thoughts: Rule-Following and the Normativity of Content, by Anandi Hattiangadi. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp

Stout s teleological theory of action

A CRITICAL EVALUATION OF KRIPKE S INTERPRETATION OF WITTGENSTEIN

In Defense of the Ideal

The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 34, No. 136, Special Issue: Frege. (Jul., 1984), pp

Structure and essence: The keys to integrating spirituality and science

McDowell s Realism Paul Broadbent

Constructing the World

Magic, semantics, and Putnam s vat brains

Ryle on Systematically Misleading Expresssions

Epistemic two-dimensionalism

Analyticity and reference determiners

Review of Peter Hanks Propositional Content Indrek Reiland

Propositions as Cambridge properties

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Fundamentals of Metaphysics

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

Pictures, Proofs, and Mathematical Practice : Reply to James Robert Brown

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

DO YOU KNOW THAT THE DIGITS HAVE AN END? Mohamed Ababou. Translated by: Nafissa Atlagh

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

DOES STRONG COMPATIBILISM SURVIVE FRANKFURT COUNTER-EXAMPLES?

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

The Normativity of the Intentional. Ralph Wedgwood. Many philosophers have claimed that the intentional is normative. (This claim is the

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract

The St. Petersburg paradox & the two envelope paradox

What Numbers Might Be Scott Soames. John's anti-nominalism embraces numbers without, as far as I know, worrying very

What Makes Someone s Life Go Best from Reasons and Persons by Derek Parfit (1984)

WHY WE REALLY CANNOT BELIEVE THE ERROR THEORY

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

Objections to the two-dimensionalism of The Conscious Mind

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

It is advisable to refer to the publisher s version if you intend to cite from the work.

The stated objective of Gloria Origgi s paper Epistemic Injustice and Epistemic Trust is:

Varieties of Apriority

Brief Remarks on Putnam and Realism in Mathematics * Charles Parsons. Hilary Putnam has through much of his philosophical life meditated on

The Rejection of Skepticism

REFERENCE AND MODALITY. An Introduction to Naming and Necessity

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Philosophy of Religion: Hume on Natural Religion. Phil 255 Dr Christian Coseru Wednesday, April 12

Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification?

Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology

Structuralism in the Philosophy of Mathematics

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Objectivity CHRISTOPHER PEACOCKE

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Four Arguments that the Cognitive Psychology of Religion Undermines the Justification of Religious Belief

An argument against descriptive Millianism

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

Class #3 - Meinong and Mill

ZAGZEBSKI ON RATIONALITY

KRIPKE'S DOUBTS ABOUT MEANING

Perceiving Abstract Objects

Trinity & contradiction

Undoing the Truth Fetish: The Normative Path to Pragmatism. Shamik Dasgupta Draft of January 2019

Linguistic Meaning and the Privacy Constraint: On Davidson's Quine, Kripke's Wittgenstein and Brandom 1

THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY

Russell s Problems of Philosophy

Lecture 38 CARTESIAN THEORY OF MIND REVISITED Overview. Key words: Cartesian Mind, Thought, Understanding, Computationality, and Noncomputationality.

The Externalist and the Structuralist Responses To Skepticism. David Chalmers

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Assertion and Inference

Transcription:

Kripke s skeptical paradox phil 93914 Jeff Speaks March 13, 2008 1 The paradox.................................... 1 2 Proposed solutions to the paradox....................... 3 2.1 Meaning as determined by past use of words.............. 3 2.2 Meaning as determined by rules or algorithms............. 3 2.3 Meaning as determined by dispositions to use words in certain ways. 3 2.3.1 The simple dispositional theory.................. 3 2.3.2 The community-wide dispositional theory............ 4 2.3.3 The counterfactual dispositional theory............. 5 2.3.4 The whatever-it-takes dispositional theory........... 5 2.4 Meaning as determined by machine program............. 6 2.4.1 Machine as physical object.................... 6 2.4.2 Machine as instantiated program or algorithm......... 6 2.5 Meaning as determined by simplicity.................. 6 2.6 Meaning as determined by irreducible meaning-experiences...... 7 2.7 Meaning as a Platonic Fregean sense.................. 7 1 The paradox Wittgenstein stated his famous rule-following paradox as follows: this was our paradox: no course of action could be determined by a rule, because every course of action can be made out to accord with the rule. This is the paradox that Kripke develops in this essay via the example of plus and quus. Plus and quus are mathematical functions, which we can symbolize as + and respectively. Plus, or the addition function, is defined in the usual way. The quus function is the same as the addition or plus function for low arguments, but diverges past a certain point. More specifically, it is defined as follows: x y = x+y if x, y < 57 x y = 5 otherwise

