TOBY BETENSON University of Birmingham

Similar documents
Is Evolution Incompatible with Intelligent Design? Outline

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

The Rationality of Religious Beliefs

Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification?

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology. In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

Intelligent Design. What Is It Really All About? and Why Should You Care? The theological nature of Intelligent Design

SAMPLE. What Is Intelligent Design, and What Does It Have to Do With Men s. Chapter 3

Templates for Writing about Ideas and Research

Review of Ronald Dworkin s Religion without God. Mark Satta Ph.D. student, Purdue University

Are Miracles Identifiable?

Science and Faith: Discussing Astronomy Research with Religious Audiences

Christianity and Science. Understanding the conflict (WAR)? Must we choose? A Slick New Packaging of Creationism

HABERMAS ON COMPATIBILISM AND ONTOLOGICAL MONISM Some problems

The Critical Mind is A Questioning Mind

1/8. The Third Analogy

Is Adventist Theology Compatible With Evolutionary Theory?

Keeping Your Kids On God s Side - Natasha Crain

Templates for Research Paper

Philosophy of Religion. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

FOUNDATIONALISM AND ARBITRARINESS


Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp

Forum on Public Policy

5 A Modal Version of the

Video: How does understanding whether or not an argument is inductive or deductive help me?

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

LESSON 1: ESTABLISHING CLASSROOM RULES, RIGHTS, AND RESPONSIBILITIES

Australian Evangelical Alliance. Should Intelligent Design be taught in schools?

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

Are There Philosophical Conflicts Between Science & Religion? (Participant's Guide)

Index of Templates from They Say, I Say by Gerald Graff and Cathy Birkenstein. Introducing What They Say. Introducing Standard Views

The Principle of Sufficient Reason and Free Will

Today we re gonna start a number of lectures on two thinkers who reject the idea

Comments on Lasersohn

We are called to be community, to know and celebrate God s love for us and to make that love known to others. Catholic Identity

What Are We Telling the Kids? Teaching Genesis to Teenagers

On A New Cosmological Argument

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Getting To God. The Basic Evidence For The Truth of Christian Theism. truehorizon.org

Contextualism and the Epistemological Enterprise

Is God Good By Definition?

Evidence and Transcendence

History of Modern Philosophy Fall nd Paper Assignment Due: 11/8/2019

A Rejection of Skeptical Theism

Spinoza, the No Shared Attribute thesis, and the

Kant and his Successors

A CRITIQUE OF THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. A Paper. Presented to. Dr. Douglas Blount. Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary. In Partial Fulfillment

Darwinist Arguments Against Intelligent Design Illogical and Misleading

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Nagel, Naturalism and Theism. Todd Moody. (Saint Joseph s University, Philadelphia)

*83 FOCUSING TOO MUCH ON THE FOREST MIGHT HIDE THE EVOLVING TREES: A RESPONSE TO PROFESSOR IRONS

SESSION 1. Science and God

The Unbearable Lightness of Theory of Knowledge:

Postscript: Reply to McLeod

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

A-LEVEL Religious Studies

A PROBLEM WITH DEFINING TESTIMONY: INTENTION AND MANIFESTATION:

Adam Smith and the Limits of Empiricism

Science and Religion: Exploring the Spectrum

Shafer-Landau's defense against Blackburn's supervenience argument

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

Cosmological Argument

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Academic argument does not mean conflict or competition; an argument is a set of reasons which support, or lead to, a conclusion.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

ARGUMENTS FOR THE EXISTENCE OF GOD J.P. MORELAND

[JGRChJ 9 (2013) R28-R32] BOOK REVIEW

G.E. Moore A Refutation of Skepticism

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

EPISTEMIC EVALUATION AND THE AIM OF BELIEF. Kate Nolfi. Chapel Hill 2010

Scanlon on Double Effect

INTELLIGENT DESIGN: FRIEND OR FOE FOR ADVENTISTS?

The Answer from Science

Two Kinds of Moral Relativism

Care of the Soul: Service-Learning and the Value of the Humanities

IS PLANTINGA A FRIEND OF EVOLUTIONARY SCIENCE?

