Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory.

Similar documents
TRUTH VIRTUAL ISSUE NO. 1. Facts and Propositions F. P. R A M S E Y

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER IX CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE

Introduction: Belief vs Degrees of Belief

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak.

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

On Interpretation. Section 1. Aristotle Translated by E. M. Edghill. Part 1

Zimmerman, Michael J. Subsidiary Obligation, Philosophical Studies, 50 (1986):

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

A Logical Approach to Metametaphysics

Chadwick Prize Winner: Christian Michel THE LIAR PARADOX OUTSIDE-IN

Horwich and the Liar

International Phenomenological Society

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC

On the Expected Utility Objection to the Dutch Book Argument for Probabilism

1/9. The First Analogy

Comments on Carl Ginet s

A CRITIQUE OF THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. A Paper. Presented to. Dr. Douglas Blount. Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary. In Partial Fulfillment

FRANK JACKSON AND ROBERT PARGETTER A MODIFIED DUTCH BOOK ARGUMENT. (Received 14 May, 1975)

Phil 435: Philosophy of Language. P. F. Strawson: On Referring

(1) A phrase may be denoting, and yet not denote anything; e.g., 'the present King of France'.

Bayesian Probability

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Can logical consequence be deflated?

Some proposals for understanding narrow content

This is a longer version of the review that appeared in Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 47 (1997)

Varieties of Apriority

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

IT is frequently taken for granted, both by people discussing logical

8 Internal and external reasons

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

Understanding Belief Reports. David Braun. In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection.

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

STILL NO REDUNDANT PROPERTIES: REPLY TO WIELENBERG

Reply to Robert Koons

The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 34, No. 136, Special Issue: Frege. (Jul., 1984), pp

TWO CONCEPTIONS OF THE SYNTHETIC A PRIORI. Marian David Notre Dame University

356 THE MONIST all Cretans were liars. It can be put more simply in the form: if a man makes the statement I am lying, is he lying or not? If he is, t

Russellianism and Explanation. David Braun. University of Rochester

On Truth Thomas Aquinas

Russell: On Denoting

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

EPISTEMOLOGY for DUMMIES

Bayesian Probability

In Reference and Definite Descriptions, Keith Donnellan makes a

Analyticity and reference determiners

The Nature of Truth. by Robert James Boyles, Mark Anthony Dacela, Jeremiah Joven Joaquin and Victorino Raymundo Lualhati

Correspondence via the backdoor and other stories 1

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER VI CONDITIONS OF IMMEDIATE INFERENCE

F. P. Ramsey ( )

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox

Minimal and Maximal Models in Reinforcement Learning

Wittgenstein s Logical Atomism. Seminar 8 PHIL2120 Topics in Analytic Philosophy 16 November 2012

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

Stang (p. 34) deliberately treats non-actuality and nonexistence as equivalent.

Realism and instrumentalism

Primitive Concepts. David J. Chalmers

In general, the simplest of argument maps will take the form of something like this:

The Problem with Complete States: Freedom, Chance and the Luck Argument

Early Russell on Philosophical Grammar

Structural realism and metametaphysics

RATIONALITY AND SELF-CONFIDENCE Frank Arntzenius, Rutgers University

Could have done otherwise, action sentences and anaphora

Stout s teleological theory of action

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5

Reasoning and Decision-Making under Uncertainty

The Unbearable Lightness of Theory of Knowledge:

Saying too Little and Saying too Much. Critical notice of Lying, Misleading, and What is Said, by Jennifer Saul

Moral Obligation. by Charles G. Finney

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries

Quine: Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

(Refer Slide Time 03:00)

Frege's Gedanken Are Not Truth Conditions

Russell on Denoting. G. J. Mattey. Fall, 2005 / Philosophy 156. The concept any finite number is not odd, nor is it even.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Saying too Little and Saying too Much Critical notice of Lying, Misleading, and What is Said, by Jennifer Saul

Aristotle on the Principle of Contradiction :

Who Has the Burden of Proof? Must the Christian Provide Adequate Reasons for Christian Beliefs?

