animals Animals 2011, 1, ; doi: /ani ISSN Book Review Ben Mepham

Similar documents
THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING

Clarifications on What Is Speciesism?

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

Attfield, Robin, and Barry Wilkins, "Sustainability." Environmental Values 3, no. 2, (1994):

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan

Disvalue in nature and intervention *

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles.

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

Philosophical approaches to animal ethics

A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University THE DEMANDS OF ACT CONSEQUENTIALISM

Summary Kooij.indd :14

Well-Being, Disability, and the Mere-Difference Thesis. Jennifer Hawkins Duke University

Action in Special Contexts

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

Explore the Christian rationale for environmental ethics and assess its strengths and weaknesses.

Why economics needs ethical theory

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

The Discounting Defense of Animal Research

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

Ethical Theory for Catholic Professionals

The dangers of the sovereign being the judge of rationality

The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970)

Reply to Brooke Alan Trisel James Tartaglia *

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Conditionals II: no truth conditions?

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

In this response, I will bring to light a fascinating, and in some ways hopeful, irony

Meta-Debate: A necessity for any debate style.

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Consider... Ethical Egoism. Rachels. Consider... Theories about Human Motivations

Born Free and Equal? On the ethical consistency of animal equality summary Stijn Bruers

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things:

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

It s time to stop believing scientists about evolution

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

Overview: Application: What to Avoid:

From: Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (2005)

Religion, Ecology & the Future of the Human Species

We recommend you cite the published version. The publisher s URL is:

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Human rights, universalism and conserving human rights practice

SANDEL ON RELIGION IN THE PUBLIC SQUARE

The role of ethical judgment based on the supposed right action to perform in a given

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

When is philosophy intercultural? Outlooks and perspectives. Ram Adhar Mall

Introduction to Animal Welfare Ethics Lecture Notes

by scientists in social choices and in the dialogue leading to decision-making.

COMITÉ SUR LES AFFAIRES RELIGIEUSES A NEW APPROACH TO RELIGIOUS EDUCATION IN SCHOOL: A CHOICE REGARDING TODAY S CHALLENGES

Secularization in Western territory has another background, namely modernity. Modernity is evaluated from the following philosophical point of view.

WHY RELATIVISM IS NOT SELF-REFUTING IN ANY INTERESTING WAY

BETWEEN THE SPECIES Issue V August 2005

The fact that some action, A, is part of a valuable and eligible pattern of action, P, is a reason to perform A. 1

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

BIBLICAL INTEGRATION IN SCIENCE AND MATH. September 29m 2016

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

This document is downloaded from DR-NTU, Nanyang Technological University Library, Singapore.

Warren. Warren s Strategy. Inherent Value. Strong Animal Rights. Strategy is to argue that Regan s strong animals rights position is not persuasive

Comments on "Lying with Conditionals" by Roy Sorensen

Interview with Edward Farley From the web site Resources for American Christianity

Christ-Centered Critical Thinking. Lesson 6: Evaluating Thinking

ZAGZEBSKI ON RATIONALITY

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

IN DEFENSE OF AN ANIMAL S RIGHT TO LIFE. Aaron Simmons. A Dissertation

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

Some proposals for understanding narrow content

Care of the Soul: Service-Learning and the Value of the Humanities

U.S. Bishops Revise Part Six of the Ethical and Religious Directives An Initial Analysis by CHA Ethicists 1

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION AND ARISTOTELIAN THEOLOGY TODAY

The Critical Mind is A Questioning Mind

Sentence Starters from They Say, I Say

SCIENTIFIC THEORIES ABOUT THE ORIGINS OF THE WORLD AND HUMANITY

H U M a N I M A L I A 3:2

Thesis Statements. (and their purposes)

Raimo Tuomela: Social Ontology: Collective Intentionality and Group Agents. New York, USA: Oxford University Press, 2013, 326 pp.

