Robert Formaini's illuminating work throws into question a

Similar documents
Israel Kirzner is a name familiar to all readers of the Review of

HAS DAVID HOWDEN VINDICATED RICHARD VON MISES S DEFINITION OF PROBABILITY?

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

ECONOMETRIC METHODOLOGY AND THE STATUS OF ECONOMICS. Cormac O Dea. Junior Sophister

METHODENSTREIT WHY CARL MENGER WAS, AND IS, RIGHT

Is Epistemic Probability Pascalian?

Lecture 9. A summary of scientific methods Realism and Anti-realism

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

Karl Popper. Science: Conjectures and Refutations (from Conjectures and Refutations, 1962)

Karl Popper & The Philosophy of Science. What Makes a Theory Scientific?

Prof. Bryan Caplan Econ 812

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Philosophy of Economics and Politics

Introduction Questions to Ask in Judging Whether A Really Causes B

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

THE ROLE OF COHERENCE OF EVIDENCE IN THE NON- DYNAMIC MODEL OF CONFIRMATION TOMOJI SHOGENJI

1/9. Leibniz on Descartes Principles

SAMPLE ESSAY 1: PHILOSOPHY & SOCIAL SCIENCE (1 ST YEAR)

A Scientific Realism-Based Probabilistic Approach to Popper's Problem of Confirmation

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

Falsification or Confirmation: From Logic to Psychology

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

1.5 Deductive and Inductive Arguments

A Brief History of Scientific Thoughts Lecture 5. Palash Sarkar

McDougal Littell High School Math Program. correlated to. Oregon Mathematics Grade-Level Standards

Why economics needs ethical theory

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

Lecture 1. The Science of Economics

Bayesian Probability

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

The poverty of mathematical and existential truth: examples from fisheries science C. J. Corkett

CHAPTER THREE Philosophical Argument

Sydenham College of Commerce & Economics. * Dr. Sunil S. Shete. * Associate Professor

Arguing with Libertarianism without Argument : Critical Rationalism and how it applies to Libertarianism

The Precautionary Principle and the ethical foundations of the radiation protection system

A Logical Approach to Metametaphysics

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

Module 1: Science as Culture Demarcation, Autonomy and Cognitive Authority of Science

Ilija Barukčić Causality. New Statistical Methods. ISBN X Discussion with the reader.

Well-Being, Disability, and the Mere-Difference Thesis. Jennifer Hawkins Duke University

AP SEMINAR: End- of- Course Exam SAMPLE RESPONSES SECTION I: PART A. The Uncertainty of Science, by Richard Feynman

Scientific Method and Research Ethics

Intersubstitutivity Principles and the Generalization Function of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh. Shawn Standefer University of Melbourne

David O Connor. Hume on Religion H. O. Mounce Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 2 (November, 2002)

MISSOURI S FRAMEWORK FOR CURRICULAR DEVELOPMENT IN MATH TOPIC I: PROBLEM SOLVING

Other Logics: What Nonclassical Reasoning Is All About Dr. Michael A. Covington Associate Director Artificial Intelligence Center

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

7AAN2004 Early Modern Philosophy report on summative essays

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

Christ-Centered Critical Thinking. Lesson 6: Evaluating Thinking

Know the Mysteries. Bible Study July 4, 2015 The Church of God, International (Philippines)

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to The Theory of Knowledge, by Robert Audi. New York: Routledge, 2011.

THE HYPOTHETICAL-DEDUCTIVE METHOD OR THE INFERENCE TO THE BEST EXPLANATION: THE CASE OF THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION BY NATURAL SELECTION

Detachment, Probability, and Maximum Likelihood

Chapter 2 Uncertainty in the History of Economic Thought

Revista Economică 66:3 (2014) THE USE OF INDUCTIVE, DEDUCTIVE OR ABDUCTIVE RESONING IN ECONOMICS

On the futility of criticizing the neoclassical maximization hypothesis

Commentaries on Gordon and on Bylund

Gilbert. Margaret. Scientists Are People Too: Comment on Andersen. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 6, no. 5 (2017):

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Friedrich von Hayek Walter Heller John Maynard Keynes Karl Marx

Actuaries Institute Podcast Transcript Ethics Beyond Human Behaviour

Why Good Science Is Not Value-Free

Key definitions Action Ad hominem argument Analytic A priori Axiom Bayes s theorem

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social

Editorial Self-Interest and Moral Contexts

Bayesian Probability

Georgia Quality Core Curriculum

Introduction to Inference

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

What Is Science? Mel Conway, Ph.D.