Millian responses to Frege s puzzle

VAGUENESS. Francis Jeffry Pelletier and István Berkeley Department of Philosophy University of Alberta Edmonton, Alberta, Canada

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ

How Subjective Fact Ties Language to Reality

What would count as Ibn Sīnā (11th century Persia) having first order logic?

AN EPISTEMIC PARADOX. Byron KALDIS

Evidential Support and Instrumental Rationality

Philosophy 240: Symbolic Logic

Truth and Simplicity F. P. Ramsey

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

Can Negation be Defined in Terms of Incompatibility?

Transcription:

Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. Monika Gruber University of Vienna 11.06.2016 Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 1 / 30

1 Truth and Probability (1926) 2 Facts and Propositions (1927) 3 Decision Theory Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 2 / 30

Truth and Probability (1926) Ramsey s goal in TP is to bring out the connection between the subjective degree of belief we have in a proposition p and the probability we assign it. Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 3 / 30

Truth and Probability (1926) Ramsey s goal in TP is to bring out the connection between the subjective degree of belief we have in a proposition p and the probability we assign it. Ramsey considers the notion of partial belief. We have to establish what a partial belief is and how it is to be measured because a degree of belief has no precise meaning, unless we specify exactly how to measure it. Therefore, Ramsey presents his first definition of a degree of a belief. the degree of a belief is a causal property of it, which we can express vaguely as the extent to which we are prepared to act on it. Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 3 / 30

Truth and Probability (1926) In order to be able to measure the strength of our beliefs, we must assign to any belief a magnitude or degree having a definite position in an order of magnitudes. Hence we must construct an ordered series of degrees and then assign numbers to these degrees in an intelligible manner. We denote: full belief by 1, full belief in the contradictory by 0, equal beliefs in the proposition and its contradictory by 1 2. Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 4 / 30

Truth and Probability (1926) In order to be able to measure the strength of our beliefs, we must assign to any belief a magnitude or degree having a definite position in an order of magnitudes. Hence we must construct an ordered series of degrees and then assign numbers to these degrees in an intelligible manner. We denote: full belief by 1, full belief in the contradictory by 0, equal beliefs in the proposition and its contradictory by 1 2. It is much more difficult to say what it means that we belief in a proposition to 2 3. Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 4 / 30

Truth and Probability (1926) In order to be able to measure the strength of our beliefs, we must assign to any belief a magnitude or degree having a definite position in an order of magnitudes. Hence we must construct an ordered series of degrees and then assign numbers to these degrees in an intelligible manner. We denote: full belief by 1, full belief in the contradictory by 0, equal beliefs in the proposition and its contradictory by 1 2. It is much more difficult to say what it means that we belief in a proposition to 2 3. This is the harder part of the task, but it is absolutely necessary; for we do calculate numerical probabilities, and if they are to correspond to degrees of belief we must discover some definite way of attaching numbers to degrees of belief. [TP, 64] Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 4 / 30

Truth and Probability (1926) Ramsey considers two ways in which we can deal with this task. The first one is assuming that a belief is perceptible by its owner and accompanied by a feeling of conviction to which a definite number could be ascribed. This method, however, is dismissed on a few very obvious grounds, i.e. the inability to ascribe numbers to feelings, or that we often have no feelings at all about our strongest beliefs. Ramsey suggest another, the only sound method the kind of measurement of belief with which probability is concerned [TP, 67] to assume that the degree of a belief is a casual property of it the extent to which we are prepared to act on this belief. Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 5 / 30

