The Trolley Problem. 1. The Trolley Problem: Consider the following pair of cases:

Similar documents
Intending Versus Foreseeing Harm

Quinn s DDE. 1. Quinn s DDE: Warren Quinn begins by running through the familiar pairs of cases:

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

Quinn s Doctrine of Doing and Allowing (DDA)

Scanlon on Double Effect

THE ROAD TO HELL by Alastair Norcross 1. Introduction: The Doctrine of the Double Effect.

Phil 108, July 15, 2010

During the Second World War as V1 rockets rained down on London, Churchill made a fateful decision. He would protect the city center and its vital

Psychological Aspects of Social Issues

Torture Does Timing Matter?

Actions, Intentions, and Consequences: The Doctrine of Double Effect

NOTE ON THE DOCTRINE OF DOUBLE EFFECT AND THE DOCTRINE OF ACTS AND OMISSIONS For Philosophy 13 Fall, 2004

Double Effect and Terror Bombing

NOTE ON THE DOCTRINE OF DOUBLE EFFECT AND THE DOCTRINE OF ACTS AND OMISSIONS For Philosophy 13 Fall, 2008

DEFENDING DOUBLE EFFECT Ralph Wedgwood

The Moral Relevance of the Past (Hanna)

Thomson s turnabout on the trolley

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

Ethics is subjective.

I may disappoint some of you when I say that the trolley problem I shall be talking about is not this one hard though it is, even after inspection of

THOMSON S TROLLEY PROBLEM. Peter A. Graham

18 Die Philippa Foot 1

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Aristotle and Double Effect

Judge s Two Options: he can (i) let the rioters kill the five hostages, or (ii) frame an innocent person for the crime, and have him executed.

Must Consequentialists Kill?

Tony Stark: The most famous mass murder in the history of America. This is one

Against Individual Responsibility (Sinnott-Armstrong)

So Close, Yet So Far: Why Solutions to the Closeness Problem for the Doctrine of Double Effect Fall Short 1

How should I live? I should do whatever brings about the most pleasure (or, at least, the most good)

Chapter 26: Causation And Ethics * ethical concepts, views, and problems. In particular, I discuss the role of causation in the family

OPEN Moral Luck Abstract:

A Kantian Revision of the Doctrine of Double Effect

Short Answers: Answer the following questions in one paragraph (each is worth 4 points).

Oxford Scholarship Online

Climate Change, Individual Emissions, and Foreseeing Harm

The Trolley Problem. 11 Judith Jarvith Thomson Killing, Letting Die and the Trolley Problem (1976) 59 Oxford University Press 204-

inertia Moral Philos Stud (2008) 140: DOI /s x Sartorio Carolina

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

WORLD UTILITARIANISM AND ACTUALISM VS. POSSIBILISM

Animal Disenhancement

In the Fall PEs many people who wrote about ethics as an Area of Knowledge indicated that ethical perspectives were always a matter of personal

Moral. Dimensions. T. M. Scanlon PERMISSIBILITY, MEANING, BLAME

Trolleys and Double Effect in Experimental Ethics

Putting the Trolley in Order: Experimental Philosophy and the

Ethics From Moral Intuition To Moral Theory

Suicide. 1. Rationality vs. Morality: Kagan begins by distinguishing between two questions:

-- To obtain permission to use this article beyond the scope of your HeinOnline license, please use:

Part 1: Use Counterpoints (pages ) to answer the following questions:

Scanlon s Investigation: The Relevance of Intent to Permissibility *

ETHICS. H istory, Theory, and Contemporary Issues. Steven M. Cahn. Peter Markie FOURTH EDITION. Edited by

THE SO-CALLED DOCTRINE or principle of double effect (hereafter called

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Is it Reasonable to Rely on Intuitions in Ethics? as relying on intuitions, though I will argue that this description is deeply misleading.

Plato s Republic Book 3&4. Instructor: Jason Sheley

Augustine and the Pear Tree

GREEK PHILOSOPHERS AND GOVERNMENT

The Additive Fallacy

Euthanasia, Intentions, and The Doctrine of Killing and Letting Die

The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Ethics.