The skeptical question is: in the past, by the symbol +, did you mean plus or quus? (The focus on the past is just a simplifying device, to allow us to now talk unambiguously about these two functions.) This question is a way of raising the paradox mentioned by Wittgenstein because it seems that any evidence cited in support of the claim that I meant plus in the past is also consistent with my meaning quus; thus, the skeptic argues, it seems that there is no fact of the matter about whether I meant plus or quus. But if this is the case, then presumably the problem of general, and there are no facts about meaning at all. The problem is is not, at least in the first instance, any sort of skepticism about mathematics. We can see the skeptic as granting that both plus and quus are perfectly well-defined arithmetic functions. The skepticism is about meaning rather than mathematics: it is about how we know which of these two well-defined functions is, or was, attached to the symbol +. As Kripke thinks of it, the skeptical challenge really has two parts: 1. Is there any fact that I meant plus, not quus? In what did my meaning plus rather than quus consist? 2. Do I now have any reason to be confident that I should answer 125 rather than 5 to 68+57, given that I now want to be consistent with my past intentions? This raises a few questions. The first is about the nature of the first version of the skeptical challenge. What does it mean to ask what a fact consists in? Does this sort of question make sense? Should we think that questions like this always have answers? If not, do they ever have answers? Compare: In what does being someone s granddaughter consist? In what does being water consist? In what does your knowing something, rather than just believing it, consist? In what does personal identity consist? In what does being red consist? What are the constraints on answers to questions like this? A second question about the nature of the skeptical challenge concerns the relationship between the two versions of the challenge Kripke identifies. Kripke himself takes the second question to put a constraint on answers to the first: whatever fact constitutes the fact that means plus rather than quus should be able to make sense of my being justified in making arithmetical judgements that presuppose my meaning plus rather than quus. Is this a reasonable requirement on answers to the skeptical challenge? 2

The bulk of the book is a consideration, and rejection, of a host of proposed answers to the skeptical challenge. Understanding Kripke s arguments against these proposed answers gives a good idea of the sorts of challenges that proposed solutions to the problem of intentionality encounter. 2 Proposed solutions to the paradox 2.1 Meaning as determined by past use of words Claim: the fact that I meant addition by + consists in the fact that I used + as a symbol for the addition function; i.e., I held true just those equations involving + which are made true by letting + stand for the addition function. Skeptical reply: Even supposing that you made no mistakes, in the past you held true only a finite number of equations involving +. But the addition function is not the only function which can make these equations true; there are an infinite number of functions which make true the equations you held true involving +. And among these infinitely many functions is the quus function. 2.2 Meaning as determined by rules or algorithms Claim: the fact that I meant addition by + consists in the fact that I adopted certain rules, or algorithms, to govern my use of + ; and these algorithms single out the addition function. Skeptical reply 1: this is just to give a rule for interpreting a rule. And just as the skeptic can give a skeptical reinterpretation of one expression (the + sign) so he can also give a skeptical reinterpretation of the expressions used in stating the rule for the interpretation of +. The presumption is that each of these expressions may be reinterpreted to preserve the skeptical hypothesis that in the past you meant quaddition by +. Skeptical reply 2: in fact, many people mean addition by + without doing anything so sophisticated as mastering algorithms for or recursive definitions of addition. So association with an algorithm is not a plausible candidate for the fact that a speaker means addition by +. 2.3 Meaning as determined by dispositions to use words in certain ways 2.3.1 The simple dispositional theory Claim: the fact that I meant addition by + consists in the fact that I was disposed, when presented with any expression x + y to respond with the sum of x and y (rather than their quum). This has an obvious advantage over the claim that meaning 3