Truth and Probability (1926) As soon as we regard belief quantitatively, this seems to me the only view we can take of it. It could well be held that the difference between believing and not believing lies in the presence or absence of introspectible feelings. But when we seek to know what is the difference between believing more firmly and believing less firmly, we can no longer regard it as consisting in having more or less of certain observable feelings; at leat I personally cannot recognize any such feeling. The difference seems to me to lie in how far we should act on theses beliefs: this may depend on the degree of some feeling or feelings, but I do not know exactly what feelings and I do not see that it is indispensable that we should know. [TP, 66] Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 6 / 30

Truth and Probability (1926) Two essential things Ramsey points out are that: the beliefs we are concerned with are dispositional, i.e. they would lead to action if acted on them, in suitable circumstances; e.g. a lump of arsenic; and Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 7 / 30

Truth and Probability (1926) Two essential things Ramsey points out are that: the beliefs we are concerned with are dispositional, i.e. they would lead to action if acted on them, in suitable circumstances; e.g. a lump of arsenic; and the degree of a belief is a casual property of it the extent to which we are prepared to act on this belief. Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 7 / 30

Truth and Probability (1926) Ramsey persists that when we talk about the strength of our beliefs what we actually mean, is how we should act, according to those beliefs, in possible situations. Therefore, also in regard to measuring partial beliefs, with which probability is concerned, Ramsey argues that the best way is the measurement of belief via basis of action. The old-established method of measuring a person s belief is to propose a bet, and see what are the lowest odds which he will accept. This method I regard as fundamentally sound; but it suffers from being insufficiently general, and from being necessarily inexact. [TP, 68] Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 8 / 30

Truth and Probability (1926) Ramsey persists that when we talk about the strength of our beliefs what we actually mean, is how we should act, according to those beliefs, in possible situations. Therefore, also in regard to measuring partial beliefs, with which probability is concerned, Ramsey argues that the best way is the measurement of belief via basis of action. The old-established method of measuring a person s belief is to propose a bet, and see what are the lowest odds which he will accept. This method I regard as fundamentally sound; but it suffers from being insufficiently general, and from being necessarily inexact. [TP, 68] Ramsey proposes to construct a general and more exact theory of quantities of belief. A theory which assumes that we act in the way we think most likely to realise the objects of our desires, so that a person s actions are completely determined by his desires and opinions [TP, 69]. Admittedly, such theory cannot apply adequately to all possible situations, nevertheless, Ramsey decides to use it claiming for the results only approximate truth. He formulates what is now known as a Bayesian principle of the maximisation of expect utility. Distancing himself from the utilitarians, for whom the pleasure had a dominating position, Ramsey holds that agents choose the act which is for them of the greatest utility, given their desires and their degrees of beliefs. Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 8 / 30

Truth and Probability (1926) The theory I propose to adopt is that we seek things we want, which may be our own or other people s pleasure, or anything else whatever, and our actions are such as we think most likely to realise those goods. [TP, 69] Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 9 / 30

Truth and Probability (1926) The focus remains on measuring the beliefs via basis of action. Ideally, our subject, having no doubts and only certain opinions about everything will always act in a way, which in her opinion, will lead to the greatest sum of good maximum expected utility. Our agent, however, being human, is not always certain to what degree she holds at least some of her beliefs. Therefore, Ramsey suggests another definition of a degree of belief, which takes account of varying degrees of certainty in the agent s beliefs. Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 10 / 30

Truth and Probability (1926) I suggest that we introduce as a law of psychology that his behaviour is governed by what is called the mathematical expectation; that is to say that, if p is a proposition about which he is doubtful, any goods or bads for whose realization p is in his view a necessary and sufficient condition enter into his calculations multiplied by the same fraction, which is called the degree of his belief in p. We thus define degree of belief in a way which presupposed the use of the mathematical expectation. [TP, 70] Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 11 / 30

Truth and Probability (1926) Supposing an agent s degree of belief in a proposition p is m n, then we define it thus Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 12 / 30

