Conservative Pragmatism, Pragmatic Conservatism

Similar documents
Pihlström, Sami Johannes.

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

What Should We Believe?

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

There is no need to explain who Hilary Putnam is in light of the sheer number of books and articles on his work that have appeared over the past

Roman Madzia. Education and Culture 30 (2) (2014):

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Religious Studies. Name: Institution: Course: Date:

Metaphysical Pluralism: James and the Neo-Pragmatists

Book Review. The Cambridge Companion to Dewey. Justin Bell

LIBERTY: RETHINKING AN IMPERILED IDEAL. By Glenn Tinder. William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company Pp. xiv, 407. $ ISBN: X.

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

Contingency, Meliorism and Fate. Henrik Rydenfelt University of Helsinki

How Successful Is Naturalism?

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

Pragmatism s Alternative to Foundationalism and Relativism. Introduction

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God

ELEONORE STUMP PENELHUM ON SKEPTICS AND FIDEISTS

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

1/8. Introduction to Kant: The Project of Critique

Care of the Soul: Service-Learning and the Value of the Humanities

Gestures in the Making

Process Thought and Bridge Building: A Response to Stephen K. White. Kevin Schilbrack

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo

Moore s paradoxes, Evans s principle and self-knowledge

An Article for Encyclopedia of American Philosophy on: Robert Cummings Neville. Wesley J. Wildman Boston University December 1, 2005

World Religions. These subject guidelines should be read in conjunction with the Introduction, Outline and Details all essays sections of this guide.


Kelly James Clark and Raymond VanArragon (eds.), Evidence and Religious Belief, Oxford UP, 2011, 240pp., $65.00 (hbk), ISBN

Spinoza and Spinozism. By STUART HAMPSHIRE. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2005.

Comments on Scott Soames, Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, volume I

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Chapter Summaries: Introduction to Christian Philosophy by Clark, Chapter 1

PHILOSOPHY OF LIFELONG EDUCATION Kenneth Wain London: Croom Helm.

Naturalism Without Reductionism. A Pragmatist Account of Religion. Dr. des. Ana Honnacker, Goethe University Frankfurt a. M.

On Liberty by John Stuart Mill

Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to The Theory of Knowledge, by Robert Audi. New York: Routledge, 2011.

Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work on

[MJTM 14 ( )] BOOK REVIEW

Well-Being, Disability, and the Mere-Difference Thesis. Jennifer Hawkins Duke University

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

RELATED SCHOLARLY PUBLICATIONS ON JAMES November 2017 May 2018

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

Adam Smith and the Limits of Empiricism

Proposal for: The Possibility of Philosophical Understanding: Essays for Barry Stroud

Yes But is it a Naturalism?

IN his preface to Lyrical Ballads, William Wordsworth noted that,

Ethical Colonialism Joseph C. Pitt Virginia Tech

From tolerance to neutrality: A tacit schism

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth).

Maverick Scholarship and the Apocrypha. FARMS Review 19/2 (2007): (print), (online)

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

Others may concern the reliability of methods for forming belief:

Philosophy Courses-1

Why Open-mindedness Matters

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

Putnam, Koethe, and Metaphysical Realism

THE ENLIGHTENMENT. 1. Alas, Dead White Males again

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

RESPONSES TO AIKIN AND KASSER MICHAEL R. SLATER

Seitz, Christopher R. Prophecy and Hermeneutics: Toward a New Introduction to the Prophets. Grand Rapids: Baker Academic, pp. $23.00.

