Colin Bradley University of Chicago

Similar documents
Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge Gracia's proposal

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Intro to Ground. 1. The idea of ground. 2. Relata. are facts): F 1. More-or-less equivalent phrases (where F 1. and F 2. depends upon F 2 F 2

5 A Modal Version of the

Postmodal Metaphysics

A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge

Aboutness and Justification

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Published in Analysis 61:1, January Rea on Universalism. Matthew McGrath

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988)

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Tuomas E. Tahko (University of Helsinki)

1 Why should you care about metametaphysics?

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan

Against the No-Miracle Response to Indispensability Arguments

The Question of Metaphysics

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

a0rxh/ On Van Inwagen s Argument Against the Doctrine of Arbitrary Undetached Parts WESLEY H. BRONSON Princeton University

Philosophy 125 Day 13: Overview

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Emergence Cannot Save Dualism, but Neo-Aristotelianism Might

Truth and Modality - can they be reconciled?

What is consciousness? Although it is possible to offer

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to

Postscript to Plenitude of Possible Structures (2016)

What We Are: Our Metaphysical Nature & Moral Implications

DO TROPES RESOLVE THE PROBLEM OF MENTAL CAUSATION?

A lonelier contractualism A. J. Julius, UCLA, January

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

METHODISM AND HIGHER-LEVEL EPISTEMIC REQUIREMENTS Brendan Murday

Nancey Murphy, Bodies and Souls, or Spirited Bodies? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006). Pp. x Hbk, Pbk.

Truth-Grounding and Transitivity

Framing the Debate over Persistence

God from God: The Essential Dependence Model of Eternal Generation

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

Entity Grounding and Truthmaking

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

Nagel, Naturalism and Theism. Todd Moody. (Saint Joseph s University, Philadelphia)

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

The Problem of Identity and Mereological Nihilism. the removal of an assumption of unrestricted mereological composition, and from there a

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

Nature and its Classification

Deflationary Nominalism s Commitment to Meinongianism

Kant and his Successors

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is

An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine. Foreknowledge and Free Will. Alex Cavender. Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division

Metaphysical Dependence and Set Theory

Metaphysics as the First Philosophy

Descartes. Efficient and Final Causation

Time travel and the open future

3. Campos de conocimiento en los que podría ser anunciado (máximo dos):

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Reviewed by Colin Marshall, University of Washington

Privilege in the Construction Industry. Shamik Dasgupta Draft of February 2018

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

Against the Vagueness Argument TUOMAS E. TAHKO ABSTRACT

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

On A New Cosmological Argument

Class #13 - The Consciousness Theory of the Self Locke, The Prince and the Cobbler Reid, Of Mr. Locke's Account of Our Personal Identity

Stang (p. 34) deliberately treats non-actuality and nonexistence as equivalent.

Truthmakers for Negative Existentials

Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology* Oxford University Press, 2009

Compositional Pluralism and Composition as Identity

Skepticism and Internalism

SPINOZA S VERSION OF THE PSR: A Critique of Michael Della Rocca s Interpretation of Spinoza

Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason

Spinoza, Ethics 1 of 85 THE ETHICS. by Benedict de Spinoza (Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata) Translated from the Latin by R. H. M.

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY

Nested Testimony, Nested Probability, and a Defense of Testimonial Reductionism Benjamin Bayer September 2, 2011

Idealism and the Harmony of Thought and Reality

Epistemic Consequentialism, Truth Fairies and Worse Fairies

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

Do Ordinary Objects Exist? No. * Trenton Merricks. Current Controversies in Metaphysics edited by Elizabeth Barnes. Routledge Press. Forthcoming.

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio

Do Ordinary Objects Exist? No. * Trenton Merricks. Current Controversies in Metaphysics edited by Elizabeth Barnes. Routledge Press. Forthcoming.