Philosophy Pathways Issue nd October

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is

Sidgwick on Practical Reason

Why is life on Earth so incredibly diverse yet so strangely similar? Similarities among Diverse Forms. Diversity among Similar Forms

Lesson 2. Systematic Theology Pastor Tim Goad. Part Two Theology Proper - Beginning at the Beginning I. Introduction to the One True God

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law

Well-Being, Disability, and the Mere-Difference Thesis. Jennifer Hawkins Duke University

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary

Egocentric Rationality

Introduction to Ethics Summer Session A

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

SAMPLE ESSAY 1: PHILOSOPHY & SOCIAL SCIENCE (1 ST YEAR)

"Are Eyebrows Going to Be Talked of in Connection with the Eye of God?" Wittgenstein and Certainty in the Debate between Science and Religion

The Irrationality of Religious Beliefs

Transcription:

254 BOOK REVIEWS AND NOTICES TOBY BETENSON University of Birmingham Bradley Monton. Seeking God in Science: An Atheist Defends Intelligent Design. Peterborough, Ont.: Broadview, 2009. Bradley Monton s Seeking God in Science: An Atheist Defends Intelligent Design is a bold attempt to abstract the arguments of Intelligent Design (ID) beyond the embattled cultural and political context that has granted the theory such notoriety, and assess the central claims of the theory dispassionately. What are the claims of ID, what are the arguments to support them, and are these good arguments? Monton feels that, as a philosopher, these are the terms on which the theory should be judged; the culture war (p. 12) should be ignored. Although Monton is not persuaded by the arguments, he does consent that they are somewhat plausible (p. 75), causing him to be less certain of his atheism than he would have been had he not heard the arguments. He begins by seeking a clear understanding of ID s claims in Chapter One: What Is Intelligent Design, and Why Might an Atheist Believe in It? After a prolonged, and occasionally simplistic, discussion of what ID cannot be claiming, we finally come to Monton s version of ID: The theory of intelligent design holds that certain global features of the universe provide evidence for the existence of an intelligent cause, or that certain biologically innate features of living things provide evidence for the doctrine that the features are the result of the intentional actions of an intelligent cause which is not biologically related to the living things, and provide evidence against the doctrine that the features are the result of an undirected process such as natural selection. (p. 39) Monton has tried very hard to formulate a statement of ID that accurately captures the claims of ID whilst ruling out any awkwardly simple ways in which the claims can be made trivially true. His is certainly an improvement on the Discovery Institute s statement: The theory of intelligent design holds that certain features of the universe and of living things are best explained by an intelligent cause, not an undirected process such as natural selection. (p. 16) Monton correctly identifies

BOOK REVIEWS AND NOTICES 255 that this can be made trivially true in such mundane circumstances as the construction of buildings, but does such mundane clarification need to be made? Perhaps it s too simple to state that everyone knows what the claims of ID are, and it is legitimate and admirable to try and isolate the actual claims of ID from potentially misleading preconceptions, but Monton s philosophically rigorous formulation is noticeably selective and betrays his own intentions. He is balancing between, on the one hand, retaining an authentic and accurate version of ID s claims, whilst on the other preserving the possibility of a non-theistic, strictly natural solution. Each refinement across the 25 page section within the first chapter moulds the ultimate statement into a just right balance between being complicated enough to rule out trueness by triviality, whilst simultaneously refraining from going all the way to a full-fledged statement of supernatural theism. Monton s claim is that ID is not inherently theistic; at the end of chapter one he argues for this claim: It is true that almost all proponents of intelligent design believe in a supernatural creator, but it doesn t follow that the thesis that there is a supernatural creator is part of the intelligent design doctrine itself. The intelligent design proponents... have chosen to put forth their doctrine in such a way that it involves some sort of commitment to an intelligent cause, without specifying whether that intelligent cause is supernatural. (p. 41, emphasis added) But have they chosen to put forth their doctrine in such a way, or has Monton chosen to formulate it so? Is intelligent design, as a matter of fact, not inherently theistic? We may grant that it is not necessarily so, but perhaps there is a recognisable difference between what ID proponents could say and what they do say. Monton ignores what might be termed the brute facts of the matter namely that ID is considered by many to demonstrably be creationism in disguise leading him to defend a version of ID that perhaps not even ID proponents would endorse. The claim that ID is not necessarily inherently theistic is important to Monton for two reasons: Firstly, surrendering the inherent requirement of a necessarily supernatural solution (i.e. God) preserves the status of ID as being legitimate science. Secondly, he needs this claim to be true in order to isolate the arguments of ID from its cultural context of merely