Utilitarianism. But what is meant by intrinsically good and instrumentally good?

Jeff McMahan, The Ethics of Killing: Problems at the Margins of Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press, xiii pp.

Resolved: The United States should adopt a no first strike policy for cyber warfare.

WHEN is a moral theory self-defeating? I suggest the following.

Why We Shouldn t Reject Conflicts: A Critique of Tadros. The original publication is available at

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

Introduction. In light of these facts, we will ask, is killing animals for human benefit morally permissible?

Instructor: Niko Kolodny Office hours and contact info:

How many people will be studied? We expect about 200 people will be in this research study internationally.

ON PROMOTING THE DEAD CERTAIN: A REPLY TO BEHRENDS, DIPAOLO AND SHARADIN

Intention, the principle of double effect, and military action.

UTILITARIANISM AND INFINITE UTILITY. Peter Vallentyne. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 71 (1993): I. Introduction

Follow this and additional works at: Part of the Arts and Humanities Commons

Frowe's Machine Cases

Responses to the sorites paradox

Ethical Analysis: PRINCIPLISM. Patrick T. Smith, Ph.D.

Quiz 1. Criticisms of consequentialism and Kant. Consequentialism and Nonconsequentialism. Consequentialism in practice. Must Choose Best Possible Act

EUTHANASIA EUTHANASIA NEWS IN CANADA

ACIM Edmonton - Sarah's Reflections. LESSON 135 If I defend myself, I am attacked.

Reductive Individualism and the Just War Framework

Double-Effect Reasoning in Ethical Theory: Its Adversarial Allies 1

TWO DOGMAS OF DEONTOLOGY: AGGREGATION, RIGHTS, AND THE SEPARATENESS OF PERSONS

The Principle of Double Effect

How to Practice Willingness

The Samson Option Longtom Radio. Some right reserved. Free to copy and distribute.

Ethics. Duty, Values, Motives, and Utilitarianism

Life, Lottery, for the Pursuit of Organs

Introduction to. Ethics

Causation and Responsibility

Suppose... Kant. The Good Will. Kant Three Propositions

Exploring Philosophy - Audio Thought experiments

Instructor: Niko Kolodny Office hours and contact info:

Killing Innocent People

THE CASE OF THE MINERS

Ethical Theory. Ethical Theory. Consequentialism in practice. How do we get the numbers? Must Choose Best Possible Act

Ethical Relativism 1. Ethical Relativism: Ethical Relativism: subjective objective ethical nihilism Ice cream is good subjective

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

Taking and Saving Lives

Boethius, The Consolation of Philosophy, book 5

The paradox we re discussing today is not a single argument, but a family of arguments. Here s an example of this sort of argument:!

Transcription:

The Trolley Problem 1. The Trolley Problem: Consider the following pair of cases: Trolley: There is a runaway trolley barreling down the railway tracks. Ahead, on the tracks, there are five people. The trolley is headed straight for them. You are standing some distance off in the train yard, next to a lever. If you pull this lever, the trolley will switch to a different set of tracks. Unfortunately, you notice that there is one person on the side track. You have two options: (1) Do nothing, and the trolley kills the five people on the main track. (2) Pull the lever, diverting the trolley onto the side track where it will kill one person. Fat Man: There is a runaway trolley headed toward five people again. Only, this time, you are not in the train yard next to a lever. You are on a bridge, watching the events from above the tracks. There is a very large man next to you. You realize that, if you push him off the bridge and down onto the tracks below, the trolley will hit and kill him, but his body is so large that it will stop the trolley before it reaches the five endangered people. You have two options: (1) Do nothing, and the trolley kills the five people. (2) Push the large man off the bridge, so that he dies, but the five others are saved. Strangely, 90% of people say that you SHOULD kill the one in Trolley (by pulling the lever), while 95% of people say that you SHOULD NOT kill the one in Fat Man though the results are the same. In each case, the option is to kill 1, or let 5 die. What explains our difference of intuition in these 2 cases? If we think it is wrong to kill 1 to save 5 in cases like Fat Man and Organ Harvest, but permissible to do so in the Trolley case, we must provide some reason for thinking that Trolley and those other cases are different in some morally relevant way. This problem is known as The Trolley Problem (see also here and here). 2. Intending vs. Foreseeing Harm: Philippa Foot (who authored the original Trolley case) suggests that the difference is that, in Fat Man, one intends to harm the fat man as a means to saving the others. In that scenario, it is necessary to use the fat man as a tool in order to save the others (though using him this way will kill him). Meanwhile, in Trolley, one does not intend the harm at all. Rather, one merely foresees it as an unfortunate, unintended side-effect. We do not REQUIRE the death of the one in order to save the five in Trolley. In fact, we would be quite relieved if the one somehow freed himself in time to avoid being hit by the trolley. We would not, if he escaped, chase him down and kill him! Furthermore, it is much worse, morally, to intentionally harm someone as a means to an end than it is to merely foresee that harm will be done to someone as an unintended, unnecessary side-effect of one s ends. 1