Response to The Problem of the Question About Animal Ethics by Michal Piekarski

AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING

VIEWING PERSPECTIVES

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

Rorty on the Priority of Democracy to Philosophy

RECENT WORK THE MINIMAL DEFINITION AND METHODOLOGY OF COMPARATIVE PHILOSOPHY: A REPORT FROM A CONFERENCE STEPHEN C. ANGLE

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Public Reason in the Open Society

Gale on a Pragmatic Argument for Religious Belief

Mark Coeckelbergh: Growing Moral Relations. Critique of Moral Status Ascription

A DILEMMA FOR JAMES S JUSTIFICATION OF FAITH SCOTT F. AIKIN

Roy F. Melugin Brite Divinity School, Texas Christian University Fort Worth, TX 76129

Précis of Democracy and Moral Conflict

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

BOOK REVIEWS. The arguments of the Parmenides, though they do not refute the Theory of Forms, do expose certain problems, ambiguities and

Philosophy Courses-1

PROSPECTS FOR A JAMESIAN EXPRESSIVISM 1 JEFF KASSER

The Pluralist Predicament

Response to Gavin Flood, "Reflections on Tradition and Inquiry in the Study of Religion"

Delusions and Other Irrational Beliefs Lisa Bortolotti OUP, Oxford, 2010

Reading Questions for Phil , Fall 2016 (Daniel)

Huemer s Problem of Memory Knowledge

이찬희.

Liberal Arts Traditions and Christian Higher Education

Habermas and Critical Thinking

Varieties of Apriority

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Dewey s Situational Theory of Science

Should We Assess the Basic Premises of an Argument for Truth or Acceptability?

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

MARK KAPLAN AND LAWRENCE SKLAR. Received 2 February, 1976) Surely an aim of science is the discovery of the truth. Truth may not be the

An Empiricist Theory of Knowledge Bruce Aune

Transcription:

Review Essay Conservative Pragmatism, Pragmatic Conservatism William F. Byrne St. John s University Conservatism and Pragmatism in Law, Politics, and Ethics, by Seth Vannatta. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2014. 277 pp. $95 hardcover, $39.99 softcover. The proper moral and epistemological grounding for politics, once a topic of considerable interest, has seen relatively little serious study in recent years. Seth Vannatta s Conservatism and Pragmatism is a partial corrective to this neglect. As the title suggests, this broad study explores various aspects of the relationship between conservatism and philosophical pragmatism. Though both a comparative and a synthetic work, it is predominantly a re-thinking of pragmatism that argues that the pragmatic method is guided by conservative norms (4). It is when it holds to this focus that the book is at its best. More broadly, one goal throughout this work... is to show that while the conservative tradition is not one that treats past custom as the only norm operative in social and political conflict, the pragmatist tradition is not one which treats future ends as the only operative norm. Both are transactive with the past and the imagined future (120). The relationship between pragmatism and conservatism has been a rocky one. Obvious affinities exist between elements of Conservatism and pragmatism are both transactive with the past and the imagined future. Wil l i a m F. By r n e is Associate Professor of Government and Politics at St. John s University. Conservative Pragmatism, Pragmatic Conservatism Humanitas 97

Pragmatism rejects the use of a priori truths and adopts an experimental approach to morality and the good order. the work of, for example, Michael Oakeshott, and philosophical pragmatists like John Dewey. Claes Ryn s early mentor, the Swedish philosopher Folke Leander, did notable work on Dewey s thought, and Ryn has included favorable treatment of aspects of Dewey in some of his own work. 1 Nevertheless, to the extent that there has been anything resembling dialog between conservatives and pragmatists, it has generally not been warm. In fact, when conservatives pay any attention at all to philosophical pragmatism, it is usually with hostility. This may be attributed in part (though only in part) to the fact that some of the most prominent pragmatists have been progressives, while most self-identified conservatives are, well, conservative. Vannatta s new study serves as a valuable alternative to this mixture of antipathy and neglect. Though it comes much more from a pragmatist perspective than from a conservative one, it offers an opportunity for conservatives to re-engage, or perhaps to engage for the first time, with philosophical pragmatism. Both pragmatism and conservatism represent alternatives to typical Enlightenment rationalism, as well as to some classical thought. Vannatta s treatment of pragmatism draws on a variety of thinkers including Dewey, Charles Sanders Peirce, Oliver Wendell Holmes, and Jane Addams. Pragmatism, like much conservative thought, recognizes that philosophy always emerges in a cultural situation for some purpose whose origins are not entirely free from the historically inherited social and political values of time and place (117). From this perspective, pragmatism rejects the use of a priori truths and instead adopts an experimental, essentially nominalist approach to morality and the good order. Vannatta quotes Dewey: The hypothesis that works is the true one; and truth is an abstract noun applied to the collection of cases, actual, foreseen and desired, that receive confirmation in their works and consequences (120). Dewey and Vannatta are correct that it is through observation of how ideas play out in the world 1 Folke Leander s primary relevant work is: The Philosophy of John Dewey: A Critical Study (Gothenburg: Elanders Printing Company, 1939). Among the places where Ryn provides some treatment of Dewey is A Common Human Ground: Universality and Particularity in a Multicultural World (Columbia, Mo.: University of Missouri Press, 2003). Neither Leander s nor Ryn s treatment of Dewey is referenced in Conservatism and Pragmatism. 98 Volume XXIX, Nos. 1 and 2, 2016 William F. Byrne