256 BOOK REVIEWS AND NOTICES religious creationism in disguise. In chapter two, Why It Is Legitimate to Treat Intelligent Design as Science, he takes up these issues via a discussion of the Kitzmiller v. Dover Area School District case. Monton is very critical of the ruling cast by judge John E. Jones III (judge Jones decided that intelligent design counts as religion, not science, and hence the teaching of intelligent design in public school is unconstitutional (p. 48)). Monton claims the judge, and those supporting his position, are mistaken when they claim that ID is not science as science does not allow for supernatural causes. Such an a priori dismissal of supernatural causes renders science less a pursuit of truth, more a pursuit of generating the best theories that can be formulated subject to the restriction that the theories are naturalistic (p. 58). Notably, whichever conclusion we draw on this, whether supernatural causes are a part of science or not, isn t strictly relevant to Monton s discussion anyway, as he has already claimed that ID is not inherently theistic or supernatural. But in any case, we might ask if this reading of the situation is fair. Judge Jones did appear to appeal to an overly-ambitious and flawed definition of science, and Monton is right to highlight this. Generally, however, when critics of ID deny that it is science, claim that it is unscientific, etc., are they literally claiming that it is not science? Or are they rather stating that it is not scientific enough? If an aging parent passes comment on the sound of a popular beat-combo emanating from a teenager s room, that s not music, that s just noise, do they literally mean that it s not music, or do they rather mean to imply that it does not meet the required standards of tunefulness to qualify as properly being called music? I am inclined to think that critics of ID are doing something very similar, implicitly claiming that there are standards of science that must be met in order to qualify, and ID does not meet these standards. One of the ways that ID fails is in invoking a supernatural cause to fill in the gaps that might appear in a theory; that this gives rise to an accusation of not being science is not due to the dogma that supernatural causes are not legitimate in science, but rather that supernatural causes should not be invoked unnecessarily in science. Monton s claim is that the judge was mistaken in perceiving ID as being inherently theistic, or inherently appealing to supernatural causes. Now whilst this claim might be true in Monton s abstract philosophical context, perhaps a little more sympathy should be extended to the judge,

BOOK REVIEWS AND NOTICES 257 and we should recognise that judge Jones made his decision very much within the cultural war context that Monton has chosen to ignore. We might consent that ID could be not inherently theistic, but the object of the judge s decision is the version of ID as put forward in Of Pandas and People, as this is the book referenced in the disclaimer that prompted the case; this version of ID certainly seems to be inherently theistic, given its contextual heritage. Monton might wish to ignore this context to dispassionately assess the arguments, but that option is not really open to the judge. This reveals a deeper criticism that can be levelled at Monton s book: Is it really fair to deal with the arguments of ID in abstract, in isolation from their context? Monton is clearly aware that this move is controversial, and does spend some time attempting to justify it. Whilst chapter three, Some Somewhat Plausible Intelligent Design Arguments, manages to stand alone as a sound attempt to do precisely such an abstract appraisal, its conclusions prompt the reader to question whether Monton is really defending ID at all. After a consideration of fine-tuning arguments and cosmological arguments, Monton concludes I consider the cosmological argument a somewhat plausible intelligent design argument (p. 99), and after an analysis of the stark improbability of life originating from non-life, and a consideration of Nick Bostrom s simulation argument, Monton concludes the simulation argument is another example of a somewhat plausible intelligent design argument (p. 129). I am tempted to ask whether many proponents of ID would endorse Monton s conclusions. How many ID-ers would consent to their theory being used in support of an argument that claims we are nothing more than a digitised plaything in some alien computer simulation? Again, the arguments of ID could be used in this way, and Monton is entitled to discuss the arguments on these terms; but are they meant to be capable of yielding these conclusions? I just don t think proponents of ID would agree. And if ID proponents do not agree with Monton s conclusions, then Monton s formulation of ID is inaccurate. He is not defending Intelligent Design, he is defending Bradley Monton s intelligent design; and these two, it seems, are significantly different. This would not matter so much if it wasn t for his final and concluding chapter four: Should Intelligent Design Be Taught in School?. It seems