Truth and Probability (1926) Supposing an agent s degree of belief in a proposition p is m n, then we define it thus Def. degree of belief in p = m n ; which means that an agent s action is such as she would choose it to be if she had to repeat it exactly n times, in m of which p was true, and in the others false [in each of the n times he has no memory of the previous ones]. [cf. TP, 70] Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 12 / 30

Truth and Probability (1926) Ramsey proves these laws to be necessarily true of any consistent set of degrees of belief. Hence he shows how Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 13 / 30

Truth and Probability (1926) Ramsey proves these laws to be necessarily true of any consistent set of degrees of belief. Hence he shows how we can measure the degree of belief an agent as in p, and Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 13 / 30

Truth and Probability (1926) Ramsey proves these laws to be necessarily true of any consistent set of degrees of belief. Hence he shows how we can measure the degree of belief an agent as in p, and provided an agent is reasonable, his degree of belief will have a measure that satisfies the mathematical laws of probability. Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 13 / 30

Truth and Probability (1926) Ramsey proves these laws to be necessarily true of any consistent set of degrees of belief. Hence he shows how we can measure the degree of belief an agent as in p, and provided an agent is reasonable, his degree of belief will have a measure that satisfies the mathematical laws of probability. He has shown that the measure representing the degree of belief that an agent has in p satisfies the axioms of probability theory. Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 13 / 30

Truth and Probability (1926) We find, therefore, that a precise account of the nature of partial belief reveals that the laws of probability are laws of consistency. They do not depend for their meaning on any degree of belief in a proposition being uniquely determined as a rational one; they merely distinguish those sets of beliefs which obey them as consistent ones. Having any definite degree of belief implies a certain measure of consistency, namely willingness to bet on a given proposition at the same odds for any stake, the stakes being measured in terms of ultimate values. Having degrees of belief obeying the laws of probability implies a further measure of consistency, namely such a consistency between the odds acceptable on different propositions as shall prevent a book being made against you. [TP, 78-9] Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 14 / 30

Truth and Probability (1926) Ramsey s aim was to show that we are able to measure the degree of belief an agent has in a proposition, and that provided the agent follows some principles of rationality, the measure by which we can represent this degree of belief is a probability measure. Moreover, Ramsey in fact has shown that the obtained measure of degree of belief is a probability measure. Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 15 / 30

Truth and Probability (1926) In Truth and Probability (1926), Ramsey laid the foundations of the modern theory of subjective probability and of modern decision theory. Seen like this, it is important to understand TP as a theory of rule-following: we can describe a person s actions in terms of rule-following. If our distribution of degrees of belief follows the rules of probability, a book cannot be made against us. Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 16 / 30

Facts and Propositions (1927) For Ramsey the problem of truth is not separate from the problem of the analysis of judgement or the content of belief, hence the problem of truth is transferred to the problem of the truth conditions of beliefs, that is why Ramsey says that if we have analysed judgement, we have also solved the problem of truth. [FP, 39] Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 17 / 30

Facts and Propositions (1927) For Ramsey the problem of truth is not separate from the problem of the analysis of judgement or the content of belief, hence the problem of truth is transferred to the problem of the truth conditions of beliefs, that is why Ramsey says that if we have analysed judgement, we have also solved the problem of truth. [FP, 39] In "Facts and Propositions" Ramsey deals with full beliefs, which he defines as a set of actions for whose utility p is a necessary and sufficient condition. Moreover, Ramsey connects his theory of belief to a theory of truth, adding that the given belief is true if p, i.e. if these actions are useful. Thus any belief used as a basis for action is true, if and only if, the agent having the belief is successful acting on it. That is Ramsey s Principle. Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 17 / 30

Facts and Propositions (1927) Before dealing with the more complex concepts judgement and belief, Ramsey turns to the issues of truth and falsehood in order to show that there is really no separate problem of truth but merely a linguistic muddle. [FP, 38] Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 18 / 30

