-- did you get a message welcoming you to the cours reflector? If not, please correct what s needed.

Similar documents
Chapter 2 Normative Theories of Ethics

Moral Theory. What makes things right or wrong?

PROFESSIONAL ETHICS IN SCIENCE AND ENGINEERING

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

Mill s Utilitarian Theory

24.02 Moral Problems and the Good Life

Deontology: Duty-Based Ethics IMMANUEL KANT

Philosophical Ethics. The nature of ethical analysis. Discussion based on Johnson, Computer Ethics, Chapter 2.

A primer of major ethical theories

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

In-Class Kant Review Dialogue 1

Computer Ethics. Normative Ethics Ethical Theories. Viola Schiaffonati October 4 th 2018

Benjamin Visscher Hole IV Phil 100, Intro to Philosophy

Chapter 2 Ethical Concepts and Ethical Theories: Establishing and Justifying a Moral System

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries

Annotated List of Ethical Theories

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

Theme 1: Ethical Thought, AS. divine command as an objective metaphysical foundation for morality.

Quiz 1. Criticisms of consequentialism and Kant. Consequentialism and Nonconsequentialism. Consequentialism in practice. Must Choose Best Possible Act

PHIL%13:%Ethics;%Fall%2012% David%O.%Brink;%UCSD% Syllabus% Part%I:%Challenges%to%Moral%Theory 1.%Relativism%and%Tolerance.

Consequentialism. Mill s Theory of Utility

Moral Philosophy : Utilitarianism

Deontology. Immanuel Kant ( ) Founder of Deontology

Lecture 12 Deontology. Onora O Neill A Simplified Account of Kant s Ethics

Journalists have a tremendous responsibility. Almost every day, we make

Ethical Theories. A (Very) Brief Introduction

Suppose... Kant. The Good Will. Kant Three Propositions

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

Ethical Theory. Ethical Theory. Consequentialism in practice. How do we get the numbers? Must Choose Best Possible Act

Backward Looking Theories, Kant and Deontology

Altruism. A selfless concern for other people purely for their own sake. Altruism is usually contrasted with selfishness or egoism in ethics.

Modern Deontological Theory: Rawlsian Deontology

W.D. Ross ( )

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6

Lecture 2: What Ethics is Not. Jim Pryor Guidelines on Reading Philosophy Peter Singer What Ethics is Not

16RC1 Cahana. Medical professionalism: Where does it come from? A review of different moral theories. Alex Cahana. Introduction

Chapter 2 Determining Moral Behavior

Sidgwick on Practical Reason

Ethics (ETHC) JHU-CTY Course Syllabus

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

Ethics is subjective.

Philosophical Ethics. Distinctions and Categories

24.01: Classics of Western Philosophy

Autonomous Machines Are Ethical

Philosophy of Ethics Philosophy of Aesthetics. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Basics of Ethics CS 215 Denbigh Starkey

SAMPLE COURSE OUTLINE PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS GENERAL YEAR 11

Introduction to Ethics

Do you have a self? Who (what) are you? PHL 221, York College Revised, Spring 2014

Computer Ethics. Normative Ethics and Normative Argumentation. Viola Schiaffonati October 10 th 2017

Course Syllabus Ethics PHIL 330, Fall, 2009

Units. Year 1 Unit 1: Course Overview. 1:1 - Getting Started 1:2 - Introducing Philosophy SL 1:3 - Assessment and Tools

Psychological Egoism, Hedonism and Ethical Egoism

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics

SPS103 LAW AND ETHICS

The form of relativism that says that whether an agent s actions are right or wrong depends on the moral principles accepted in her own society.

EUROANESTHESIA 2007 Munich, Germany, 9-12 June 2007

BOOK REVIEW: CONTEMPORARY MORAL PROBLEMS

Q2) The test of an ethical argument lies in the fact that others need to be able to follow it and come to the same result.

Contents. How to Use This Book Preface Acknowledgments

Course Syllabus. Course Description: Objectives for this course include: PHILOSOPHY 333

Teleological: telos ( end, goal ) What is the telos of human action? What s wrong with living for pleasure? For power and public reputation?

Deontology: Duty-Based Ethics IMMANUEL KANT

Deontology (Duty Ethics) Ross Arnold, Fall 2015 Lakeside institute of Theology

Some Ethical Theories

Categorical Imperative by. Kant

CHAPTER 2 Test Bank MULTIPLE CHOICE

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

Time: 3hrs. Maximum marks: 75. Attempt five questions in all. All questions carry equal marks. The word limit to answer each question is 1000 words.

Critical Reasoning and Moral theory day 3

PHIL 202: IV:

Is euthanasia morally permissible? What is the relationship between patient autonomy,

(d) Exam Writing Options Candidates can satisfy the MPL Comp requirement in one of two ways.