A Complex Eternity. One of the central issues in the philosophy of religion is the relationship between

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

Presentism, persistence and trans-temporal dependence

A note on science and essentialism

Varieties of Apriority

Quaerens Deum: The Liberty Undergraduate Journal for Philosophy of Religion

No Physical Particles for a Dispositional Monist? Baptiste Le Bihan Université de Rennes 1. Draft (Forthcoming in Philosophical Papers)

Under contract with Oxford University Press Karen Bennett Cornell University

Transcription:

hylomorphic substance and ontological independence Colin Bradley University of Chicago abstract There are two notions of substance enjoying some vogue in neo-aristotelian metaphysics. The first is an idea of substance as an ontologically independent entity. The second notion is more familiar: substance as a hylomorphic compound of form and matter. However, given most interpretations of this sort of compound, it appears that any hylomorphic substance depends for its very being on either its form or its matter or both. This raises a question about whether and how we can understand both ontological dependence and hylomorphic compounds so that we can preserve both notions. In this paper, I examine two recent attempts to resolve this problem by Kathrin Koslicki and E.J. Lowe. I argue that both end up side-stepping rather than actually resolving the problem. I give an account that attempts to preserve what is correct in each approach, and recommend a path toward a genuine solution. There are two conceptions of metaphysical substance both commanding venerable histories (tracing their lineage to Aristotle) and with a great deal of independent motivation, which seem to conflict quite violently. These are the notion of substance as an ontologically independent entity, and the notion of substance as a hylomorphic compound that is, as an entity essentially comprising form and matter. Presumably such an entity would be ontologically dependent on either its form, its matter, or both. Most plausible accounts of ontological independence stipulate that for any entity to be considered independent, it cannot stand in any essential dependence relations to any entities distinct from itself. An entity s form and its matter, while perhaps internal in some way to the entity, are nonetheless considered 42

colin bradley distinct items. The entity then, on the desirable account of substance specifically as an independent entity, could not qualify as a substance, since it would depend for its being what it is on something distinct from itself. One way to bring this tension out is through the trajectory of Aristotle s own writings. In the Categories, where the idea of a substance as metaphysically independent originates, the paradigmatic substances are individuals like this individual horse or human being. Later in Physics and Metaphysics, however, Aristotle begins to explore the possibility that those individuals which were taken as something like an unanalyzable simple were actually much more complex, comprising both form and matter, combined in a certain way. Yet on this view, the hylomorphic conception of substance, the view of substance as independent appears either irrelevant or incorrect. There are at least two recent attempts to resolve this problem undertaken by Kathrin Koslicki and E.J. Lowe. Neither Koslicki nor Lowe, I will argue, provides a satisfactory solution to this particular problem. Koslicki s proposal (though perhaps not the one she personally endorses) is based on distinguishing between so-called simple substances on one hand, and composite substances on the other. She then provides separate criteria for substancehood for each type of substance. On the face of it, the resulting bifurcation of the concept substance instills doubt that we are left with just one unique concept instead of two related ones. Lowe s alternative solution requires taking on an extremely substantive position in which all ordinary objects are to be identified with their forms. In that case there are no hylomorphic compounds, properly speaking, and the problem ostensibly vanishes. I show that Lowe s account, in addition to requiring one to adopt further substantive metaphysical commitments runs into several difficulties. I argue rather that we should use Koslicki s framework, but I suggest several reasons for rejecting her distinction between simple and composite substances for the sake of providing a sufficient set of criteria for substancehood. i. koslicki s bifurcated account Kathrin Koslicki 1 considers various ways to provide criteria for substances based 1. It should be remarked that Koslicki personally favors another option, having nothing to do with ontological independence. I will therefore speak, when appropriate, of the Koslicki-theorist. 43

hylomorphic substance and ontological independence on ontological independence, continuing a tradition that has its roots in Aristotle s Categories and is enjoying a contemporary vogue largely due to the work of Jonathan Schaffer (2009), Gideon Rosen (2010), and Kit Fine (1995). She settles finally on the following (Koslicki, in progress): ( 4) ( ): x is a composite substance def (i) x is composite and (ii) there is no y such that (a) y is not identical with x, (b) x is essentially identity right way. 2 It will be noticed right away that this definition stipulates that the substance be composite, rather than simple. Why might that be? In a previous attempt at defining substance in terms of independence, Koslicki wants to allow that a substance might ontologically depend on its proper parts (here revised in terms of an intrinsic/extrinsic distinction), while remaining a substance, that is, an ontologically independent item. An objection is then raised (attributed to Patrick Toner) that this definition unfairly excludes potential simple substances, i.e., substances which have no proper parts at all and which therefore, a fortiori, cannot ontologically depend on their essential proper parts (Koslicki, in progress). To accommodate this, Koslicki adopts two different criteria and suggests the following criterion for these simple substances: ( ) x is a simple substance def (i) x is simple and (ii) there is no y such that (a) y is not identical with x and (b) x is essentially identity dependent on y. This raises an obvious question: What is the significance of having two different definitions? The move comes in response to a perspicacious question asked by Toner: Why accept that simple substances, which are self-sufficient in one way (a way 2. The notion of essential identity dependence is from (Lowe 2005): x is essentially identity dependent on y def There is some function such that it is part of the essence of x that x = (y). x s relation to y. 44

