REVIEW: James R. Brown, The Laboratory of the Mind

Similar documents
REVIEW: Marc Lange, Laws and Lawmakers: Science, Metaphysics, and the Laws of Nature.

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

Intro to Philosophy. Review for Exam 2

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

The British Empiricism

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

PH 1000 Introduction to Philosophy, or PH 1001 Practical Reasoning

MAKING A METAPHYSICS FOR NATURE. Alexander Bird, Nature s Metaphysics: Laws and Properties. Oxford: Clarendon, Pp. xiv PB.

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Do we have knowledge of the external world?

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Against the No-Miracle Response to Indispensability Arguments

Logic, Truth & Epistemology. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Van Fraassen: Arguments concerning scientific realism

Introduction to Deductive and Inductive Thinking 2017

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Reprint of: and: Abstract: Author:

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

The linguistic-cultural nature of scientific truth 1

Philosophy 125 Day 4: Overview

5 A Modal Version of the

How Successful Is Naturalism?

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

The Positive Argument for Constructive Empiricism and Inference to the Best

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo

Some Good and Some Not so Good Arguments for Necessary Laws. William Russell Payne Ph.D.

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Contents EMPIRICISM. Logical Atomism and the beginnings of pluralist empiricism. Recap: Russell s reductionism: from maths to physics

ESSAYS IN HONOR OF CARL G. HEMPEL

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

Ibuanyidanda (Complementary Reflection), African Philosophy and General Issues in Philosophy

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

THE ROLE OF APRIORI, EMPIRICAL, ANALYTIC AND SYNTHETIC IN PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS.

! Jumping ahead 2000 years:! Consider the theory of the self.! What am I? What certain knowledge do I have?! Key figure: René Descartes.

THE CHALLENGES FOR EARLY MODERN PHILOSOPHY: EDITORIAL INTRODUCTION 1. Steffen Ducheyne

Hoong Juan Ru. St Joseph s Institution International. Candidate Number Date: April 25, Theory of Knowledge Essay

COURSE GOALS: PROFESSOR: Chris Latiolais Philosophy Department Kalamazoo College Humphrey House #202 Telephone # Offices Hours:

Epistemic Normativity for Naturalists

AKC Lecture 1 Plato, Penrose, Popper

Epistemology Naturalized

An Empiricist Theory of Knowledge Bruce Aune

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Summary of Sensorama: A Phenomenalist Analysis of Spacetime and Its Contents

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 7 : E P I S T E M O L O G Y - K A N T

Intro to Ground. 1. The idea of ground. 2. Relata. are facts): F 1. More-or-less equivalent phrases (where F 1. and F 2. depends upon F 2 F 2

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

IN THIS PAPER I will examine and criticize the arguments David

Ayer on the argument from illusion

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

The Principle of Sufficient Reason and Free Will

SCIENCE AND METAPHYSICS Part III SCIENTIFIC EPISTEMOLOGY? David Tin Win α & Thandee Kywe β. Abstract

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 110, No. 3. (Jul., 2001), pp

Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn

Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2

DR. LEONARD PEIKOFF. Lecture 3 THE METAPHYSICS OF TWO WORLDS: ITS RESULTS IN THIS WORLD

Skepticism and Internalism

Psillos s Defense of Scientific Realism

Task 1: Philosophical Questions. Question 1: To what extent do you shape your own destiny, and how much is down to fate?

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

The logic of the success/failure system

Practical Inadequacy: Bas van Fraassen's Failures of Systematicity. Curtis Forbes

Qualified Realism: From Constructive Empiricism to Metaphysical Realism.

REVIEW THE DOOR TO SELLARS

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 7 : E P I S T E M O L O G Y - K A N T

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Revision Guide (all topics)

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

A Quick Review of the Scientific Method Transcript

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT David Hume: The Origin of Our Ideas and Skepticism about Causal Reasoning

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

Intuitions in science : thought experiments as argument pumps

Business Research: Principles and Processes MGMT6791 Workshop 1A: The Nature of Research & Scientific Method

Realism and Anti-Realism about Science A Pyrrhonian Stance

Introduction The Science Wars in Perspective

A Warning about So-Called Rationalists

Are Scientific Theories True?

