Noonan, Harold (2010) The thinking animal problem and personal pronoun revisionism. Analysis, 70 (1). pp ISSN

Similar documents
IA Metaphysics & Mind S. Siriwardena (ss2032) 1 Personal Identity. Lecture 4 Animalism

Journal of Cognition and Neuroethics

THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY

APA PANEL TALK ON ORGANISMS, PERSONS AND BIOETHICS

A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports. Stephen Schiffer New York University

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon

ORGANISMS, PERSONS AND BIOETHICS II

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

This is the peer reviewed version of the following article: Árnadóttir, S. T. (2013), Bodily Thought and the Corpse Problem. European Journal of

Reflections on the Ontological Status

Personal identity and the radiation argument

Moderate Monism, Sortal Concepts and Relative Identity. comes in two varieties permanent and temporary. Moderate monism (about

Personal Identity. 1. The Problems of Personal Identity. First published Tue Aug 20, 2002; substantive revision Thu Jul 9, 2015

What We Are: Our Metaphysical Nature & Moral Implications

What Matters in Survival: The Fission Problem, Life Trajectories, and the Possibility of Virtual Immersion

Two Conceptions of Reasons for Action Ruth Chang

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

1. The narrow criterion Derek Parfit endorses a view of personal identity over time that he puts like this:

This is a repository copy of An Argument for Animalism. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper:

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true.

The Zombies Among Us. Eric T. Olson To appear in Nous.

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Philosophy 125 Day 13: Overview

THE POSSIBILITY OF AN ALL-KNOWING GOD

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 3e Free Will

Primitive Concepts. David J. Chalmers

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Stang (p. 34) deliberately treats non-actuality and nonexistence as equivalent.

PHIL 480: Seminar in the History of Philosophy Building Moral Character: Neo-Confucianism and Moral Psychology

Correct Beliefs as to What One Believes: A Note

ORGANISMS, BRAINS AND THEIR PARTS UB PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY CONFERENCE

DANCY ON ACTING FOR THE RIGHT REASON

Varieties of Apriority

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

a0rxh/ On Van Inwagen s Argument Against the Doctrine of Arbitrary Undetached Parts WESLEY H. BRONSON Princeton University

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 3d Free Will

Why Counterpart Theory and Three-Dimensionalism are Incompatible. Suppose that God creates ex nihilo a bronze statue of a

Reflections on sociology's unspoken weakness: Bringing epistemology back in

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

This is a repository copy of Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive intellect..

abstract: What is a temporal part? Most accounts explain it in terms of timeless

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988)

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

Class #13 - The Consciousness Theory of the Self Locke, The Prince and the Cobbler Reid, Of Mr. Locke's Account of Our Personal Identity

SENSE AND SUBJECTIVITY

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

FOUNDATIONALISM AND ARBITRARINESS

Kant Lecture 4 Review Synthetic a priori knowledge

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa

Nancey Murphy, Bodies and Souls, or Spirited Bodies? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006). Pp. x Hbk, Pbk.


Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Précis of Democracy and Moral Conflict

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

John Charvet - The Nature and Limits of Human Equality

Philosophical Review.

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

The unity of the normative

The Theory and Practice of Personal Identity

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives

Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial.

Moral Psychology

Eric Schliesser Philosophy and Moral Sciences, Ghent University ª 2011, Eric Schliesser

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

Review: The Objects of Thought, by Tim Crane. Guy Longworth University of Warwick

Personal Identity and Ethics

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

What does Functionalism Tell Us about Personal Identity?


Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

DO TROPES RESOLVE THE PROBLEM OF MENTAL CAUSATION?

Can Ordinary Materialists be Autonomous? Abstract

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Huemer s Clarkeanism

Robert Audi, The Architecture of Reason: The Structure and. Substance of Rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xvi, 286.