Deontological Ethics

factors in Bentham's hedonic calculus.

Definitions: Values and Moral Values

Aims of Rawls s theory

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2011

The fact that some action, A, is part of a valuable and eligible pattern of action, P, is a reason to perform A. 1

A Framework for the Good

Wednesday, April 20, 16. Introduction to Philosophy

Kant, Deontology, & Respect for Persons

Quote. Analyzing Ethical Dilemmas. Chapter Two. Determining Moral Behavior. Integrity is doing the right thing--even if nobody is watching

Philosophical Ethics. Consequentialism Deontology (Virtue Ethics)

Hello again. Today we re gonna continue our discussions of Kant s ethics.

(naturalistic fallacy)

Introduction to Ethics

Kantian Deontology - Part Two

AS Philosophy and Ethics

Psychological Aspects of Social Issues

Course Coordinator Dr Melvin Chen Course Code. CY0002 Course Title. Ethics Pre-requisites. NIL No of AUs 3 Contact Hours

Introduction to Ethics Summer Session A

INTRODUCTORY HANDOUT PHILOSOPHY 13 FALL, 2004 INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY---ETHICS Professor: Richard Arneson. TAs: Eric Campbell and Adam Streed.

Introduction to Philosophy Professor: Mark Fagiano Intern: John McArdle

4 Liberty, Rationality, and Agency in Hobbes s Leviathan

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Download: Two clips from Star Trek. The needs of the many and The needs of the one found in Course Content Kant folder.

Lecture 23 Ethics Review

Transcription:

1

-- did you get a message welcoming you to the coursemail reflector? If not, please correct what s needed. 2

-- don t use secondary material from the web, as its quality is variable; cf. Wikipedia. Check first; cf. earlymoderntexts.com? 3

-- for future reference, as a study aid, I also put up a previous year s paper and exam assignments (along with samples of A work, plus the TA s comments) -- also, some recommended readings (for later) -- other pages contain information about me and my interests in philosophy, along with photos 4

5

-- focus is more intellectual; intended in the first instance to give philosophy students basic knowledge of the main figures and positions in the history of ethical theory 6

-- emphasis on the major figures in the subject, figures that philosophy majors ought to know about, rather than the most exciting figures (e.g. Plato, Nietszche), though these authors also have had an important influence. We have other courses focusing on at least some of these figures. 7

8

-- let s first locate moral theory ( N.B. moral and ethical used interchangeably) in terms of prior entries on the chart -- vs. practical ethics: -- practical (as in PHIL 140) focuses on particular cases, often cases currently in dispute; less abstract, more accessible for beginners to philosophy -- ethical theory emphasizes general principles meant to explain our intuitions on cases we tend to agree about, as well as yielding answers to some disputed cases -- at a higher level, philosophical ethics divides into meta- and normative ethics: -- normative ethics is ethics proper, answering what we normally think of as ethical questions, practical or theoretical, about what s right or wrong, good or bad, etc. -- metaethics takes normative ethics as its subject matter and asks other kinds of philosophical questions about it, e.g. whether and how we can have knowledge of it; we ll see a bit of this, especially in Hume, but as a separate subject it s primarily a product of twentieth-century philosophy (as in PHIL 640 and at least some versions of 440) -- philosophical ethics as a body of thought, rather than behavior patterns (so that Kant s ethics doesn t refer to his moral practices but rather a theory he came up with) -- ethical theory can be characterized as a branch of philosophical ethics aiming to systematize morality into an organized body of thought -- can sometimes be taken to include metaethics, though I m going to simplify a bit to construct a coherent chart; usual use of the term refers to the more abstract and systematic areas of normative ethics -- consists in philosophers attempts to account for our ordinary moral beliefs ( intuitions ) with general principles or other standards of behavior (e.g. an ideal of the morally good person) 9

-- building toward overall map of the area (detailed enough to locate Mill s view), showing where ethical theory is located, along with the classification of the particular authors we re reading, plus others I ll mention for contrast -- just meant by way of preview, with more terms mentioned than I d expect you to remember; the crucial terms will come up again later -- print out the ultimate map to refer to as we do further readings; finding it on the web as part of your first assignment should help you see if you can find your way around my web site 10

-- ethical theory has its own subdivisions, extending the chart lower -- virtue ethics: the approach of classical philosophers, recently revived -- focuses on questions of moral good, applicable to persons or their character and motives -- links ethics to psychology -- examples we re reading: Aristotle, Hume -- duty ethics: generally the more modern approach, despite Hume (and contemporary versions of virtue ethics) -- focuses on questions of right or wrong; applicable to acts or rules of conduct -- links ethics primarily to law -- examples we re reading = Mill, Kant, Rawls 11