The Illusion of Scientific Realism: An Argument for Scientific Soft Antirealism

Transcription:

REVIEW: James R. Brown, The Laboratory of the Mind Author(s): Michael T. Stuart Source: Spontaneous Generations: A Journal for the History and Philosophy of Science, Vol. 6, No. 1 (2012) 237-241. Published by: The University of Toronto DOI: 10.4245/sponge.v6i1.15820 E D I T O R I A L O F F I C E S Institute for the History and Philosophy of Science and Technology Room 316 Victoria College, 91 Charles Street West Toronto, Ontario, Canada M5S 1K7 hapsat.society@utoronto.ca Published online at jps.library.utoronto.ca/index.php/spontaneousgenerations ISSN 1913 0465 Founded in 2006, Spontaneous Generations is an online academic journal published by graduate students at the Institute for the History and Philosophy of Science and Technology, University of Toronto. There is no subscription or membership fee. Spontaneous Generations provides immediate open access to its content on the principle that making research freely available to the public supports a greater global exchange of knowledge.

R James R. Brown. The Laboratory of the Mind: Thought Experiments in the Natural Sciences. 2nd edition. x + 226 pp. London: Routledge, 2010. * Michael T. Stuart Originally published in 1991, The Laboratory of the Mind: Thought Experiments in the Natural Sciences is the first monograph to identify and address some of the many interesting questions that pertain to thought experiments. While the putative aim of the book is to explore the nature of thought experimental evidence, it has another important purpose which concerns the crucial role thought experiments play in Brown s Platonic master argument. In that argument, Brown argues against naturalism and empiricism (Brown 2012), for mathematical Platonism (Brown 2008), and from the Platonist-friendly, abstract universals posited by the Dretske-Tooley-Armstrong (DTA) account of the laws of nature to a more general, physical Platonism. The Laboratory of the Mind is where he takes this final step. The main philosophical question that motivates Brown s study is the following: how do thought experiments reveal novel truths about the physical world without the need for additional empirical input? As a response, Brown develops a Platonic account of thought experiments that explains their epistemic power by portraying some of them as (occasionally foggy) windows into the Platonic world of forms. Brown s account supplied so much grist for the philosophical mill that it merited a second edition, which includes updated arguments, two additional chapters, a new preface, and a rejuvenated a erword. Brown first acquaints the reader with thought experiments by providing a bevy of examples. These lay the foundation for his taxonomy, which groups thought experiments based on function. The most important category is the Platonic thought experiment, which destroys one theory while simultaneously establishing another in a way that takes us beyond the setup or execution of the thought experiment (p. 41). These special thought experiments work by establishing (in the imagination) the thought-experimental phenomenon (p. 43, brackets in the original). It is the phenomenon that we mentally experience which refutes some theory, and it is the same phenomenon that provides * Received 10 November 2011. Mike is a Ph.D. candidate at the University of Toronto. He would like to thank Yi ach Fehige and James R. Brown for their enduring support. Spontaneous Generations 6:1 (2012) ISSN 1913-0465. University of Toronto. Copyright 2012 by the HAPSAT Society. Some rights reserved. 237