258 BOOK REVIEWS AND NOTICES odd to discuss the appropriate course of action on an issue within a particular context, whilst insisting on a separation of that issue from its context, but this is what Monton seems to do. He assesses the question of whether ID should be taught in schools without reference to certain features of the cultural war from which it originates, such as the overtly religious purposes of many ID supporters. Although Monton does make some concessions to recognising the additional contextual considerations that must be taken into account when deliberating on this question, he chooses to focus upon such contextualised questions as: is it pedagogically good for the children to be taught intelligent design? Will it further the cause of science if children are taught intelligent design? Is it good for society as a whole if intelligent design is taught in school? Is it legally permissible for intelligent design to be taught in school? (p. 136) These might appear to be concessions to recognising the contextual demands, but underlying all of these questions is one significant problem: The intelligent design under consideration is not Intelligent Design as put forward by ID proponents in books such as Of Pandas and People, and The Design of Life; the ID under consideration is Monton s idealised version of ID, abstractly formulated. So when he outlines his Six Thoughts on Teaching Intelligent Design (p. 141), broadly supporting the idea that ID should be taught in schools (briefly put: 1. Inquiry-based learning is better that fact-based learning, and ID could feature in this inquiry. 2. They re going to hear about it anyway. 3. ID can be taught well, in a non-proselytising way. 4. Let s teach the philosophy of science. 5. ID arguments are interesting. 6. We should discuss with students what should be taught), a tension between Monton s version of ID and what we might term the real ID becomes apparent; a tension heightened when Monton considers objections to his view. We d be teaching religion!, the objector says to Monton. Monton reasserts that ID is not necessarily inherently religious. I refer to my previous criticisms as to why this is deeply disingenuous, given the actual context in which ID plays out. We d be misrepresenting the content of science! ; Monton replies, again, that ID is legitimate science; I reply, again, that though Monton s version of ID may be, the classical version of ID, as found in Of Pandas and People, does not meet the standards

BOOK REVIEWS AND NOTICES 259 required to qualify as science. This is not the same as saying it is not science, merely that it is unscientific ; it is not good enough science to be taught as science to schoolchildren. We d be ignoring consensus! and We wouldn t be teaching a real controversy! ; Monton responds by pointing out that Newtonian physics is not the consensus view in science either, and yet is considered acceptable to teach; perhaps we can teach critical thinking by considering the controversies of ID, along with the issues of the Newtonian versus the contemporary paradigm? Finally, Monton considers the objection that we d be asking too much of teachers and students to achieve all of this. His response is a reiteration of an idealised inquiry-based learning scenario, and a claim that denying this option is nothing more than an attempt to preserve the status quo. Are we to expect every high-school science teacher to be expert enough in the areas of philosophy of science (and religion), theoretical physics, and the post-doctoral level biology necessary for a complete understanding of the proposed controversy surrounding ID? Are we to expect every student to take this on board in the correct way, to at least a similar degree to which they currently take on board the fact-based educational experience? Are we even dealing with this proposal as our option, or are we rather deciding whether Of Pandas and People and The Design of Life are appropriate to use in the classroom? Which teachers would take up the opportunity to teach ID, and would they teach Monton s philosophical version or the classical theistic version? Irrespective of what could occur, what is actually likely to occur? He concludes his book with a flourish I envision my writings being read many years from now, in a cultural climate without the sort of heated rhetoric that we have now, and I picture those readers saying: yes, Monton had it right. This reader does not agree.