Facts and Propositions (1927) Before dealing with the more complex concepts judgement and belief, Ramsey turns to the issues of truth and falsehood in order to show that there is really no separate problem of truth but merely a linguistic muddle. [FP, 38] Truth and falsity are ascribed primarily to propositions, which may be either explicitly given or described. Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 18 / 30

Facts and Propositions (1927) Before dealing with the more complex concepts judgement and belief, Ramsey turns to the issues of truth and falsehood in order to show that there is really no separate problem of truth but merely a linguistic muddle. [FP, 38] Truth and falsity are ascribed primarily to propositions, which may be either explicitly given or described. explicitly given it is evident that It is true that Caesar was murdered means simply that Caesar was murdered, and it is false that Caesar was murdered means that he was not murdered. We add is true and is false for emphasis or stylistic reasons. We also say it is a fact that which means the same. In the case of explicitly given propositions, if we substitute p for Caesar was murdered we do not have to add is true to p, for it is true that Caesar was murdered means simply that Caesar was murdered, hence the use of the variable p is substitutional. Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 18 / 30

Facts and Propositions (1927) described here, we get statements from which we cannot in ordinary language eliminate the words true and false, e.g. He is always right means that the propositions he asserts are alway true, The matter seems more complicated in the case of described propositions, although Ramsey is determined to hold that that it is just as simple. For as soon as we present our propositions in a clear logical notation, For all p if he asserts p, then p (is true) the predicate is true can easily be eliminated, since the propositional function p is true is the same as p, like the value of Caesar was murdered is true is the same as Caesar was murdered. It could, however, be argued that the quantification here, is one over the objects, and not sentences, as in the case of explicitly given propositions. For Ramsey it was not, but he suggests yet another interpretation, i.e. to express it as a relation of the form arb ; then He is always right could be expressed by For all a, R, b, if he asserts arb, then arb (is true) the elimination of the predicate is true does not present any difficulties. Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 19 / 30

Facts and Propositions (1927) For all p iff p then p which amounts to simply stating p itself. To sum it up, on Ramsey s redundancy account of truth to say that p is a fact, or that it is a fact that p means the same as to say that p is true, which in turn amounts to simply stating p. Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 20 / 30

Facts and Propositions (1927) This short statement has, however, been misinterpreted by the deflationists. Ramsey s redundancy conception of truth only makes sense together with his theory of belief which, in turn, is dependent on his complete theory of truth. Hence, his theories of belief and of truth are interdependent. Ramsey s goal in FP is to present a logical analysis of judgement and belief, and he is determined to account for the truth conditions of beliefs and judgements. He wants to establish the factor that makes the truth predication of these notions possible, or more precisely, what these mental states have in common that enables us to state their truth or falsity. Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 21 / 30

Facts and Propositions (1927) As Michael Dummett notices, it is not possible that Ramsey held a redundancy conception of truth which amounted to the given equivalence, and at the same, using this equivalence wanted to determine the truth conditions of our beliefs, or generally, of all our mental states. Moreover, Ramsey was definitely aware that if one holds that it is true that p amounts simply to p one needs to know the content or the meaning of p. Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 22 / 30

Facts and Propositions (1927) The following quote makes it clear that for Ramsey any discussion of truth is strictly connected to his theory of belief. It is, perhaps, also immediately obvious that if we have analysed judgement we have solved the problem of truth; for taking the mental factor in a judgement (which is often itself called a judgement), the truth or falsity of this depends only on what proposition it is that is judged, and what we have to explain is the meaning of saying that the judgement is a judgement that a has R to b, i.e. is true if arb, false if not. We can, if we like, say that it is true if there exists a corresponding fact that a has R to b, but this is essentially not an analysis but a periphrasis, for The fact that a has R tob exists is no different from a has R to b. [FP, 39] Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 23 / 30