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries

Transcription:

Noonan, Harold (2010) The thinking animal problem and personal pronoun revisionism. Analysis, 70 (1). pp. 93-98. ISSN 0003-2638 Access from the University of Nottingham repository: http://eprints.nottingham.ac.uk/1914/2/the_thinking_animal_problem and_person_prono un_revisionism.pdf Copyright and reuse: The Nottingham eprints service makes this work by researchers of the University of Nottingham available open access under the following conditions. This article is made available under the University of Nottingham End User licence and may be reused according to the conditions of the licence. For more details see: http://eprints.nottingham.ac.uk/end_user_agreement.pdf A note on versions: The version presented here may differ from the published version or from the version of record. If you wish to cite this item you are advised to consult the publisher s version. Please see the repository url above for details on accessing the published version and note that access may require a subscription. For more information, please contact eprints@nottingham.ac.uk

The Thinking Animal Problem and Person Pronoun Revisionism HAROLD W. NOONAN In his book (2007) Eric Olson makes some criticisms of a response to the problem of the thinking animal (also called the two many minds or two many thinkers problem) which I have offered, on behalf of the neo-lockean psychological continuity theorist. Olson calls my proposal personal pronoun revisionism (though I am not suggesting any revision). In what follows I shall say what my proposal actually is, defend it and briefly respond to Olson s criticism. The problem of the thinking animal, briefly, is that it seems indisputable that human animals, i.e., human beings, or at least, all normal healthy adult human beings, are thinkers. But so, by definition are persons. However, according to the psychological continuity theorist of personal identity, persons are not human beings (they differ in their persistence conditions). So the psychological continuity theory entails the existence of too many thinkers. Moreover, it creates an irresoluble epistemic problem: how do I know I am the person sitting here typing this thinking truly that he is person and not the coincident human animal thinking falsely that he is a person? Finally, if human animals, in addition to persons, are thinkers, they must be persons after all, since their thoughts have whatever complexity and sophistication any ordinary definition of person could require they have just the same thoughts, after all, as the persons with whom on the psychological continuity account, they cohabit, so the neo-lockean s attempt to identify the persistence conditions for persons collapses into incoherence, since he has to acknowledge different kinds of person with different persistence conditions as it were person-persons and animal-persons. 1

My claims are: (a) that the most sensible thing for the psychological continuity theorist to do in response to the too many thinkers problem is (i) to distinguish the concepts of an object of first-person reference and a thinker of first-person thoughts and (ii) to say that when an animal coincident with but distinct from a person is a thinker of a first-person thought, not he, but the coincident person, is the object of the thought (b) that this is not a reductio of the psychological continuity theory. My argument is as follows: (1) Persons and only persons are objects of first-person reference I take this to be trivially analytic. If anything is a person it is capable of being an object of (its own) first-person reference and anything which is capable of being an object of firstperson reference is a person. (Sometimes, of course, we pretend that something which is not a person is an object of first-person reference. For example, I put a sign on my door saying I am unlocked, please come in and wait. Or the justifiably aggrieved (but rather bossy) Departmental Secretary puts a notice up in the lecturers coffee room, purporting to be from the Cleaning Angel, which reads I do not exist. Wash up and dry your cups yourselves. ) (2) All persons are psychological continuers This is a formulation of the standard neo-lockean view, I do not have to defend it here since I am only concerned to bring out its consequences. (3) Some normal healthy adult human animals are not psychological continuers 2

This is undisputed by neo-lockeans, since it is an acknowledged fact of observation that all normal healthy adult human beings have had foetal stages to which they are not psychologically connected and some will have late vegetative stages to which they are not psychologically connected. (4) All normal healthy adult human animals are thinkers of true first-person thoughts This is what the animalist urges, rightly, I think, on the neo-lockean as an evident common-sense truth. Some neo-lockeans, notably Shoemaker, deny it. From (1)-(4) follows: (5) Some normal healthy adult human animals have first-person thoughts which are not about themselves but about psychological continuers with which they are not identical By (1) their first-person thoughts must be about persons. So by (2) they must be about psychological continuers. But if the human animals in question are among those that are not psychological continuers, whose existence is certified by (3), they cannot be thinking about themselves, but, by (4), some of their first-person thoughts are true, so must have referents hence their referents must be psychological continuers distinct from themselves. (5), then, I claim, is what the neo-lockean, the defender of (2), must say on pain of denying a trivial analytic truth, (1), or a plain fact of observation, (3), or an evident common-sense truth, (4). 3