Thus, in Trolley, it is permissible to kill the one because one s primary intention is to save the five. The death of the one on the side track is a secondary effect (sometimes called a double-effect. And the principle that intending harm is worse than foreseeing it is sometimes called The Doctrine of Double-Effect, or DDE). Foot suggests that we have different judgments in the two cases because there are really TWO duties of nonmaleficence: (1) The duty not to harm others intentionally as a means to some end, and (2) the duty not to harm others as a foreseen, but unintended side-effect of some action and the former is much stronger than the latter. Application: This distinction nicely explains the wrongness in many other difficult moral cases (e.g., Innocent Conviction, Organ Harvest, and Crowded Cliff). Killing the innocent person is morally wrong in all of those cases, apparently, because the death is a harm that is intended as a means to some other end. Consider also this pair of cases: Strategic Bomber: A pilot bombs a factory that contains the enemy s store of weapons, and thus shortens the war, saving millions of lives. Unfortunately, 10,000 civilians live next to the factory who will die in the bombings. Terror Bomber: A pilot deliberately bombs 10,000 innocent civilians in order to demoralize the enemy, thus shortening the war and saving millions of lives. In Terror Bomber, the 10,000 deaths are intended as a means to ending the war and saving millions of lives. In Strategic Bomber, the deaths of 10,000 is merely a foreseen, but unintended side-effect of ending the war and saving millions. On DDE, strategic bombing is morally permissible, but terror bombing is not and, indeed, the majority of people s intuitions are aligned with this verdict. 3. Objection To The DDE: The following case is said by many to refute the DDE: Looping Trolley: This is the same as Trolley, except that the side track with one person on it is actually a circle, which loops back on to the main track. If you were to pull the lever WITHOUT one person on the side track, the trolley would merely loop around back onto the main track and kill the five. However, since there IS someone on the main track, the trolley hits them and is stopped by their body, thus saving the five. In Looping Trolley, the death of the one is intended as a means to saving the five. However, most people still think it is permissible to pull the lever. Does this render the DDE false? 2