evidence for a new theory by suggesting something about the laws of nature. However, to appreciate the appeal of Brown s position fully, we need to view it in relation to that of his philosophical counterpart, John D. Norton. Norton is convinced that thought experiments are epistemically no different from arguments (Norton 1991; 1996; 2004a; 2004b). Since everyone accepts that arguments are capable of producing new information from old, Norton claims that we should adopt the default empiricist view that thought experiments are merely arguments. As we ve seen, one way Brown opposes this account is by describing thought experiments as processes that produce phenomena, and then trying to show that producing phenomena is not the same thing as making a step-by-step propositional inference. To this end, Brown introduces a new type of thought experiment he calls a counter thought experiment (introduced in his new Chapter Three). These are thought experiments that work by denying the phenomena of another thought experiment, which they do by presenting contrasting phenomena of their own. Since they work on phenomena, using phenomena, their function must be orthogonal to the parts of a thought experiment that may be reconstructed as an argument. Since 2004, Norton s position has become more flexible, identifying thought experiments not only as deductive and inductive, but informal arguments as well, which may or may not be identifiable because of tacit premises or inferences. But as it still limits thought experiments to manipulations of propositional content, Brown s account will appeal to any who see mental reasoning as non-propositional. A er discussing counter thought experiments, Brown introduces his mathematical Platonism in Chapter Four. He anticipates the usual twofold response from empiricists: Platonism does not respect the causal theory of knowledge, and it proposes no theory of its own to explain how Platonic perception works or when it goes wrong. To the first, Brown presents several convincing counterarguments to the causal theory of knowledge. Further, he claims that quantum mechanics allows for knowledge that cannot (even possibly) be tied to physical measurement or observation. 1 Brown concedes that the second objection is serious, but argues that our ability to perceive abstract truths is no more mysterious than our apparently innocuous ability to arrive at abstract entities (thoughts, beliefs, etc.) from sensory input. Given mathematical Platonism, Brown begins to argue for physical Platonism. There are two non-mutually exclusive ways to view Brown s argument here: (1) Analogical: in the same way that mathematical picture proofs allow us to see mathematical objects and relations, thought experiments allow us to see the laws of nature (p. 98); and (2) Inference to the best explanation: to explain successful thought-experimenting in science, we must posit Platonic 1 For more on this, the reader should refer to Brown s Platonic interpretation of quantum mechanics given in Chapter Eight. Spontaneous Generations 6:1(2012) 238

access to the laws of nature (p. 124). Both of these strategies are in harmony (p. 107) with the best account of laws of nature (p. 72), the DTA account. This account portrays laws as necessary relations among abstract universals. Assuming harmony with Brown s Platonism, we should ask: is this really the best account of laws of nature? Perhaps not. Since 1991, the DTA account has lost quite a bit of ground to other realist accounts, including dispositional essentialism and property and structural realism. These accounts ground events and objects in more fundamental metaphysical entities like categories, essences, structures, properties, etc. 2 The question becomes: could these accounts be adopted in support of Platonism? Someone like Brown could certainly argue that we have Platonic access to the dispositions, properties, structures, or essences that these accounts postulate. This is especially obvious in the case of structural realism, a position which sometimes advances abstract universals and emphasizes the metaphysical priority of relations (see Stein 1989, 59). But even if we allow for the possibility of Platonic perception and the existence of universals, there remain some interesting questions. While Brown claims that we see the laws of nature using thought experiments, what he really wants to say is that we see the universals that figure into those relations (p. 98, 107). I wonder if the necessary relations into which the universals figure are entailed by the universals themselves. If so, this works quite nicely with Peacocke s (2000) and BonJour s (1998) views of the a priori. If they are not entailed, do we learn about them empirically, Platonically, or both? Since we can grasp mathematical objects, and there is no empirical way to find the relations between them, we must also be able to grasp the relations Platonically as well. So if Brown s analogy holds, we should be able to grasp the relations between physically instantiated universals in the same way. Brown cites experiment as a separate path to knowledge of the relations between universals. Are these two paths always open, and which has priority when they conflict? The same questions arise with respect to the entailment between a law of nature and its corresponding physical regularity: is this entailment deductive, perceived, observed, or some combination of all three? There is another issue concerning Platonic thought experiments and laws of nature, which is related to the possibility of a unified account of thought experiments. Rachel Cooper (2005) argues that we should strive for an account of thought experiments that ranges over all fields of inquiry, not just science. If there are Platonic thought experiments in fields outside of physics and mathematics, those fields must have their own laws of nature for the Platonic 2 See, e.g., A. Chakravar y, A Metaphysics for Scientific Realism: Knowing the Unobservable, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007); B. Ellis, The Metaphysics of Scientific Realism, (Acumen: Durham, 2009); S. French, The Interdependence of Structure, Objects and Dependence, Synthese 175(1) (2010): 89-109; and A. Bokulich and P. Bokulich, eds., Scientific Structuralism, (Dordrecht: Springer, 2010). Spontaneous Generations 6:1(2012) 239