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS

EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Freedom of Religion and Law Schools: Trinity Western University

HOW TO BE (AND HOW NOT TO BE) A NORMATIVE REALIST:

Oxford Scholarship Online

PROSPECTIVE TEACHERS UNDERSTANDING OF PROOF: WHAT IF THE TRUTH SET OF AN OPEN SENTENCE IS BROADER THAN THAT COVERED BY THE PROOF?

book review Out of Time The Limits of Secular Critique MACQUARIE UNIVERSITY

Environmental Ethics. Espen Gamlund, PhD Associate Professor of Philosophy University of Bergen

Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008

When does human life begin? by Dr Brigid Vout

To link to this article:

Discussing Laudato Si In Your Congregation A Guide

Causation and Free Will

Do we have responsibilities to future generations? Chris Groves

Phenomenal Consciousness and Intentionality<1>

Use the following checklist to make sure you have revised everything.

PROSPECTS FOR A JAMESIAN EXPRESSIVISM 1 JEFF KASSER

Transcription:

Animals 2011, 1, 200-204; doi:10.3390/ani1010200 OPEN ACCESS animals ISSN 2076-2615 www.mdpi.com/journal/animals Book Review The Animal Rights Debate: Abolition or Regulation? By Gary L. Francione and Robert Garner. Columbia University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2010; Paperback, 144 pp; $23.05; ISBN: 978-0231149556; Hardcover, 288 pp; $74.10; ISBN: 978-0231149549 Ben Mepham Centre for Applied Bioethics, School of Biosciences, University of Nottingham, Sutton Bonington Campus, LE12 5RD, UK; E-Mail: ben.mepham@nottingham.ac.uk Received: 8 March 2011 / Accepted: 11 March 2011 / Published: 15 March 2011 The simple, but quite unusual plan, promised much: two leading academics (Gary Francione and Robert Garner) prepared to make their respective cases with conviction and candour, followed by a lively debate between them, during which no stone need be left unturned. In prospect, then, was an opportunity for nuances to be clarified, misunderstandings dispelled and some common ground established. But while it proved to be an enthralling engagement, the apparent inability of one author to concede even an inch of ground to the other s case meant that the divide between the viewpoints was, regrettably, no narrower at the end than at the beginning. Francione, a law professor at Rutgers University in the USA, is a leading philosopher of animal rights theory. He has pioneered the abolitionist theory of animal rights, claiming that animal welfare regulation is both theoretically and practically unsound, and serves merely to prolong the status of animals as property by making the public feel comfortable about using happy animals. Accordingly, abolishing animal use, e.g., by adopting strict veganism, is the only acceptable course of action and the only basis on which people ought to be encouraged to relate to animals. Garner, a politics professor at Leicester University, UK, is a political theorist who specialises in the field of animal protection. One of his major concerns (as summarised on his website) is the difficulties of protecting the interests of animals from within the liberal tradition: focusing on the costs, for liberal societies, of adopting animal rights; the impact of liberal neutrality as regards the good society; and the protection of human autonomy. While acknowledging the importance of campaigning for veganism, and indeed practising it personally, he considers it can realistically only form one part of an overall program to encourage more ethical treatment of animals.

