Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

Similar documents
Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal?

A Platonic Theory of Epistemic Value. Joseph Andrew Barnes. A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the. requirements for the degree of

Skepticism and Internalism

Aboutness and Justification

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis

Truth as the Epistemic Goal Marian David. From Steup, M Knowledge, Truth, and Duty.

Epistemic Consequentialism, Truth Fairies and Worse Fairies

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

Philosophical Ethics. Distinctions and Categories

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

KNOWLEDGE, JUSTIFICATION, AND THE NORMATIVITY OF EPISTEMOLOGY

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

Epistemological Foundations for Koons Cosmological Argument?

24.01: Classics of Western Philosophy

LODGE VEGAS # 32 ON EDUCATION

Truly Normative Matters: An Essay on the Value of Truth

Is there a distinction between a priori and a posteriori

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Knowledge and its Limits, by Timothy Williamson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xi

The normativity of content and the Frege point

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Epistemic Normativity for Naturalists

Constructing the World

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

A Priori Bootstrapping

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

dialectica dialectica Vol. 65, N 4 (2011), pp DOI: /j x What Should a Theory of Knowledge Do?

Phenomenal Conservatism and the Internalist Intuition

Postmodal Metaphysics

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

Penultimate Draft: Final Revisions not included. Published in Philosophical Books, 1995.

Lecture 5 Rejecting Analyses I: Virtue Epistemology

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

On David Chalmers's The Conscious Mind

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

Review of Nathan M. Nobis s Truth in Ethics and Epistemology

Huemer s Problem of Memory Knowledge

Review of "The Tarskian Turn: Deflationism and Axiomatic Truth"

McDowell and the New Evil Genius

Understanding and its Relation to Knowledge Christoph Baumberger, ETH Zurich & University of Zurich

Theories of epistemic justification can be divided into two groups: internalist and

A number of epistemologists have defended

AGENT CAUSATION AND RESPONSIBILITY: A REPLY TO FLINT

Let s Bite the Bullet on Deontological Epistemic Justification: A Response to Robert Lockie 1 Rik Peels, Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam.

Knowledge is Not the Most General Factive Stative Attitude

Introduction: Paradigms, Theism, and the Parity Thesis

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2011

Epistemic Value and the New Evil Demon. B.J.C. Madison. (Forthcoming in Pacific Philosophical Quarterly) Draft Version Do Not Cite Without Approval

INTRODUCTION. This week: Moore's response, Nozick's response, Reliablism's response, Externalism v. Internalism.

Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work on

An Epistemology That Matters Richard Foley

Knowledge and its Limits, by Timothy Williamson. Oxford: Oxford University

From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy

The unity of the normative

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

Class 4 - The Myth of the Given

Review of Steven D. Hales Book: Relativism and the Foundations of Philosophy

Internalism Re-explained 1. Ralph Wedgwood

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

Revelation, Humility, and the Structure of the World. David J. Chalmers

METHODISM AND HIGHER-LEVEL EPISTEMIC REQUIREMENTS Brendan Murday

Introduction: Belief vs Degrees of Belief

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Varieties of Apriority

knowledge is belief for sufficient (objective and subjective) reason

HABERMAS ON COMPATIBILISM AND ONTOLOGICAL MONISM Some problems

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

PHILOSOPHY 5340 EPISTEMOLOGY

Epistemological Externalism and the Project of Traditional Epistemology. Contemporary philosophers still haven't come to terms with the project of

Rationalism of a moderate variety has recently enjoyed the renewed interest of

New Lessons from Old Demons: The Case for Reliabilism

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

AN ACTUAL-SEQUENCE THEORY OF PROMOTION

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

A Priori Skepticism and the KK Thesis

Is Knowledge True Belief Plus Adequate Information?

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Internalism Re-explained

Grounding and Analyticity. David Chalmers

xiv Truth Without Objectivity

INTRODUCTION: EPISTEMIC COHERENTISM

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

Why there is no such thing as a motivating reason

The Many Problems of Memory Knowledge (Short Version)

Notes for Week 4 of Contemporary Debates in Epistemology

Stout s teleological theory of action

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

Transcription:

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes I. Motivation: what hangs on this question? II. How Primary? III. Kvanvig's argument that truth isn't the primary epistemic goal IV. David's argument that truth is the primary epistemic goal V. More arguments against epistemic truth monism I. What hangs on questions about epistemic values or goals: 1. Some arguments in normative epistemology depend on questions about value. e.g. the 'swamping problem' for reliabilism proceeds from monism about truth 2. The significance of epistemic evaluations for non-epistemological humans. e.g. if it turned out that we didn't value the things of epistemic value. 3. Some arguments in metaphysics about value in general. e.g. if epistemology involves only some hypothetical imperative about truth. II. What way of being primary is important to each of these motivations? 1. If there are any other epistemic values, then the reliabilist has a response to the swamping problem. 2. If there are any other epistemic values, then we can't just check whether we care about the primary one, in order to decide whether we care about epistemic evaluations 3. If there are any other epistemic values, that may cause trouble for epistemological naturalism. So it seems to me that the way of being primary which matters is well captured by monism: there's really only one intrinsic epistemic value. And anything else which has epistemic value has it only because of some relationship it has to whatever is of intrinsic epistemic value. This will be important. III. Kvanvig: The strategy: come up with a permissive criterion for which evaluations are epistemic, then: i. prima facie "each independent kind of cognitive success within the purview of epistemology identifies a cognitive goal in its own right." There's something importantly right about this. ii. some of these kinds of cognitive success "can be explained without recourse to the goal of truth", as: a. Having an empirically adequate theory "that will never be refuted by the course of experience" What's it mean to not be refuted? This doesn't count as a counterexample on my understanding. b. Making sense of the course of experience, since "one makes sense of the course of experience by developing a classification for experiences together with a theory of explanation of how the various categories are explanatorily related." Won't those explanations, if correct, involve truth both in the explanans and explanandum? c. Responsibly inquiring, on a 'real deontologist' account. Wouldn't such an account beg the Q? c.' intellectually blameless inquiry d. Foley Rationality, on which a belief is justified iff one would hold it after a Cartesian Meditation. 1

The demarcational issue: What is epistemology? Kvanvig: epistemology is the investigation of successful cognitive processes, events & states; & of their success -when investigated philosophically (so it's not e.g.,psychology) -considered irrespective of causal consequences How about a different criterion: an evaluation is epistemic if people care about it in the same way they care about paradigm epistemic evaluations (e.g. knowledge, justification) Perhaps the different demarcations are motivated by a desire to capture different things: The narrow conception, on which epistemology is just the theory of knowledge, is motivated by a desire to capture the environment in which recent disputes in epistemology came about; so it might be relevant to I.1, above. A broader conception, though not necessarily Kvanvig's, would capture what's clearly relevant to I.3 and I.2. I.1, too? On the narrow conception: Even on the narrow conception of epistemology, the truth-goal isn't obvious: i. it's not clear that justification can be explained in terms of truth ii. it's not clear that the Gettier thing can be explained in terms of truth (+justification) iii. it's not clear that the supervenience base of epistemic evaluations will be true beliefs iv. nor would the supervenience base of epistemic evaluations be a goal v. reliabilism isn't an argument for a metaepistemological thesis vi. even if there has to be some goal, why truth rather than knowledge? (& why is either primary?) the circularity worry here (p. 291) seems confused; even if it would be "bad epistemology to invoke the knowledge-goal as part of the theory of knowledge," how is that what one would be doing? IV. David How could truth be a goal? Truth as a goal means possessing truth by believing or knowing true propositions -so the goal of having knowledge is a truth-goal This seems wrong; one can have X but not Y as a goal even when X entails Y How is having something as a goal different from just desiring it, for David? As an end? How to formulate truth goals? (1) G (p)(tp -> Bp & Bp -> Tp) "collective true belief goal" First conjunct has to be restricted to "important and interesting" props. Same for 3.1 & 3.2. (2) (p) G (Tp -> Bp & Bp -> Tp) "distributive true belief goal" This can't be it, since "we can't have all these goals." Is that true? But we can restrict the domain to propositions p "such that we are seriously asking whether p" (3.1) G (p)(tp -> Kp & Bp -> Tp) "weak collective knowledge goal" (3.2) G (p)(tp -> Kp & Bp -> Kp) "strong collective knowledge goal" (4.1) (p) G (Tp -> Kp & Bp -> Tp) "weak distributive knowledge goal" (4.2) (p) G (Tp -> Kp & Bp -> Kp) "strong distributive knowledge goal" 2

Which goals are epistemic? "Epistemology is the theory of knowledge" What is this doing, for David? Does it entail that, e.g., evaluations of Foley rationality are not epistemic? So, in addition to the knowledge-goal and the truth-goal: the justified-belief-goal is epistemic. Which goals are primary? The primary epistemic goal will be the one we want the others for the sake of. qualification: "within the domain of epistemology" What does it mean to want something within a domain? qualification: "we ought to have [non-primary goals] because we have the" primary one What's the force of that "ought"? Just to prevent empirical falsification? Bigger question: why does primacy, in this sense, matter? It's just an ordering of our desires, isn't it? Or an ordering of how our desires "ought" to be? How "ought" our desires, epistemically, be? The true-belief goal is prior to the justified belief goal. A1 If you want to have TBs you ought to have JBs A2 We want to have JBs because we want to have TBs B1 If you want to have JBs you ought to have TBs B2 We want to have TBs because we want to have JBs I think we should grant that A1 and A2 are far more plausible than B1 and B2. But so what? Nothing follows. What explains the plausibility of A1? A3 does: A3 For any p: if you want to <believe p iff p is true> then you ought to <believe p iff you have justification for believing p> And, what explains the plausibility of A3, A2, and A1? A4 does: A4 You ought to have justified beliefs rather than unjustified beliefs, given that you want to have true beliefs rather than false ones, because justified beliefs are likely to be true, at least considerably more likely to be true than unjustified ones. Objection to the claim that A4 explains A1/2/3: it might be that justified beliefs are just beliefs made sufficiently more likely to be true by their justifiers - which wouldn't entail that they're likely "in any absolute sense." The true-belief goal and the knowledge-goal. 3 C1 If you want to have TBs you ought to have K. Taken as a claim about the class 'knowledge,' plausible; about individual props, 'deviant' C2 We want to have K because we want to have TBs. D1 If you want to have K you ought to have TBs. D2 We want to have TBs because we want to have K. D1 is made plausible by D3: D3 for any p, if you want to <know p it is true, and believe p only if you know it> then you ought to <believe p if it is true, and believe p only if it is true>