An Analysis of Freedom and Rational Egoism in Notes From Underground

Reid Against Skepticism

In his celebrated article Toward a Reconstruction of Utility and Welfare Economics,

Foundations of Economics: A Christian View

A Christian Philosophy of Education

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Are Miracles Identifiable?

WHAT IS HUME S FORK? Certainty does not exist in science.

ON THE POSSIBILITY OF ASSIGNING PROBABILITIES TO SINGULAR CASES, OR: PROBABILITY IS SUBJECTIVE TOO!

I thought I should expand this population approach somewhat: P t = P0e is the equation which describes population growth.

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory.

PHIL 155: The Scientific Method, Part 1: Naïve Inductivism. January 14, 2013

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

Søren Kierkegaard Philosophical Fragments, Concluding Scientific Postscript excerpts 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 10/10/13 12:03 PM

Courses providing assessment data PHL 202. Semester/Year

The Problem of the External World

MILL ON JUSTICE: CHAPTER 5 of UTILITARIANISM Lecture Notes Dick Arneson Philosophy 13 Fall, 2005

The Decline of the Traditional Church Choir: The Impact on the Church and Society. Dr Arthur Saunders

Religion and Science: The Emerging Relationship Part II

Seth Mayer. Comments on Christopher McCammon s Is Liberal Legitimacy Utopian?

Science, Rationality and the Human Mind. by Garry Jacobs

Against Against Intellectual Property: a Short Refutation of Meme Communism

Transcription:

The Myth of Scientific Public Policy. By Robert Formaini. New Brunswick, N.J.: Transaction Books, 1990. Robert Formaini's illuminating work throws into question a key doctrine of social planners not satisfied with the free market. A common argument for the market emphasizes consumer sovereignty: the goods and services produced in a free economy will be those demanded by consumers, since profit-making entrepreneurs have every incentive to produce what consumers wish. Those who will not or cannot do so find themselves rapidly replaced by those more alive to the market's signals. Against this, many supporters of government planning claim that the free market does not stand alone in its ability to give rise to desirable programs. Quite the contrary, scientific measures of analysis permit objective scientists to determine which programs best promote social welfare. Among the most important of the methods that are alleged to achieve these wondrous results, risk evaluation and cost-benefit analysis rank foremost. Formaini exposes the pretensions of these pseudo-scientific techniques with withering criticism. Risk evaluation can be used either by itself or as part of cost-benefit analysis. It attempts to answer questions such as: what are the chances there will be a meltdown at a nuclear plant? or, how likely is an epidemic of influenza? Unless problems of this sort can be solved, scientific analysis of public projects cannot succeed. If the designers of a nuclear plant do not know the likelihood of a meltdown, they will be unable to assess the costs of building the plant. Formaini raises a far-reaching difficulty for all such attempts: no consensus exists on the nature of probability. To some, probability is an objective matter. The chance, e.g., of The Review of Austrian Economics, Vol. 5, No. 1 (1991): 129-134 ISSN 0889-304 7 129