Animals 2011, 1 201 The contents of the book fall into three, roughly equal, parts, viz. Francione s essay, The abolition of animal exploitation, Garner s essay, A defence of a broad animal protectionism, and the discussion between the two. In essence, both the essays and the discussion epitomise the marked differences that prevail between a lawyer s categorical, legalistic, approach and the much more pragmatic, politically-informed, approach of a political scientist. In the following, reference to specific points is made by quoting in parentheses the pages on which they are made. Francione s position is based on several strong assertions. For example, he claims that: ethical veganism is a recognition of the moral personhood of animals, for which the only cognitive characteristic required is that they be sentient (p. 15), a condition which is itself inconsistent with the property status of animals, and with any animal use, however humane (p. 4). While conceding that there are relevant differences between the minds of humans and non-humans, these are not logically relevant to whether they are used in experiments or killed for other purposes (p. 19), because to say that a sentient being is not harmed by death denies that the sentient being has the very interest that sentience serves to perpetuate (pp. 15,16). These rights arguments are supported by several consequentialist claims, e.g., that animal welfare regulations do not work, and that there is absolutely no evidence whatsoever that animal welfare reform will reduce animal use in future (p. 26); that most human disease is due to consumption of animal products (p. 29), which are also a disaster for the environment (p. 28); and that welfarism has not decreased animal use (p. 47) in fact, animal advocacy groups have aided the meat industry (p. 46). Unsurprisingly, the categorical nature of such assertions encounters some difficult issues. The thorny question of how to cope with the needs of billions of non-humans on a shrinking planet is answered by arguing that we should stop bringing animals into existence (p. 79), an objective which is facilitated by the belief that sterilisation is consistent with abolitionist programs (p. 80). For however well we treat non-human companions, they are completely dependent on humans for every aspect of their existence (p. 79). And in response to the alleged inconsistency that vegans appear unconcerned by the harms accidentally inflicted on wildlife in cultivating crops or in building roads, Francione argues that although it is impossible to avoid such secondary effects, they are different morally from intentionally killing an individual animal (p. 72). In conclusion, Francione argues that bringing about a paradigm shift in our relationship with animals would be best achieved by a program of clear, unequivocal, non-violent education targeted at abolishing all animal use (p. 85). For, if instead of the dominant welfarist approach, an abolitionist agenda had been pursued in the past, there likely would be many hundreds of thousands more vegans than there are today (p. 65). Garner s approach is quite different in style and in the assumptions made about how improvements in the condition of non-humans might best be achieved. For him: it is important to distinguish between what is prescribed by ethics and what is achievable politically or strategically, because any viable moral discourse must take into account more than rationalistic ethical principles (p. 105). Like Francione, he stresses that sentience is a crucial factor in ascribing ethical standing to animals, but this does not equate with the notion that animals have personhood (p. 113) For example, loss of life causes harms to humans that, inter alia, entail loss of beliefs, desires, goals, projects etc. experiences of a qualitatively different nature from those experienced by animals (p. 116).

Animals 2011, 1 202 In answer to Francione s claim that animal welfare measures introduced have been counter-productive because people feel more comfortable about eating meat from happier animals, Garner argues that the improvements are in themselves desirable, and that claims about the likely effectiveness of vegan campaigns are highly speculative (p. 122): indeed, it is possible that matters might be worse if all efforts had been directed to an abolitionist program. The political reality is that no country in the world has prohibited use of animals in medical research or as a source of food (p. 125). Garner agrees that much of what is currently permitted under the aegis of animal welfare ought to be banned (p. 119), but suggests that no measure that does not at the same time promote benefit to humans is likely to gain a hearing (p. 126). Fundamentally, he argues that abolitionist aims are unrealistic because the underlying principle that animals have a moral status close, if not identical, to humans is not accepted by the vast majority of society (p. 143). The political reality for Garner is that the battle of ideas in a liberal democratic society is conducted in a pluralistic universe where the rationale is not for one set of ideas to prevail but for a plurality of ideas to coexist (p. 148), conditions which, e.g., have been the guiding force behind post-war legislation on homosexuality in some western societies. In this context, he cites the late John Rawls, who stressed the importance, in seeking sound political decisions, of reflective equilibrium, i.e., the need to check rational principles with moral intuitions. The upshot is that, for him, the advantage of concentrating on eliminating unnecessary suffering is that it maximises public support, and is progressive in that what is deemed unnecessary has expanded over recent decades, reflecting greater public awareness, changes in cultural norms and technological developments (p. 142). Although the discussion is presented as a verbatim dialogue, it would be interesting to know precisely how it was conducted. For example, were the discussants present in the same room or conversing by telephone? Did the discussion occupy more than one session? Since the published version is word perfect, one suspects it was edited and if so it presumably lost some spontaneity, and hence authenticity. Even so, the discussion is a revealing part of the book, although perhaps not entirely in ways the protagonists might have anticipated. Without attempting a blow-by-blow summary of the exchange, I doubt that I am the only reader to be left with an impression of a discussion characterised by Francione s somewhat strident approach, to which Garner responded with remarkable amiability. And while Garner was prepared to acknowledge several areas of agreement, Francione s only reciprocal response was the single word agreed, in the book s final sentence, to the proposition that currently animals endure unacceptable levels of suffering. Not even the revelation that Garner was a dietary vegan, in reply to Francione s personal question, elicited any recorded response (p. 257). A discussion where one participant seems unprepared to concede any merit in the opposing perspective, a condition which is perhaps intrinsic to an absolutist, abolitionist stance, hardly provides fertile ground for intellectual enquiry. Yet it might have been anticipated that the fact that both participants reputedly sought to achieve desired changes incrementally would have provided a sound basis for fruitful discussion. Readers of this review will doubtless detect a bias in views expressed here, but there are some matters (perhaps like the appropriateness of nudism, or belief in astrological predictions!) which it is virtually impossible for a thoughtful person to approach with a completely open mind. Acknowledging that caveat, Francione seems to me to be guilty of making several assertions that are either speculative in the extreme or based on a very limited consideration, or understanding, of objective evidence.