D3 gives a reason to think that the knowledge-goal is prior to the true-belief goal. Flawed reply: true belief is more basic, and a goal, therefore a more basic goal. Second reply: to want knowledge is not to want anything more than justified true beliefs Problem: Gettier cases Third reply: to want knowledge is not to want anything more than justified non-accidentally true belief So the goal of having non-accidentally true belief is prior to the goal of having knowledge. Meno Problems If (non-accidentally) true belief is the primary epistemic goal, this seems to entail epistemic value monism: (TM) The sole epistemic good is true belief (& the sole epistemic bad is false belief) (NATM) The sole epistemic good is non-accidentally true belief (& the sole epistemic bad is...?) What does TM mean? Does it entail that (is this an epistemic sense of ought?): "We ought to want knowledge and justification only because, and insofar as, we want true beliefs." This is importantly different from my formulation of epistemic value monism - this is talking about an ordering of desires - desiring X for the sake of Y. That's compatible with X not being explicable in terms of Y. Is (TM) or (NATM) true? Does the primary-goal stuff entail it? Why? If (TM) is right, then although otherwise plausible, these seem wrong (for (NATM), too, except (a)): (a) Knowledge seems better than mere true belief (b) Justified true belief seems better than unjustified true belief (c) Unjustified false belief seems worse than justified false belief (d) Unjustified true belief versus justified false belief? Intuition hesitates. This is false; intuition doesn't hesitate - justified false belief is epistemically better; TM gets it wrong. NATM? On the other hand, (KM) seems to get (a)-(c) right & maybe (d); (TJP) even more clearly does. (KM) The sole epistemic good is knowledge (& the sole epistemic bad is? ) David doesn't have a real response to this. (TJP) Both justified belief and true belief are basic epistemic goods If (TJP) were right, why does A1 seem right? David: A1 is plausible because you epistemically ought to have justified beliefs. But "absolute oughts" belong only in ethics. Surely not; pragmatic oughts? And, if this were so, why would justification involve producing evidence of truth? But being justified isn't a matter of justifying! Nor is it obviously a matter of just having evidence! A better response: A1 seems right as a claim not about epistemic oughts, but about our all-things-considered desires, because true beliefs are pragmatically better than justified beliefs; but that pragmatic claim shows nothing about epistemic value. 4

How else might TM or NATM account for (a)-(d)? In terms of desires: i. We have a basic desire for true beliefs ii. We have a derived desire (from our desire for true beliefs) for justified beliefs iii. Things seem epistemically better which satisfy more of our desires But it's clearly false that: iii.' Things are epistemically better which satisfy more of our desires And i-iii, rather than i-iii', would at most explain why we think (a)-(d). But if the claim is that (a)-(d) are literally false; then I have no handle whatsoever on epistemic value. V. More against Truth Monism What seems right about Kvanvig's objection that, prima facie, we should expect that there will be as many epistemic values as there are kinds of cognitive success, is that if monism is true, then all epistemic evaluations will be explained by reference to some relation they bear to that one intrinsic value. So, e.g., justification would be a certain relation to truth. The exact nature of the relation is a matter of great controversy, of course, but doesn't matter for epistemic value monism. What's important for us is that the relation to truth is explanatory - truth monism doesn't depend on any ordering of our desires. More on the Meno problem: The 'swamping problem' for reliabilism, and the 'Meno problem' above, both rely on some supposed consequences of truth monism, either that (i) true belief is epistemically unimprovable or that (ii) any true belief is epistemically better than any false belief. (a) and (b) trade on (i); (d) trades on (ii). But why think that either (i) or (ii) is right? One argument: they're right because the relationship between derived and intrinsic values is explanatory; and no relation R to truth could explain (i)' why a true belief, which also stands in R to truth, is better than a true belief which doesn't stand in R to truth, nor (ii)' why any false belief which stands in R to truth is better than any true belief which doesn't stand in R to truth. Another argument: if any relationship to truth in important, then being true is the most important. In general, what principled way would point to certain relationships to truth, rather than others? A non-meno problem, for explanation: If TM is right, then there is some set of relations to truth which all and only things of derived epistemic value share. It's hard enough to see how this could be the case for justification. But what about: (a) Foley Rationality (b) Believing that beliefs are justified (c) Coherence (d) Having beliefs which conform to the probability axioms (e) Whatever rationalizing ability (i) goes along with justification but (ii) is not truth-conducive (f) Whatever explanatory ability (i) is part of knowing why but (ii) is not factive (g) Whatever makes believing Moore's paradoxical propositions worse than believing "I have at least one other false belief" 5