130 The Review of Austrian Economics, Vol. 5, No. 1 drawing a particular card out of a well-shuffied deck is 1 out of 52, no more and no less. The figure has not been arrived at by empirical testing: instead, it follows from the mathematical theory of chances, whose axioms are a priori. Formaini, unsympathetic to this approach, raises two problems for it. First, it depends upon the existence of complete information: in the example just given, one must know that there are 52 equally likely possibilities. In cases that risk evaluators commonly deal with, however, full information cannot be obtained; Second, any actual results are consistent with the theory. If a very improbable event occurs, the theory has not ruled it out. Since the rules of probability are "true by definition," the theory cannot be falsified. The first of Formaini's points is well put, but I am not quite sure that I grasp what he has in mind in the second objection. Why is it a difficulty in the theory that it cannot be falsified? Incidentally, it is not quite right to say that the theory is made true by definition. (How incidentally can something be made true by definition?-a famous question posed by Quine.) The theory is based on certain axioms, which, though knowable a priori, are not definitions: of course, Formaini is right that definitions are also needed. I may well have misunderstood Formaini's point: he might mean that the question of the theory's application to "real world" cases is not settled by the theory itself. If so, he is perfectly correct. 1 But these are mere quibbles. The view just discussed by no means stands alone in the field. The Bayesian.approach, toward which Formaini is more sympathetic, regards probability as dependent on subjective estimates. It does not operate from an a priori basis but instead looks to the facts of a particular case. If a Bayesian claims that the chance of getting heads on the toss of a coin is 1-in-2, he will base his assertion on the evidence of past tosses of that coin. His estimates are always subject to revision as further information comes to light. The dispute between the two views is not a theoretical issue with no practical relevance. As Formaini shows, the two variant approaches sometimes arrive at different estimates of probability for the same case. If so, the scientific pretensions of non-market decision makers already seem shaky. If no consensus exists on the way to estimate probability, how can it be claimed that there is a scientifically objective w~y of c:alculating benefits and costs? The main thrust of Formaini's argument strikes to the essence. Furthermore, the theories must confront additional objections be- 1 The passage that I have difficulty interpreting is on ~age 22.

Book Reviews 131 sides the ones our author has effectively urged against them. Ludwig von Mises contended that the calculus of probability, which he termed class probability, does not apply to individual events at all. To revert to our instance of the deck of cards, Mises would contend that one can properly speak only about the mathematical chances of classes of events. Nothing about an individual event, the drawing of a particular card, follows from class probability. Even if one does not accept Mises's characteristically radical and incisive proposal, another severe problem faces the theory. This point is especially prominent in the work of a writer of quite another stripe than Mises: John Maynard Keynes. In the Treatise on Probability, Keynes shows that the application of the theory to single events depends on a controversial and seemingly arbitrary assumption, the principle of insufficient reason. And what about the Bayesian approach? Here I think that more might have been made of the fact that Bayes's theorem requires that one assign a prior probability. The choice of this figure can radically affect one's results, but it can be picked only on an arbitrary basis. Formaini also proposes an improvement in the way probability estimates are applied. He suggests that the analyst modify his estimate by the degree of confidence he has in his calculation. "A simple formula can be added to probability calculations to allow for uncertainty attaching either to the data or the theory through which the data is [sic] manipulated" (p. 21). If one uses the Bayesian approach, has not uncertainty in the data already been considered in the calculation? So far as uncertainty about the theory one uses is concerned, Formaini's suggestion threatens to produce a regress. How is one to estimate one's certainty? How certain, again, is this calculation? Must we discount yet again for uncertainty? This problem was raised long ago by David Hume. Formaini goes on to suggest that if a good event is expected, one should discount the likelihood of the event's occurrence; if one predicts something bad, the likelihood should be increased. Once again, I fear that I have misunderstood. It is not apparent why certainty about one's calculation should vary directly with the badness of an event, and inversely with the goodness; and in any case one cannot be more certain thanp = 1, which will result in the original sum calculated, not an increase. But more likely Formaini intends the discount for the nature of the predicted event as another step in the calculation, not as a consequence of the certainty estimate. If so, he gives no justification for this additional step.