thought experiments to see. Brown hints early on (p. 31) that the lack of thought experiments in chemistry might be due to the absence of laws in that discipline. If chemical laws are reducible to physical laws, it seems natural that there should be no Platonic thought experiments in chemistry. But what about philosophy? Philosophy is full of thought experiments meant to disprove one theory and simultaneously establish another. By Brown s logic, this should imply that there are necessarily related abstract universals in the domains of metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, etc., to which these thought experiments give access. Brown may be happy to admit laws of metaphysics and personal identity and so on, since when it comes to abstract entities, the Platonist s mo o is the more the merrier. However, admi ing laws here might make a Platonic account of laws less appealing to those already on the fence. In the remainder of the book, Brown applies his theory to scientific episodes and actors from the pre-socratics to quantum mechanics. One episode features Einstein, who is justifiably known as one of the most important thought experimenters since Galileo. An issue here concerns the standard interpretation of Einstein as an ageing verificationist, who nonetheless employed unverifiable thought experiments. This would make him methodologically inconsistent. Brown provides a reconstruction of Einstein s meta-philosophical stance on the relation of theory to evidence which harmonizes Einstein s use of thought experiments with his other writings. Yet, it is interesting to note that Einstein expressed vehement distaste for even the use of the phrase thought experiment when applied to his arguments (see Kühne 2005, 227-29). This suggests that more work needs to be done to square Brown s account of Einstein with Einstein s own, perhaps misdirected remarks (but see Ierodiakonou and Roux 2011, 1-27). Whether you will be romanced by Platonism or not, this book is invaluable reading for anyone with overlapping interests in the history and philosophy of science, or the traditional debates of metaphysics and epistemology. Empiricists will find a stimulating opponent, rationalists will find ammunition for their cause, and all will appreciate the clear prose and lasting philosophical issues with which Brown has almost single-handedly fathered the growing subfield that now studies thought experiments. M T. S IHPST, University of Toronto 91 Charles St. W. Toronto, ON Canada M5S 1K mike.stuart@utoronto.ca Spontaneous Generations 6:1(2012) 240

R BonJour, Lawrence. 1998. In Defense of Pure Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Brown, James R. 2008. Philosophy of Mathematics: A Contemporary Introduction to the World of Proofs and Pictures. London: Routledge. Brown, James R. 2010. The Laboratory of the Mind: Thought Experiments in the Natural Sciences, 2nd ed. London: Routledge. Brown, James R. 2012. Numbers and Nature: Platonism, Naturalism, and Mathematical Knowledge. London: Routledge. Cooper, Rachel. 2005. Thought Experiments. Metaphilosophy 36(3) (April): 328-47. Kühne, Ulrich. 2005. Die Methode des Gedankenexperiments. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. Norton, John D. 1991. Thought Experiments in Einstein s Work. In Thought Experiments in Science and Philosophy, eds. Tamara Horowitz and Gerald Massey, 129-48. Savage: Rowman and Li lefield. Norton, John D. 1996. Are Thought Experiments Just What You Thought? Canadian Journal of Philosophy 26(3) (September): 333-66. Norton, John D. 2004a. Why Thought Experiments Do Not Transcend Empiricism. In Contemporary Debates in the Philosophy of Science, ed. Christopher Hitchcock, 44 66. Somerset: Wiley-Blackwell. Norton, John D. 2004b. On Thought Experiments: Is There More to the Argument? Philosophy of Science 71(5) (April): 1139-51. Peacocke, Christopher. 2000. Explaining the A Priori: The Programme of Moderate Rationalism. In New Essays on the A Priori, eds. Paul Boghossian and Christopher Peacocke, 255-85. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Stein, Howard. 1989. Yes, but Some skeptical remarks on realism and antirealism. Dialectica 43(1-2): 47 65. Spontaneous Generations 6:1(2012) 241