12

-- deontological ethics based on Greek word for ought -- often contrasted with teleological ethics (based on the Greek word for end or aim ; but that term crisscrosses the virtue/duty distinction, applying to Aristotle as well as Mill); better term = consequentialism -- takes rules or principles as determining what acts are right; essentially a more general version of the sort of approach we find in the Ten Commandments and similar religious codes of rules -- different versions depend on the nature and number of the principles taken as basic: -- the categorical imperative: a single principle (though with several formulations) due to Kant; amounts to an unconditional ought from which more specific rules may be derived -- prima facie duties: a more pluralistic approach due to twentieth-century English philosopher W. D. Ross -- contractarianism/contractualism: basic principles of ethics (or sometimes just justice) as derived from group consent -- includes historical social contract theories, as in Hobbes, Locke, and Rousseau, plus a more modern approach that takes the contract as merely hypothetical, basing ethics (or for Rawls, political justice) on what people would consent to under certain conditions -- recently, the word contractualism has been used to distinguish those versions that claim inspiration from Kant (who was influenced by Rousseau) and begin with moral presuppositions rather than attempting to reduce them to nonmoral, following Hobbes 13

-- note that Mill misclassifies Epicurus as a fellow utilitarian -- teleological (but covers Aristotle too -- consequentialist ethics takes right action as explained in terms of good consequences -- also focuses on questions about what s right, but explains right action in terms of a more fundamental concept of nonmoral good = experiences or events that are good for people, etc. -- summed up most simply as the right maximizes the good, though there are more complex versions not involving maximizing = creating the most good -- in other words, the right act (of all alternatives that are possible for a given agent) is the one that produces the best consequences -- different variants, depending on whether the good consequences that matter to an act s rightness are said to be -- consequences that benefit the agent: egoism (Epicurus) -- everyone ought to promote his own good -- sometimes not thought to be an ethical theory (since it can t resolve conflicts among individual agents), but rather a competitor to ethics -- consequences that benefit anyone, without distinguishing persons: utilitarianism (Bentham and Mill) -- often thought of as benefiting everyone, or the majority, but that s not really implied by the classical (Bentham/Mill) version -- instead, focuses on the total good, a lump sum whose quantity matters independently of how it s distributed, i.e. who gets how much -- basic issue between deontological and consequentialist approaches = rules versus results: -- whether a rule may be broken (e.g., it s whether OK to tell a lie) in circumstances where it s necessary to improve the situation for all concerned -- cf. Kant s favorite example, making a lying promise to secure a loan that one won t be able to replay (presumably from someone who wouldn t really suffer if he lost the money) ) 14

15

-- what s called classical utilitarianism (essentially meaning the earliest version, i.e. Bentham, Mill, and others) understands the good in a particular way, as happiness in a sense that s explainable in terms of pleasure (meaning pleasure minus pain, or balance of pleasure over pain) -- hedonism comes from the Greek for pleasure, but in philosophy it doesn t mean living a life devoted to sensual indulgence, as it does in common speech; cf. Epicurus s egoistic view, on which the best way to maximize your own pleasure was to minimize your desires, to avoid the pain of unsatisfied desire -- pleasure said to be the only thing that s good intrinsically, or in itself, with other things considered good only instrumentally, insofar as they promote pleasure, again in the sense of pleasure minus pain; cf. example of taking a medicine to cure an illness, i.e. minimize pain -- Bentham s hedonism was meant to make the rightness of an act something one could calculate mathematically, at least in principle, by summing the pleasure/pain value of its consequences across all persons over time; but there are big problems about whether it s possible to compare different people s experiences, or the experiences deriving from different activities -- Mill instead, in ch. 2, defends qualitative distinctions among pleasures; i.e. he claims that pleasures differ, not just in quantity, but also according to whether the activities they re associated with are mental (intellectual or spiritual) or merely physical, the former ranked higher than the latter; there are questions about whether this still amounts to hedonism, strictly speaking -- contrasting view is pluralistic utlitarianism (also called agathistic, or ideal utilitarianism), espoused by twentieth-century philosopher G. E. Moore, who argued that some things were good independently of whether they resulted in pleasure, or any conscious experience -- e.g. beauty would be good in itself even if there were no one to behold it -- knowledge as good in itself, even where it makes you unhappy (e.g. knowledge that your spouse is cheating on you) -- personal relations: cf. spouse who dies, etc 16

-- further distinctions come up in interpreting Mill, e.g. between actual and expected (probabilistic) utilitarianism, act- and rule-, etc.; see Crisp s Intro (and the endnotes?) for a fairly complete account 17