132 The Review of Austrian Economics, Vol. 5, No. 1 An objection that might be raised to Formaini is that his case is in a sense too good. If probability calculations lack a firm basis, why does this count against non-market methods of decisions alone? Is it not necessary for entrepreneurs in the market to calculate risk? Will not precisely the same problems of estimation confront private deci-. sion makers? Although the book does not directly address this problem, Formaini has the resources adequately to deal with it. The response in fact emerges in the third chapter. Before this, however, Formaini briefly sets forward the method of the Austrian School. His second chapter accomplishes a great deal, covering in a succinct and accurate way the foundation of the Austrian School; its conflict with the German Historical School; the Austrian deductive method; the use of verstehen; and the development of Austrian economics in the twentieth century. (lncidentially, it was not the German Historical School, as Formaini thinks, who proclaimed themselves "intellectual bodyguards of the House of Hohenzollern." Though its members would have enthusiastically assented, the statement comes from Emil DuBois-Reymond. Also, Hayek did not leave Austria owing to the Nazis (p. 27); he was named to a chair at the London School of Economics in 1931. In addition, Karl Popper does not think that the inductive methods of science can falsify a theory, nor does he claim that a well-corroborated theory is true [p. 33]. His best-known doctrine is the utter rejection of induction.) The book's third chapter, "A Subjectivist Evaluation of Cost Benefit Analysis," is the best in the book. In painstaking detail, Formaini shows the numerous problems that confront cost-benefit analysis in the vain efforts of its proponents to elevate it to the rank of objective science. For one thing, a social discount rate must be estimated. This rate determines how much future benefits are to be lowered when conducting a cost-benefit analysis. If, e.g., someone proposes that a subway be constructed that will be able to carry passengers for 50 years, one cannot simply add together the benefits from travel 50 years' worth of passengers will receive. Future benefits are not worth as much as present gains: but how much less? As Formaini shows, there is no good way of telling. Further, cost-benefit analysis usually rests on the assumption that perfect competition is a welfare ideal. In the Austrian view, this assumption is without basis. Why is a particular market structure more desirable than whatever is actually to be found on the free market? To this the neoclassicals have a ready answer. They claim that monopoly results in a welfare loss; further, any deviation from perfect competition imposes at least a degree of monopoly.

Book Reviews 133 Formaini's response is forthright. The "welfare loss" in question depends on hypothetical preferences that are ascribed to people. The Austrians refuse to adopt this conception of preference, which they regard as arbitrary. The only acceptable conception of preference, as Austrians see matters, is demonstrated preference. If an actor does something, one can say that at the moment he preferred the choice he made to any alternative available to him. On this view of preference, the claim that a welfare loss is caused by monopoly cannot get off the ground. Neither can alleged benefits from public goods expenditures be demonstrated. Of course, paying taxes that are used for public projects does not demonstrate a preference for these projects, since these subventions are exacted by coercion. The powerful tool of demonstrated preference enables the Austrian approach to respond to the objection I raised earlier. There is no special free market way of calculating probability, and the establishment of a free economy does not resolve the difficulties of probability discussed earlier. But we can say that if people on the market engage in a project, they have demonstrated a willingness to assume whatever risks are involved in that project. The problems inherent in cost-benefit analysis are many and various. The welfare criteria that cost-benefit analysis analysts use are either ineffective or questionable. The Pareto criterion, according to which a project can be undertaken if at least one person is made better off and no one worse off, rules out almost all state activity. Thus resort is frequently made to the Kaldor-Hicks principle, which allows changes if the gainers from a project are able to compensate the losers. The criterion does not mandate actual compensation: it thus sacrifices the welfare of the losers to the winners. Formaini notes that sometimes planners attempt to add up total benefits and total costs: a project will go forward if benefits exceed costs to a greater extent than for any alternative. This procedure Is not a "watered-down" version of Kaldor-Hicks, as the author claims (p. 55), since application of the latter criterion need not maximize welfare. In a final chapter, Formaini gives a detailed account of the swine-flu vaccination program, a major debacle of 1976. The constant errors of the bureaucrats responsible for this program cast a grim light of humor over the pretensions of cost-benefit analysis to be scientific. The government medical establishment conjured up a swine-flu epidemic out of a handful of flu cases. Their prevention measures for the non-existent epidemic cost hundreds of people their lives. In a brief postscript, the author sums up the lessons of his outstanding study. Ethics provides a much more solid basis for decision

134 The Review of Austrian Economics, Vol. 5, No. 1 on whether public projects should be built than the supposed objective discipline of cost-benefit analysis. I wish that Formaini had explained in detail his reasons for thinking that Brown v. Board of Education was decided in a morally correct way (p. 95). Common sense is a better guide than dubious expert assessments. I have sometimes, I fear, been unjust to Formaini in the preceding remarks. For reasons of temperament, I tend to emphasize points of disagreement. But my overall reaction to this excellent book is one of wholehearted assent. David Gordon The Ludwig von Mises Institute