But is this not a reductio of neo-lockeanism? I do not think so. Olson makes much of the idea of what we mean by person (and the plural term people ) in the ordinary sense of the word. He writes: if something were psychologically indistinguishable from you would you refuse to call it a person until you were told whether it persists by virtue of psychological continuity? That seems no part of what we ordinarily mean by person. If human animals really are psychologically just like ourselves, they will count as people in any ordinary sense of the word. Human animals may fail to satisfy some specialized philosophical sense of person, owing to having the wrong persistence conditions or on some other trivial grounds. But they are surely people in the sense that informs our ordinary use of personal pronouns (2007: 16) It would not help me if I were to submit to Olson s insistence that being a (sophisticated) thinker suffices for being a person (even in the case of something which is not an object of first-person reference), since then I would simply face a too many persons problem as well as a too many thinkers problem. But this is all beside the point. The debate to which the neo-lockean intends to contribute is about two questions: What am I (fundamentally)? and What are my persistence conditions? The primary formulation of these questions is first-personal. The word person as it is used in this debate (and its synonym self ) is merely intended to allow a non-indexical formulation of these questions. So person in the philosophical debate simply means object of firstperson reference. (1) is trivially true. (And for what it is worth, I think, would be so regarded by the man in the street (though I doubt that he would so regard the formulation 4

using people in place of persons ). So although he would not wait to call something a person until he knew whether it was a psychological continuer, he would hesitate to call something a person if he believed it never referred to itself (at least in thought) in the first-person, ADD: AND WOULD NOT HESITATE TO CALL IT A PERSON IF HE BELIEVED IT WAS AN OBJECT OF FIRST-PERSON REFERENCE.) So the substantive point at issue is the neo-lockean claim (2), which is the claim that (as a matter of conceptual necessity) objects of first-person reference are psychological continuers. Following out the consequences of this (given empirical facts and common-sense truth) leads to the surprising conclusion that there are more thinkers than common-sense acknowledges and that some of these are not objects of their firstperson reference (and so are thinkers that are not persons if we interpret person one way, or are persons that are not objects of first-person reference if we interpret it another way). But it is hardly news that neo-lockeanism leads to this unless, like Shoemaker s version, it offends common-sense at a different point. Locke himself distinguished between thinking substances, which he thought were probably immaterial, and persons, and so had to acknowledge the existence of thinkers distinct from persons that were not objects of first-person reference that is, could not think of themselves as themselves in different times and places; he worried about their fate on the Great Day, when all hearts will be opened. Butler and Reid homed in on this duality of thinking substances and person in their critiques of Locke. And, of course, as Olson acknowledges, the fourdimensional version of the psychological continuity account endorses a multiplicity of thinkers that are not objects of first-person reference and requires what Olson calls personal pronoun revisionism. Anyway animalism has its own conflicts with common- 5

sense: in the restricted ontology it endorses, its denial of the transplant intuition, and its acceptance of the consequence that if your brainstem is replaced by an inorganic substance gradually, bit by bit (Olson 1999:141), without interruption of consciousness throughout, or your cerebrum removed for transplantation, the result is a new rational conscious being, which is not a human being, or else a series of thoughts and sensations that are not the thoughts of anyone (Olson 1999:141-2). 1 (It should be noted also that the too many thinkers problem also arises in the case of non-human animals. The transplant intuition is as strong in the case of dogs as it is in the case of human beings and it is as obvious that dogs think as that men do. So someone who endorses the transplant intuition in this case also faces the problem of too many thinkers. But what Olson calls the epistemic problem and the personhood problem do not arise since dogs are not selfconscious and we have no words related to canine animal as person and people are related to human animal. So the challenge in this case reduces to the insistence that those who endorse the transplant intuition must say that there are two thinkers where Fido is and that this is wrong.) But, it may be said, the thing that is wrong with my response to the problem of too many thinkers is that it creates a mystery. How can a normal healthy adult human being, capable of sophisticated first-person thought, not be capable of referring to himself in the first-person in such thought when the psychologically indistinguishable person is? 1 Animalists also need to say something about the reduplication problem. Bernard Williams first posed this problem as an objection to psychological continuity accounts of personal identity, in particular, ones that certified the intelligibility of reincarnation. But opponents were quick to ask why the objection, if good, did not apply equally to his own account of personal identity. Williams never gave a very convincing answer. Williams was an animalist or, at least, maintained a position that entailed animalism (though he never called himself an animalist, of course). His stated position was that persons were bodies (and he gave organisms as examples of bodies), and he certainly did not think that in addition to the bodies that were persons there were normal healthy adult human animals that were not persons (and were either not bodies or were bodies that were not persons). 6