colin bradley that doesn t exclude dependence on their parts) are the same kind of things as substances that are self-sufficient in a very different kind of way (a way that does except dependence on their parts)? (40) Why should we think that any item which receives substance-status through the back door, that is, by the exception provided by ICCS4 (ii.c), is of the same metaphysical category is the same kind of thing as a simple substance, i.e. one without parts, or numerically distinct intrinsic properties? Koslicki grants the objection, and therefore finds herself with two different conceptions of substance. But, nonetheless, she maintains they both count as substance. How can she think so? She argues: There is after all a non-ad-hoc and metaphysically significant distinction between simple entities and composite entities. Assuming that a criterion of substancehood serves as an indicator of ontological fundamentality, it is perhaps no surprise that there might be distinct roads towards ontological fundamentality, among them one for simple entities and another for composite entities. (15) Of course, there is a difference between distinct roads to the same place and drastically different tolls charged at the gate once you get there. Koslicki appears to conflate the notion of substance as ontologically fundamental, and as ontologically independent. The notion she used to motivate her discussion was one of ontological independence. But as Kit Fine has pointed out (albeit in a slightly different context), there is not sufficient reason to demonstrate that whatever is ontologically independent must also be taken to be ontologically fundamental (Fine 2001). 3 Koslicki s bifurcated notion of substance removes ontological independence from its privileged explanatory role. Instead she relies on the questionable inference from ontological independence to fundamentality, and merely asserts that the enlarged concept of substance is to be co-extensive with that fundamentality. ii. not-so-simple substances 3. Rather, Fine argues that we should take metaphysical fundamentality (or, Reality as he puts it) as a primitive notion that is correlated with the relational notion of metaphysical dependence, but cannot be assumed to stand as the terminus of an aggregation of x is dependent on y is dependent on z is dependent on relations. 45

hylomorphic substance and ontological independence I suggest that we resist Koslicki s response to Toner s objection. In particular, I would like to resist the idea of simple substances, or at least that such items would be different enough from composite substances so as to warrant their own definition. Imagine a machine that spits out substance candidates. It has been programmed according to a certain formula to output candidates according to the following configuration: SubstanceCandidate(Form: ; Matter: ). A substance candidate can therefore be one of three sorts: form-without-matter, matter-withoutform, or a combination of both form and matter. The majority (and perhaps even all) substances will receive both form and matter. However as the brackets indicate, these are both to be construed as internal to the substance, and therefore do not jeopardize its ontological independence status given ICCS4 or something similar. Now we consider the limiting cases. Imagine the machine outputting a hunk of matter-without-form. Perhaps we can try to think of some unspecified quantity of shapeless liquid. Whatever, if anything, these may turn out to be, any item of this sort is unlikely to be a substance-candidate, victims rather to the unity clause of ICCS4. The Koslicki-theorist suggests that as an example of matter-withoutform we might take physical simples, i.e., incomposite concrete material objects which may be included in the inventory of fundamental physics as possible simple substances (Koslicki, in progress). This is almost certainly incorrect. If these supposed items are indeed material, then they by definition are composed of matter, and there is no reason to believe that they do not in addition have forms also. For if they did not have forms, this seems to imply we are working with an oddly spatial conception of form. Form is easily thought of as providing unity, but why must this be a unity of parts to a whole? Why not of history? Or purpose? Or essence? So these so-called physical simples should not be considered simples to begin with. Next imagine an output of form-without-matter. Here we can think of a soul, or person, or perhaps God. And surely if any of these things exist, they are likely substance candidates. E.J Lowe, whom I will discuss further below, also submits the conception of an immaterial physical simple, instead of the apparently untenable material physical simple. Lowe argues that form construed as particular instances of substantial universals, like this tree or that statue of such-and-such a shape is relatively independent from matter, contrary to the doctrine of hylomorphism, and indeed 46