that we get a handle on truth. A common error of ideologues of all sorts is their tendency to warp their perceptions of reality in order to keep facts in line with preferred a priori concepts and theories. Vannatta notes appropriately that Burke appeals to common sense, history, reason, habit, nature, and principle. By combining these, he does not pretend that reason and principle stand free of human history, custom, or common sense but are emergent tools which function within customary forms of practice (33). There are clear similarities between conservatism and pragmatism, but where things get problematic is in the question of precisely how similar, or compatible, conservatism and pragmatism ultimately are. The author is critical of Russell Kirk s treatments of both John Dewey and Edmund Burke. He sees the thought of Dewey and Burke as highly compatible, while Kirk sees the two thinkers as almost polar opposites. For Vannatta, Kirk offers a shallow and very incomplete reading of Dewey, and mistakenly equates Deweyan pragmatism with Benthamite utilitarianism. Vannatta seems to feel that Kirk was far too quick to dismiss and reject philosophical pragmatism based on its historical association with Progressive politics, before he had given it a fair read. As for Burke, Vannatta sees much that is positive in Kirk s treatment of him treatment far more extensive, of course, than Kirk s treatment of Dewey but faults Kirk for making Burke a Natural Law thinker. Vannatta s points are well taken, especially with regard to Dewey, but one can argue that he swings too far to the opposing side in his own interpretations of Dewey and Burke, and that his own considerations of each thinker s perspectives are too selective and limited in scope. Vannatta is rather fuzzy regarding precisely what he thinks Burke believes. At times he appears to maintain that Burke rejects any transcendent truths or first premises, though he admits that Burke will resort to natural law arguments on occasion. Now, it is very true that Burke should not be characterized as a hard-core Natural Law thinker of the most classic sort. But a great deal of secondary literature attempts to address this question in various ways, and a claim that Burke rejects or dismisses transcendent truths and is insincere Conservative Pragmatism, Pragmatic Conservatism Humanitas 99

Dewey s spiritual values a far cry from traditional religion. or reluctant when he makes Natural Law-type arguments really demands considerable engagement with that literature, as well as much more extensive engagement with the corpus of Burke s writings than the few fragments touched on here. Because this engagement doesn t occur, Vannatta s claim is inadequately unsupported and unconvincing. Moreover, it is not entirely clear that Vannatta believes that Burke rejects the existence of transcendent truths; at times it appears that it may be that he merely considers Burke a moderate fallibilist. But if Burke is a moderate fallibilist, how different is Vannatta s Burke from Kirk s, really? Unfortunately, the level of exploration and development necessary to answer this question well is not here. More broadly, Vannatta often takes a very blackand-white view of whether an approach to political questions is pragmatic or metaphysical, not seriously considering the possibility of subtle alternatives. In the case of Dewey, Vannatta is correct that Kirk engages in mischaracterizations of him and is too quick to dismiss him with a broad brush. But Vannatta also draws very selectively on Dewey, and, broadly speaking, Vannatta s portrait of Dewey is itself very much open to challenge. For example, one complaint Vannatta makes about Kirk is that he fails to acknowledge that Dewey sees a role for what Vannatta calls spiritual values, but in fact Dewey s spiritual values are a very far cry from traditional religion, particularly orthodox Christianity, toward which Dewey might be fairly characterized as hostile. Moreover, Dewey repeatedly emphasizes the ability of democracy and organized intelligence to achieve great progressive change, a perspective that sounds a lot more like Burke s ideological opponents than like Burke himself. Notably, Vannatta feels compelled to declare that what Dewey represents is not a politics of faith in democracy (215), but again we are effectively asked to accept this claim on Vannatta s authority; the kind of argument necessary to defend it properly is not mounted. It should be noted that direct characterizations of Burke, Kirk, and even Dewey make up only a modest portion of Conservatism and Pragmatism; the book is in fact rather wideranging in its scope, treating many thinkers. This is both a strength and a weakness. Touching on many diverse (though 100 Volume XXIX, Nos. 1 and 2, 2016 William F. Byrne