consists in actual past usage. After all, even if I never considered the expression 68 + 57 before, I surely was disposed to accept 68 + 57 = 125. Skeptical reply 1: Error. Typically we are not disposed to respond to every instance of x + y with the sum of x and y: everyone is disposed, in at least some cases, to make mistakes. But then it follows that if the function attached to + is determined by the equations involving + which we are disposed to accept, we do not mean addition by +. Skeptical reply 2: Finitude. We are finite creatures capable only of understanding numbers of limited size; so not only my actual performance, but also the totality of my dispositions, is finite (26). But the addition function is defined over numbers of arbitrary size. So, once again, the dispositional theory delivers the wrong result: if our dispositions for using + really did determine the function attached to it, then the function expressed by + would apply to only numbers small enough for us to grasp. But addition is not like this. Skeptical reply 3: Normativity. The dispositionalist tries to explain the nature of meaning in terms of what we are disposed to do. But, Kripke says, this is the wrong sort of answer. He says: Suppose I do mean addition by +. What is the relation of this supposition to the question how I will respond to the problem 68 + 57? The dispositionalist gives a descriptive account of this relation: if + meant addition, then I will answer 125. But this is not the proper account of the relation, which is normative, not descriptive. The point is not that, if I meant addition by +, I will answer 125, but that, if I intend to accord with my past meaning of +, I should answer 125.... The relation of meaning and intention to future action is normative, not descriptive (37). We should be clear about two points about this objection. (i) It is supposed to explain why the error and finitude objections get their force. (ii) It is closely related to the second form of the skeptic s challenge, that of explaining how we are justified in answering 125 when queried with 68 + 57. The idea is that even if we knew our past dispositions, this would not be enough to justify our view that 125 is the correct answer. (See on point (ii) pp. 23-24.) This objection is not easy to understand, and we ll be coming back to what it might mean to say that meaning is normative. 2.3.2 The community-wide dispositional theory Claim: the fact that I meant addition by + consists in the fact that most or all members of my linguistic community were disposed, when presented with any expression x + y to respond with the sum of x and y (rather than their quum). This has some advantage over the individualistic dispositional theory: it gets rid of some cases of error, and, sometimes, if we imagine a possible linguistic community diverging in 4

their judgements in sufficiently systematic ways from ours, we also imagine the meanings of their terms as different from ours. This fits nicely with the community-wide version of the dispositional theory. Skeptical reply 1: Community-wide error. This doesn t seem to solve all cases of error. Skeptical reply 2: Finitude. If this is a good objection to the simple dispositional theory, it applies equally well here. Skeptical reply 3: Normativity. Ditto. 2.3.3 The counterfactual dispositional theory Claim: the fact that I meant addition by + consists in the fact that, were my brain expanded or were my cognitive capacities massively increased, I would have been disposed, when presented with any expression x + y to respond with the sum of x and y (rather than their quum). So on this view facts about meaning consist not in what people are or were disposed to do, but in what they would have been disposed to do, had certain conditions been fulfilled. Skeptical reply 1: Science fiction. This makes facts about meaning hostage to claims about what would have happened had the world been changed in certain radical ways. But really we have no idea what the world would have been like in such settings. (There s a connection here with the idea that any answer to the skeptical challenge should provide facts which can justify our answers to addition questions.) Skeptical reply 2: Normativity. See above. 2.3.4 The whatever-it-takes dispositional theory Claim: the fact that I meant addition by + consists in the fact that, were I free from mistakes, I would have been disposed, when presented with any expression x + y to respond with the sum of x and y (rather than their quum). Skeptical reply 1: this is circular. The skeptic is challenging you to say what the facts are in virtue of which you meant addition rather than quaddition by +. If you appeal to facts about what you would have said had you not made any mistakes, the skeptic will say that in such a situation you would have been correct to answer 5 to 68 + 57 since, after all, you mean quaddition all along. To rule this out you must assume that you meant addition, which is of course the point at issue. (See pp. 27-28.) Skeptical reply 2: Normativity. (Again.) 5