Animals 2011, 1 203 One example that must suffice to make a point of more general validity is his claim that Animal agriculture is a disaster for the environment because it involves a very inefficient use of natural resources... (p. 28). While the statement is accurate in the case of many intensive animal production systems, it is certainly not universally true. Thus, the claim ignores those, admittedly rarely-practised, forms of animal husbandry (but how can vegans dismiss claims merely because they are made by other minorities?), which operate within a permaculture livestock economy, and that achieve efficient food productivity in socially and ecologically integrated systems, in which the by-product of one component is easily available to provide the feedstock of another. The quotation is from Simon Fairlie s book [1], which might be read with advantage by vegans, not least because Fairlie s aim was to provide both a critique of veganism and a tribute to vegans and vegetarians from Shelley onwards.... Fairlie s point assumes enormous significance in terms of the environmental crisis that humanity faces in consequence of the combined effects of climate change and diminishing fossil fuel reserves; developments that imply the urgent need to adopt sustainable practices entailing energy descent. In achieving the latter, energy will necessarily be largely derived from biomass, renewable resources such as wind, water and solar, and increased use of muscle power; and farm animals could play an effective role in different elements of this process. The Farncione/Garner book certainly provides clear expositions of contrasting attitudes, but the territory explored often seems rather abstract, omitting consideration of several critical issues. So in conclusion it is perhaps appropriate to identify some of these. For example, the ethical implications of the following surely merit attention. (i) The resources allocated to concern for animals as opposed to those employed to address human survival, suffering or wellbeing which may entail substantial opportunity costs for vegans. For example, the energy and time expended in ensuring dietary integrity, and promoting the vegan cause, is necessarily denied to efforts to ease the suffering of humans, of whom about one billion suffer from malnutrition in less-economically developed countries, while many, world-wide, are victims of abuse and exploitation. (ii) The rights and interests of humans at the level of personal health and wellbeing, in societies whose economies, cultures and, in some cases survival, depend on a symbiotic relationship with animals. The discussion in the book seems dominated by attitudes and conditions in western developed countries. (iii) The fate of prey, and more generally of adverse effects on ecological sustainability in the wild (including animal and plant species in managed wildlife reserves), of permitting predators, and wild species in general, to satisfy their biological needs. If sentience is the sole relevant characteristic in granting animals rights, what could be the ethical basis of showing partiality to domesticated rather than wild animals? (iv) The adverse effects on wild animals (at individual, group and species levels) of practices employed in arable farming, on which most vegan diets are necessarily dependent. For example, pest control, not only of insects but also of indisputably sentient mammals like rabbits and mice, is crucial for efficient arable farming. Is it really valid to argue that since the adverse effects on wild animals are accidental they are beyond vegans ethical concern?

Animals 2011, 1 204 (v) The basis of the distinction assigned to the meaning of property in the cases of farmed animals (especially when kept in organic, and particularly permacultural, systems) and rescued companion animals. Indeed, it is pertinent that there is a real sense in which human children are, when young, their parents property without this being considered remotely problematical from an ethical perspective. The rigour with which vegans attempt to lead lives according to the strict observance of ethical principles is often regarded as exemplary, and vegan philosophy certainly represents a significant challenge to long-established norms of behaviour. But if the aim of ethics is to choose the right, or best, course of action in specific circumstances all things considered, it is arguable that adherence to such an absolutist agenda is simplistic and open to serious self-contradictions. Or, as Farlie puts it, with characteristic panache: to conclude that veganism is the only ethical response is to take a big leap into a very muddy pond (p. 2). References 1. Fairlie, S. Meat: A Benign Extravagance; Chelsea Green: White River Junction, VT, USA, 2010; p. 41. 2011 by the authors; licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/3.0/).