colin bradley there is nothing absurd in the notion of form without matter (Lowe 1998, 224). Lowe recommends that instead of saying a particular statue has an instance of the universal property of being a statue of such-and-such a shape, we say rather that it is an instance of the universal property of being a statue of such-and-such a shape. Though I confess it is not altogether clear to me why. When promising an explanation, he instead distinguishes between substantial and non-substantial universals. The former are denoted by sortal terms: things like statue and tiger. The latter are denoted by adjectival terms: things like red and round. He calls these latter items modes and says, these are ontologically dependent entities, depending for their existence upon the individual concrete things whose modes they are (Lowe 1998, 222). He claims that particular instances of substantial universals, on the other hand, just are the individual concrete things. Lowe takes this to have the result that he can square Aristotle s conception of substance from the Categories, as a discreet macroscopic thing, with his conception of substance from the Metaphysics, as a particular substantial form, since the two supposedly coincide. The feasibility of Lowe s approach rests on the claim that it is not absurd to have an item of sort form-without-matter. As an example he suggests the fundamental particles of physics. He claims that these particles are immaterial, insofar as they are not immediately made of anything at all (this relies on his notion of proximate matter). But, he continues, there is no reason why we cannot say that these particles do not have form. He has provided plausible arguments that it is form rather than matter that provides criteria both of identity and individuation for any items. But, as Lowe himself admits, it is very difficult to think of the fundamental particles as having fully determinate identity conditions, owing partly to quantum entanglement. So it is extremely unlikely that we should take these items to be substances at all (Lowe 1998, 224). Nonetheless, in spite of the failure of this (his only) example, he maintains that the idea of form-without-matter is perfectly coherent. However, it seems clear that he has either to concede (i) that these fundamental particles of physics are both immaterial and formless (which is absurd); or (ii) that they have form, but cannot be individuated, and therefore form does not always succeed in providing criteria of identity and individuation. Lowe grants that for any substance we should be able to identify its criteria of identity and individuation. But he has also argued that matter does not succeed in providing these cri- 47

hylomorphic substance and ontological independence teria, and in the case of the fundamental particles of physics, it appears that form similarly is unable to provide those criteria. Since form is supposed to be able to do that work, this should be a problem which Lowe s account needs to resolve if he intends to maintain his notion of form-without-matter as substance. Now we can ask two questions. First, what are we to make of the apparent asymmetry between a form-without-matter, and a matter-without-form, whereby the former is a likely substance candidate while the latter is not? This does seem to support the intuition shared by Koslicki and Lowe that form is doing most of the work in determining what is and is not a substance (and perhaps then also what is ontologically dependent and independent). This makes sense since we are using an essence-based account of ontological dependence, and essence and form are closely related notions. But what sorts of things belong to the type form-without-matter? Possible candidates include those mentioned above, namely Cartesian minds, souls, or God. I d prefer not to take on either defending or challenging whether or not we should think such things exist. Second, should we have any reason to think that an output of either sort matter-without-form (if these are even possible) or form-without-matter (i.e. simple substance) is categorically 4 different from an output of both form and matter (i.e. composite substance)? I see no reason to think so. We can think of all substance candidates as having the same structure, per the machine example above, just with sometimes this or that slot left open or filled. To be more precise: Presumably, someone like Toner would insist that a soul is a substance of the type form-without-matter. He would further insist that this is a simple substance, as opposed to a composite substance, say a horse, that has both form and matter. But by this account there is still a difference between a soul and a soul s form. Therefore I see no reason to suggest that this substance is actually simple. Perhaps the substance is thought to be numerically identical with what? Numerical identity is a dangerous concept if we do not know exactly what we are counting. For if we are counting in such a way that x, x s matter, and x s form are all distinct items, such that if x is found to depend ontologically on either x s matter or x s form then it is a composite and qualifies as a substance by way of a special clause, then surely the same way of counting must 4. By categorically different, I mean something like different in kind so as to require separate 48

colin bradley come up with the result that y and y s form are two distinct items such that if y depends ontologically on the latter, it too is composite. The method of counting should not be sensitive to the absence or presence of matter. This leaves four options open for the Koslicki-theorist. Either (i) abandon the idea of simple substances and adopt a single independence criterion for substances; (ii) allow that there might be simple substances, but decide that these would not be categorically different from composite substances so as to require a separate criterion, and again subsume these under a single generalized independence criterion for substances; or (iii) follow Lowe partly by identifying a substance of type formwithout-matter with its form, thereby preserving simple substances, and then (iii.a) decide that even these are not categorically different than composite substances; or (iii.b) insist that these simple substances do warrant their own independence criterion for substances, bite the bullet, and take on the critics of a bifurcated account of substance. Anyone opting for option (iii) must meet two challenges, in addition to those presented by a bifurcated account of substance alone. The first is one Lowe himself must meet, which is demonstrating the feasibility of substances of type form-without-matter which, aside from putative candidates like God and souls, I do not think can be done. The second challenge is to establish a principled way to ensure that only substances of type form-without-matter are identified with their form, and not all things whatsoever. For otherwise, the Koslicki-theorist would have to take on the considerable costs she attributes to Lowe s account, which I am going to discuss next. iii. lowe s particular instances of substantial universals So what are these costs? Koslicki attributes to Lowe an unpalatable extension of Cartesian dualism. It may, she suggests, be acceptable given independent motivation to conceive of a Cartesian mind which is identified with its form and therefore only temporarily resides in some hunk of matter or another. But Lowe s account has further consequences. Koslicki writes, For example, if H 2 0-molecules are unified whole (and thus are included within the range of cases to which the hylomorphic analysis of unified whole can be expected to apply), then Lowe s strategy 49