related) points helps make this an interesting and thoughtprovoking book. As has been suggested, however, the tradeoff is that there is relatively little development or defense of the many individual points that are raised, or claims that are made, and many related questions begged by such points or claims are not addressed or explored. The degree of precision in the ideas conveyed is often less than a fully engaged reader may desire. Moreover, the author s objectives are not always precisely clear. Much of the book is devoted to an exploration of the presence of conservative elements in pragmatism and to the benefits to be gained through greater embrace of those elements for a conservative pragmatism. Vannatta is strongest with this material. At other times Vannatta seems to be more engaged in comparing, and broadly exploring relationships between, conservatism and pragmatism, which is a daunting task. It is difficult enough comparing two thinkers within a single modest-length monograph. Comparing two isms is much more challenging, and when one of those isms is as slippery and complex as conservatism this becomes almost impossible to do both briefly and well. While there are indeed important relationships between conservatism and pragmatism, Vannatta finds parallels partly by effectively re-defining conservatism as something that very closely resembles Deweyan pragmatism. Early in the book Vannatta states that we need not define conservatism essentially, but rather seek to highlight its methodological norms (23). The precise distinction between what conservatism is essentially and what its methodological norms are is not made clear. But by the time one gets near the end of the book, one might argue that, despite his early disclaimers, Vannatta is very much in the business of defining conservatism: Attention to experience, particularity, non-neutrality, as well as skepticism of abstraction are common features of the methodology of conservatism and pragmatism. Conservatism is not a defense of traditional hierarchies, of men s dominance of the home or of the public sphere. It is just a methodology attentive to context and its entire experiential nexus. Conservatisms whose first principle is a divine social order, if they are to be defended, must either be radically fallible concerning our epistemic access to such a divine social order, or they must be abandoned in favor of that which leans toward pragmatism in all of its openness and freedom of communal inquiry (210-11). Conservative Pragmatism, Pragmatic Conservatism Humanitas 101

This paragraph alone would require a book-length explication and defense beyond what is offered in this volume. To say that conservatism is just a methodology attentive to context and its entire experiential nexus is at once so limiting and so vacuous a definition that its usefulness is highly questionable. Nor is it at all clear what the author means in this particular context by radically fallible. If Vannatta means that one must possess epistemic humility, one would imagine that any thinker widely recognized by scholars as anything like a Burkean conservative would fit the bill, and that, at least as far as scholarly thought is concerned, this caution or qualification is largely moot. If Vannatta means a higher fallibilism than this, big questions arise regarding one s ability to engage in meaningful, useful political-philosophical thought of any type (including pragmatist) in the context of extreme skepticism. Notably, Vannatta argues repeatedly that his pragmatic approach to politics protects against absolutism and the authoritarianism associated with it. It is very true that the sort of ahistorical, rationalistic adherence to Truth that Vannatta opposes can lead to extremism and oppression, either by prohibiting any deviation from established ways or, more typically in the modern world, by fostering a revolutionary, ideological, totalitarian state. Yet, one may question whether Vannatta s pragmatism offers much protection. What matters in politics is not the precise approach to public questions of a few philosophers. Philosophers do not make policy; less-schooled political elites, in conjunction with the general public, do. Deweyan pragmatism s meliorism (celebrated by Vannatta) and emphasis on an almost revelatory role for democracy and organized intelligence, combined with its dismissal of traditional conceptions of truth, opens the door to a political culture embracing radical innovation accompanied by majority tyranny, oppressive social engineering by elites, or a combination of the two. The fact that this might not be Dewey s intent, or that philosophers strictly adhering to Dewey s stated approaches might not yield this result, is largely beside the point; if one is to be a true pragmatist, one must focus on the likely practical political impact of a particular moral-epistemological approach in the real world, with real political actors. 102 Volume XXIX, Nos. 1 and 2, 2016 William F. Byrne