Facts and Propositions (1927) On Ramsey s account given in FP, a belief is a disposition to act if certain preferable circumstances were present and a disposition to act as if believed proposition was true. He considers the mental factors in a belief and holds that Their nature will depend on the sense in which we are using the ambiguous term belief: it is, for instance, possible to say that a chicken believes a certain sort of caterpillar to be poisonous, and mean by that merely that it abstains from eating such caterpillars on account of unpleasant experiences connected with them. The mental factors in such a belief would be parts of the chicken s behaviour, which are somehow related to the objective factors, viz. the kind of caterpillar and poisonousness. An exact analysis of this relation would be very difficulty, but it might well be held that in regard to this kind of belief the pragmatist view was correct, i.e. that the relation between the chicken s behaviour and the objective factors was that the actions were such as to be useful if, and only if, the caterpillars were actually poisonous.[fp, 40] Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 24 / 30

Facts and Propositions (1927) Poisonous Edible Eat Upset stomach Excellent dinner Refrain Avoids upset stomach Missed dinner 1 1 Sahlin, 1990, 72. Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 25 / 30

Facts and Propositions (1927) Thus any set of actions for whose utility p is a necessary and sufficient condition might be called a belief that p, and so would be true if p, i.e. if they were useful. 1 and he adds in a footnote that It is useful to believe arb would mean that it is useful to do things which are useful if, and only if, arb; which is evidently equivalent to arb. [FP, 40] Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 26 / 30

Facts and Propositions (1927) This brings us back to the problem of the truth conditions of beliefs, hence a combined theory of truth and belief, understood as the basis of our actions, which leads us to yet another formulation of what has been called Ramsey s Principle a belief that p is true, if and only if it is useful to do the things of which the truth of p is a necessary and sufficient condition. Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 27 / 30

Facts and Propositions (1927) The essence of pragmatism I take to be this, that the meaning of a sentence is to be defined by reference to the actions to which asserting it would lead, or more vaguely still, by its possible causes and effects. Of this I feel certain, but of nothing more definite.[fp, 51] Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 28 / 30

Decision Theory Two main types of factors influence our decisions: Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 29 / 30

Decision Theory Two main types of factors influence our decisions: our wants or desires, which determine the utilities of the possible outcomes of our decisions, Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 29 / 30

Decision Theory Two main types of factors influence our decisions: our wants or desires, which determine the utilities of the possible outcomes of our decisions, and our beliefs about the world, which determine the probabilities of the possible outcomes. Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 29 / 30

Decision Theory Two main types of factors influence our decisions: our wants or desires, which determine the utilities of the possible outcomes of our decisions, and our beliefs about the world, which determine the probabilities of the possible outcomes. A decision theory tells us how to handle our desires and beliefs and provides an account of how to combine these into a rational decision. We can describe a person s actions in terms of rule-following. If the chicken doesn t know whether the caterpillar is poisonous or not, it should act in a way that maximizes his expected utility. If, on the other hand, the chicken has a full belief that the caterpillar is poisonous, it will refrain from eating it an action that is useful iff the caterpillar is, in fact, poisonous. Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 29 / 30

Decision Theory Two main types of factors influence our decisions: our wants or desires, which determine the utilities of the possible outcomes of our decisions, and our beliefs about the world, which determine the probabilities of the possible outcomes. A decision theory tells us how to handle our desires and beliefs and provides an account of how to combine these into a rational decision. We can describe a person s actions in terms of rule-following. If the chicken doesn t know whether the caterpillar is poisonous or not, it should act in a way that maximizes his expected utility. If, on the other hand, the chicken has a full belief that the caterpillar is poisonous, it will refrain from eating it an action that is useful iff the caterpillar is, in fact, poisonous. It is perspicuous how Ramsey s ideas on truth presented in FP (1927) are dependent on the ideas on probability presented in TP (1926). Moreover, the same ideas are clearly visible in Ramsey s latest unpublished and far from completed manuscript On Truth. Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 29 / 30

Decision Theory Thank you. Monika Gruber (University of Vienna) Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory. 11.06.2016 30 / 30