hylomorphic substance and ontological independence would lead us to identify H 2 0-molecules with their forms as well. But, assuming that forms are essentially non-material, H 2 0-molecules will then also (surprisingly, I take it) turn out to be essentially non-material entities which only reside in their material embodiments and possibly do so only temporarily (Koslicki, in progress). (Hence my warning in the previous paragraph that a Koslicki-theorist would need to limit the identification of substance with form.) I share her concerns entirely. However I also have two further concerns. One, as I have already hinted, has to do with Lowe s suggested immaterial physical simple. The other has to do with Lowe s difficulty in accounting for artifacts while remaining faithful to a conception of substance as ontologically independent. Lowe therefore rejects the notion of a hylormorphic compound, which might be a perfectly reasonable move, but does not represent a satisfactory resolution of the problem we set out to explore. Remember the goal is to reconcile ontologically independent substance with hylomorphic compounds, that is, to retain both notions. Koslicki and Lowe appear each to have simply rejected one notion or the other. In what follows, I will continue examining Lowe s account (despite its departure from our goal), in order to better understand which of the options outlined above for the Koslick-theorist we should ultimately adopt. Lowe s account runs into a further difficulty accommodating artifacts 5. On his account, all discreet macroscopic objects can be identified with particular instances of substantial universals. His examples are this statue and this tiger. It is unclear whether the term substantial universal is intended to imply that any particular instance should be classified as a substance; though, clearly, all substances must be particular instances of substantial universals. Hopefully particular instances of substantial universals are to be considered substance-candidates, but not necessarily substances. Here is why: Lowe asks us to consider mere parts or portions of material stuff, say a bunch of gold in a room (Lowe 1998, 226). We are to take this as matter-without-form; it cannot be counted since there is no principle to separate one part from another (though again, I am skeptical of this category). In 5. Of course, whether or not Aristotle considers artifacts substances is controversial. I take it to be more likely that he does not, since they have neither fysis, telos, nor energeia of their own. of its own. It is still a thing, but likely not a substance. But this is beside the point since Lowe obviously takes this statue as a legitimate substance-candidate. 50

colin bradley order to be counted, the gold would have to be given a form. This is easily done: we roll the gold into a lot of little gold balls. So we have given the gold balls their form. Presumably, then, they are essentially identity dependent on us. Then, by Lowe s SUB-4 definition (or Koslicki s appropriately revised ICCS4 definition) of substance, these particular instances of the substantial universal of being a gold ball of such-and-such a shape, are not substances, since they depend for their identity on something external, namely whoever provided their form by rolling them into balls. This, I take it, makes the significance of Lowe s distinction between substantial and non-substantial universals rather fuzzy, since to be a particular instance of a substantial form is not necessarily to be a substance. This further complicates the explanation he invoked in order to explain his identification of form with particular instance of substantial universals, and therefore to the notion that there are substances of type form-without-matter. iv. options for the koslicki-theorist I presented four options above for the Koslicki-theorist. Options (iii.a) and (iii.b) implicate one in the same problems I just laid out for Lowe s account none perhaps are fatal, but they are well worth bearing in mind. Also as I have already indicated since the Koslicki-theorist is opposed to the general identification of discreet macroscopic item with its form, but is comfortable in principle of allowing something like God or a Cartesian mind to be so identified such an account would have the added difficulty of establishing a principled way to ensure that only the right sorts of things get identified with their form. It may be worth mentioning the basic objection to a bifurcated account of substance. Basically, substance, taken as an ontologically independent item, is intended to be a fundamental category, one that carves nature at the joints as Ted Sider would put it. But it is extremely unlikely that nature is double-jointed in this way. That is, if the category of substance were really bifurcated in this way, it adds even greater force to Fine s (and Sider s) intuition that ontological independence cannot on its own reveal fundamental reality. The idea of substance in general is intended to capture something about the very fundamental structure of reality substance is supposed to be that which is most fundamental, or at the very least which does 51