2.4 Meaning as determined by machine program Claim: Machines can be built to embody functions; in particular, they can be built to embody the addition function. (Just think of a calculator.) But if a machine can be built to embody the addition function, then surely human beings, which are relevantly like complex machines, can do so as well. A machine can follow this rule; whence does a human being gain a freedom of choice in this matter which a machine does not possess? (Dummett, quoted p. 32) As we ll see, there are two different versions of this response to the skeptic. 2.4.1 Machine as physical object Claim: a machine like a calculator embodies the addition function just in case when given two numbers as input, the machine spits out their sum (rather than their quum). Skeptical reply: This is just a version of the dispositionalist s response, and open to the same objections. In particular, calculators like human beings are finite, and are prone to breakdown (error). 2.4.2 Machine as instantiated program or algorithm Claim: But cases in which machines break down are cases in which they fail to act as they were programmed to act. So when it is said that a machine can embody the addition function, what is meant is not that some particular physical machine or other can embody it, but rather that a computer program can embody it. Skeptical reply: This is just a version of the view, discussed above, that the meaning of + for me is determined by which algorithm or rule I associate with the symbol. That is to say that this is just giving a rule for interpreting a rule, which is open to the objections discussed above. 2.5 Meaning as determined by simplicity Claim: It is true that my dispositions do not single out the addition function as the meaning of +. But the addition function is the simplest function similar enough to my dispositions. (Quaddition seems a more complex function perhaps because it is defined in terms of addition.) I mean addition by + in part because of my dispositions and in part because when there is indeterminacy between an expression meaning one of several things, the simplest of these things is automatically assigned as the meaning. (For relevant discussion, see footnote 25 rather than the confused discussion on pp. 38-39. Kripke is right that using simplicity alone to solve the skeptical problem makes 6

no sense; but presumably the relevant version of the idea uses simplicity along with something like the dispositional solution, to decide between alternate interpretations of + between which the version of the dispositional solution in question does not decide.) Skeptical reply 1: Problems defining simplicity. Skeptical reply 2: Seems on the wrong track. Would we decide that we didn t mean addition by + if we found out that, according to the true measure of simplicity, quaddition was simpler than addition? Skeptical reply 3: This reply is ill-suited to answer the justificatory problem raised by the skeptic; I do not justify my choice of 125 rather than 5... by citing a hypothetical simplicity measure of the kind mentioned (p. 40). 2.6 Meaning as determined by irreducible meaning-experiences Claim: Meaning addition by + is having a certain introspectible experience, like a headache (except, presumably, more subtle), upon using + with this meaning. This view has the significant advantage that it can explain how we know that we mean addition by +. Skeptical reply 1: But it cannot explain how we can be so sure that we should answer 125 rather than 5. Even if we had a special headache associated with meaning addition by +, how would this headache tell us how to answer? Skeptical reply 2: It does not seem that there is any such introspectible experience. (If there were such, how could the skeptic s challenge have seemed difficult in the first place?) 2.7 Meaning as a Platonic Fregean sense Claim: Meanings - including the meaning of + - are abstract objects in Frege s third realm, and thus are not contained in anyone s minds. It is simply in the nature of such abstract objects to determine their reference: so it is simply in the nature of the addition function to imply that 125 is the right answer to 67 + 58. Skeptical reply: This is not to the point. Granted, once we have the result that the addition function is the meaning of +, there is no further problem about why 125 is the right answer to 68 + 57. But the skeptic s challenge is to show us how the addition function gets to be the meaning of + in the first place. 7