4. Introducing vs. Re-Directing a Harm: A moral distinction that is closely related to the doing-allowing distinction is the distinction between introducing a new threat and merely diverting a pre-existing one. Judith Thomson (who authored the original Fat Man case) considers a pair of cases: Divert The Bomb: Terrorists have launched a nuclear missile at New York City. The only way to prevent the destruction of New York is to divert the missile. Unfortunately, if the missile is diverted, it will hit Ithaca (a much smaller city) instead. The president orders the bomb to be diverted. Explode The Bomb: Terrorists have launched a nuclear missile at New York City. The only way to prevent the destruction of New York is to launch our own nuclear missile to destroy Ithaca. This blast will destroy the terrorist missile as it passes over Ithaca s airspace. The president orders an attack on Ithaca. Thomson thinks that it is ok to divert the bomb, but not to explode it. [Do you share this intuition?] But why should there be any moral difference between the actions if the results are exactly the same? She thinks that the key difference is between (1) diverting a threat that already exists and (2) creating a new one: Diverting A Threat: If a threat exists, and is about to harm a certain number of people, Thomson believes it is morally acceptable to divert that threat onto some lesser number of people (just as long as there are no other morally relevant factors. For example, you did not promise the lesser number of people that you would do everything you could to keep them safe). Introducing A Threat: If a threat exists, and is about to harm a certain number of people, Thomson believes it is morally unacceptable to prevent the harm to those people, if the only way to do so is to create some new threat that was not already there, which harms a different group of (a lesser number of) people. Think of it this way: You are a physician with 5 doses of a certain medicine that will cure a fatal disease. You have 6 six patients. 5 of them would be cured with a single dose. But, the 6 th patient s illness is advanced, and can only be cured if given all 5 doses. It seems permissible, Thomson states, to save the lives of the 5 patients rather than the 1. There is a single benefit, up for distribution, she says. It is permissible to direct it to wherever it will do the most good. This is not only true of benefits, but also for harms. In Trolley, there is a single harm up for distribution. It is permissible to direct it to wherever it will do the least amount of harm. And, if introducing a NEW threat is much worse, morally, than re-directing a pre-existing one, this distinction solves The Trolley Problem: 3

In Trolley, by pulling the lever, you are merely diverting a pre-existing threat from the five onto the one. You do not create any new threat, and your action is therefore morally acceptable. In Fat Man, you save the five by pushing the fat man off of the bridge. However, in doing so, you introduce a new threat to the fat man that was not previously there. Your action is therefore morally unacceptable. Furthermore, this explains why harming the one in cases such as Organ Harvest, Innocent Conviction, and Crowded Cliff are wrong (because they introduce a new harm to the one). 5. Objection To Divert-vs.-Redirect: Thomson thinks that the reason it is wrong to push the fat man, but permissible to pull the lever, is that there is a duty not to harm others by introducing a new threat (even if doing so produces a greater good). This is stronger than the duty not to harm others by diverting a threat to produce a greater good. But, consider the following case: Trolley Initiation: This is the same as the Trolley case, except that the lever, instead of diverting the trolley on the side track, causes two things when pulled: (1) The runaway trolley stops, and (2) A motionless trolley on the side track begins moving. It is still the case that the one dies and five are saved. Surely it should still be permissible to pull the lever in this revised case, even though doing so initiates a threat, rather than diverts one? 6. Conclusion: Note that there are two extreme views that do not yield a trolley problem (though they are still problematic in their own way because so many find these views to be counter-intuitive). Doing vs. Allowing Harm: It is worth mentioning another popular moral distinction. Many believe that DOING harm to someone is much worse, morally, than merely ALLOWING harm to come to them. For instance, most think that, if I were to send missiles to destroy starving people in Africa, this would be wrong. On the other hand, merely sitting back and doing nothing while they starve to death is morally permissible. However, even if doing harm IS worse than allowing harm, this does not explain away The Trolley Problem. For, in both Trolley AND Fat Man, you seem to be DOING harm to the one in order to save the 5 (either by pulling the lever or by pushing the man), rather than merely sitting back and allowing it. Note that some do believe that killing is ABSOLUTELY wrong that is, it is NEVER permissible to do harm. In that case, one should allow the 5 to die in both scenarios. 4

Utilitarianism: Utilitarians do not have a Trolley Problem either. For them, an action is morally wrong if it fails to maximize happiness. As such, you should ALWAYS kill 1 to save 5 (in Trolley, Fat Man, Organ Harvest, etc.). Yet, they seem to deliver the wrong verdict in cases like Fat Man and Organ Harvest. Conclusion: However, if we want to maintain the ideal of capturing the intuitions of ordinary morality, we need to come up with a model which can accurately explain our intuitions in these various cases. Why IS it sometimes permissible to kill one to save five (e.g., in Trolley), and sometimes impermissible (e.g., in Fat Man)? Is there any moral distinction which explains our ethical intuitions in these cases? Answering these questions is, as we have just seen, quite difficult. [Possible suggestion: Perhaps two or more of the distinctions that we have just examined could be COMBINED in some way in order to explain our ordinary intuitions. What do you think?] 5