hylomorphic substance and ontological independence not depend for its being what it is, on something else that is more fundamental. In this way it is supposed to capture the most basic sort of thing with which we could ever have occasion to interact in some meaningful way. Yet if we introduce a distinction within this fundamental category between the composite and the simple substances it seems very likely that our putatively fundamental category has rather failed to perform the function for which it was originally intended, and we are left gerrymandering an unmotivated concept. That leaves options (i) and (ii). Both, I think, are feasible. The main difference has to do with one s openness towards items of sort form-without-matter, like God or Cartesian minds. One who is more accepting of such things would clearly prefer the motivation behind option (ii), but ultimately, I think both call for the same move. The Koslicki-theorist should adopt a single criterion for substance, either under the assumption that there are no simple substances, or that these will be unproblematically subsumed under the general criterion. It might look something like this (adapted from Koslicki s ICS3 and ICCS4): 52 ( ) x is a substance def (i) there is no y such that (a) y is not identical with x, (b), x is essentially identity dependent on y, and (c) y is This criterion is of course far from satisfactory. As Koslicki herself notes, a much fuller explanation of clauses (i.c) and (ii) would need to be given. Clause (ii) is included to prohibit items like mereological sums and sets from qualifying as substance. It is worth pausing for a moment on sets. In Koslicki 2013, it is argued that all essence-based accounts of ontological dependence have the funny result that the empty set is considered a substance, while no other set is. It does appear that ICS faces the same problem, unless the empty set is construed to be essentially identity dependent on the axioms of set theory. These difficulties are perhaps why Koslicki opts for a different option, which focuses on unity and has no mention of identity dependence. I leave this option aside, since I want only to explore the relationship between substance and an account of ontological dependence. Despite its nascent status, as only a start down a promising path rather than a detailed map to our destination, ICS is certainly pointing towards allowing one to

colin bradley hold both that substance is ontologically independent, and that it is hylomorphic. We do not face Koslicki s original problem of a bifurcated notion of substance that no longer appears to represent a metaphysically fundamental category, since we have decided that any putative simple substances either do not actually exist, or, if they do, they are not categorically different from hylomorphic substances. Allowing such a bifurcated conception of substance is, after all, really just to eschew the problem with which we began reconciling ontologically independent substances with hylomorphic substance, where substance is intended to be a robust, fundamental metaphysical concept. Furthermore, unlike Lowe, we do not simply reject the notion of a hylomorphic compound for the sake of an apparently problematic identification of substance with substantial form, but still try to do justice to the idea of a unity of form and matter. works cited Fine, Kit. The Question of Realism. Philosopher s Imprint 1.2 ( June 2001): 1-30. --------- Ontological Dependence. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 95 (1995): 269-290. Koslicki, Kathrin. Ontological Dependence: An Opinionated Survey. In Varieties of Dependence, edited by Miguel Hoeltje, Benjamin Schnieder, and Alex Steinberg, 31-64. Munich: Philosophia, 2013. --------- Substance, Independence and Unity. In Aristotle on Method and Metaphysics, edited by Edward Feser, 169-96. Basingstoke: Palgrave/Macmillan, 2013. original reference: Koslicki, Kathrin (in progress). Substance, Independence and Unity <http://spot.colorado.edu/~koslicki/documents/substance,%20independence%20and%20unity%20december%202012.pdf>, draft as of December 2012. Lowe, E.J. Form Without Matter. Ratio 11 (1998): 214-234. ---------- Ontological Dependence. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2010 Edition), edited by Edward N. Zalta. <http://plato.stanford.edu/ archives/spr2010/entries/dependence-ontological>. 53

hylomorphic substance and ontological independence Rosen, Gideon. Metaphysical Dependence: Grounding and Relation. In Modality: Metaphysics, Logic, and Epistemology, edited by Bob Hale and Aviv Hoffmann, 109-36. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010. Schaffer, Jonathan. On What Grounds What. In Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology, edited by David Manley, David J. Chalmers, and Ryan Wasserman, 347-383. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009. Toner, Patrick. Independence Accounts of Substance and Substantial Parts. Philosophical Studies 155 (2011): 37-43. 54