How can the human animal lack this capacity which its psychologically indistinguishable twin possesses? But to ask this question is to misunderstand the proposal. The neo-lockean claim is that it can be established by conceptual analysis that the following is a de dicto necessary truth: Only psychological continuers are objects of first-person thought It follows that if A is a human animal, who is in fact not a psychological continuer, the following is a de dicto necessary truth: If A is not a psychological continuer A s first-person thoughts are not thoughts about A. It does not follow, even though A is not in fact a psychological continuer, that the following is a necessary truth: A s first-person thoughts are not thoughts about A. Nor does it follow that A is necessarily or essentially something whose first-person thoughts are not about itself no de re necessity follows. This is because it is no part of the neo-lockean story that A could not have been a psychological continuer. To say that A is not a psychological continuer is to say something about A s history, and A could have had a completely different history. 2 The sense in which it is established by the neo- Lockean account that A lacks the capacity to think I -thoughts about itself is just that, qua something which is not a psychological continuer, its I -thoughts cannot be about itself, just as qua someone who never marries, it can never be true of Miss Jones that she 2 Or not, if a Kripkean argument for the necessity of origin can be defended. In which case there is no possible world in which A is a psychological continuer and so A could never have referred to himself in the first-person way in thought.but now there is no mystery: this incapacity is explained by the neo-lockean argument for the de dicto necessity of (2), together with the Kripkean argument for the necessity of origin. 7

is a bride, or qua someone who never has been and never will be Prime Minister I cannot ever be correctly referred to by the Queen as my first Minister. Discomfort may remain. According to my version of the neo-lockean account it is not possible for something that is not a psychological continuer to be an object of its own first-person thoughts, no matter how sophisticated its thoughts are. 3 But why, it can be asked, should this be so? However, the explanation is simple: to be a psychological continuer is to have a certain kind of history: a certain kind of past, present and future. It is like being a past and future Prime Minister. But whether something is a thinker now and the level of sophistication of its present thoughts cannot depend upon its actual future, certainly not its actual future many years hence. 4 So no matter how sophisticated a creature s present thoughts they cannot ensure that it is a psychological continuer (or a future Prime Minister). Consequently, given the neo-lockean thesis (2), they cannot ensure that it is an object of its own first-person thoughts. The proper focus of scepticism about neo-lockeanism should be on the contention that philosophical analyis can identify any persistence conditions at all for any constraints at all on the past and future histories of objects of first-person reference as such. 5 Why, it can reasonably be asked, is the concept of an object of first-person 3 Actually, this is also trivially true on Shoemaker s account, since on that account it is not possible for something that is not a psychological continuer to think (first-person thoughts) at all. 4 This is the point on which I agree with the animalist and disagree with Shoemaker. Of course, actual normal healthy adult human animals differ from psychological continuers in their pasts as well as their futures (they have foetal stages). But if we imagine hypothetical beings that are otherwise identical but differ from psychological continuers only in their futures (e.g., because they come into existence fully formed), Shoemaker would still deny that they were thinkers, because of their differing futures. In fact, he would deny that human beings permanently coincident with persons were thinking things (just as he would deny that Goliath was Lump). I think the permanently coincident objects are identical and I do not think that merely future differences can determine whether something is now a thinker. Hence my agreement with the animalist. 5 The persistence conditions, or criterion of diachronic identity, for a kind of thing K can be given in the form If x is a K then for any times t and t, if x exists at t and t then Rxtt and there is no R not entailed by 8

reference in this respect not like the concept of something red or something weighing five pounds or a rolling, moving thing with size and weight? That is, why can quite different kinds of thing with quite different kinds of persistence condition not be objects of firstperson reference (see Noonan 1978: 351)? This is a very good question. The only answer, I think, is the transplant intuition, which has to be accommodated. University of Nottingham Nottingham, NG72RD, UK harold.noonan@nottingham.ac.uk References Noonan, H.W. 1978 Locke on Personal Identity. Philosophy 53:343-5. Olson, E. 1999 The Human Animal: Personal Identity without Psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Olson, E. 2007 What are We? A Study in Personal Ontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. R such that if x is a K then for any times t and t, if x exists at t and t then Rxtt. Notice that this requires no mention of identity. 9