Vannatta speaks repeatedly against authority in politics, but all politics is based on authority. Burke recognized this, at least implicitly, and he recognized that appeals to dead authorities tend to be much less likely than appeals to live ones to lead to absolutism or authoritarianism. Burke s whole project was one of preventing or minimizing caprice and tyranny in politics by fostering the idea that there was in fact Truth to which individuals and society should conform, and that knowledge of this Truth is embodied, mysteriously and fuzzily, in the practices, customs, institutions, and great figures of the past. The conservative pragmatism for which Vannatta argues, and which he ascribes to Dewey and other pragmatist thinkers and political actors, is in fact very far from Burkean conservatism. Despite lip service to tradition, the openness that Vannatta celebrates is strikingly un-burkean and is far less likely to encourage meaningful constraints on a capricious will. While it is very true, as Vannatta notes, that Natural Law and the like can be misused in political argument, merely serving as cover for one s own preferences, it is equally true that a pragmatic claim that a particular course of action is demanded by the circumstances at hand can also serve merely as cover for one s own preferences. Vannatta favorably notes Dewey s science-inspired approach: The very norms of scientific inquiry that Dewey promoted openness, experimentation, fallibility, and a rejection of dogma and prejudice, are norms of praxis because thinking is an activity. Scientific inquiry, following these norms, has achieved results, and Dewey felt that inquiry into moral problems should follow such a pattern (156-57). On one level, Dewey and Vannatta are certainly correct about the experimental nature of inquiry into moral problems. But the French philosophes with their new moral science of ideology, and Enlightenment thought generally, also emphasized rejection of dogma and prejudice ; Burke understood that this purported rejection generally amounted to a willful replacement of particular old dogmas and prejudices with new dogmas and prejudices that were hastily arrived at and were usually inferior to the old ones. As Vannatta notes, the pragmatists recognized that philosophizing always occurs within a particular historical context and that it is shaped by The openness celebrated by Vannatta is strikingly un- Burkean. Conservative Pragmatism, Pragmatic Conservatism Humanitas 103

the existing culture and by the philosophers understandings of the problems presented to them. It is because of this that the right sort of cultural and social grounding one might say a very conservative cultural and social grounding is necessary to ensure that legitimate efforts to broaden one s thinking don t morph into the confusion of one s own arbitrary opinions with transcendent truths and to ensure that one does not fall into the sort of scientism that is really but another expression of closed-mindedness. While many readers are likely to have disagreements with elements of Conservatism and Pragmatism, it is a valuable addition to scholarly thought and is worthy of attention. There is a need for greater consideration of fundamental questions regarding the wellspring of sound political thought and action, and this book will serve as a useful tool in future scholarship and reflection. In addition to shedding new light on philosophical pragmatism and its role in American political thought, this book highlights, for conservative-leaning thinkers in particular, the need to take up a question that urgently needs re-visiting in the twenty-first century: What is conservatism? Finding a workable path to good order is a formidable challenge in today s world and one that demands that concerned scholars step outside of their comfort zones and muster all of the intellectual resources available for the task. 104 Volume XXIX, Nos. 1 and 2, 2016 William F. Byrne