Handout 2 Argument Terminology

Similar documents
ELEMENTS OF LOGIC. 1.1 What is Logic? Arguments and Propositions

Argument Mapping. Table of Contents. By James Wallace Gray 2/13/2012

PLEASE DO NOT WRITE ON THIS QUIZ

PHI Introduction Lecture 4. An Overview of the Two Branches of Logic

Pastor-teacher Don Hargrove Faith Bible Church September 8, 2011

What is a logical argument? What is deductive reasoning? Fundamentals of Academic Writing

Argumentation Module: Philosophy Lesson 7 What do we mean by argument? (Two meanings for the word.) A quarrel or a dispute, expressing a difference

Directions: For Problems 1-10, determine whether the given statement is either True (A) or False (B).

A Primer on Logic Part 1: Preliminaries and Vocabulary. Jason Zarri. 1. An Easy $10.00? a 3 c 2. (i) (ii) (iii) (iv)

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

PHI 244. Environmental Ethics. Introduction. Argument Worksheet. Argument Worksheet. Welcome to PHI 244, Environmental Ethics. About Stephen.

Example Arguments ID1050 Quantitative & Qualitative Reasoning

Introduction to Philosophy

ARGUMENTS. Arguments. arguments

Introduction to Analyzing and Evaluating Arguments

The Appeal to Reason. Introductory Logic pt. 1

Chapter 1 - Basic Training

What. A New Way of Thinking...modern consciousness.

Worksheet Exercise 1.1. Logic Questions

PHILOSOPHY ESSAY ADVICE

Genuine dichotomies expressed using either/or statements are always true:

The Relationship between the Truth Value of Premises and the Truth Value of Conclusions in Deductive Arguments

Chapter 1. Introduction. 1.1 Deductive and Plausible Reasoning Strong Syllogism

Philosophical Arguments

Introducing Our New Faculty

Skim the Article to Find its Conclusion and Get a Sense of its Structure

Portfolio Project. Phil 251A Logic Fall Due: Friday, December 7

Introduction to Philosophy

A Brief Introduction to Key Terms

A. Problem set #3 it has been posted and is due Tuesday, 15 November

Logic Book Part 1! by Skylar Ruloff!

What is an argument? PHIL 110. Is this an argument? Is this an argument? What about this? And what about this?

Academic argument does not mean conflict or competition; an argument is a set of reasons which support, or lead to, a conclusion.

Intro Viewed from a certain angle, philosophy is about what, if anything, we ought to believe.

HOW TO ANALYZE AN ARGUMENT

Lecture 1: Validity & Soundness

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

Deduction. Of all the modes of reasoning, deductive arguments have the strongest relationship between the premises

Geometry TEST Review Chapter 2 - Logic

1. To arrive at the truth we have to reason correctly. 2. Logic is the study of correct reasoning. B. DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE ARGUMENTS

Test Item File. Full file at

Moore on External Relations

Weaknesses in arguments

WHY SHOULD ANYONE BELIEVE ANYTHING AT ALL?

Russell on Descriptions

Philosophical Methods Revised: August, 2018

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Phil. 103: Introduction to Logic The Structure of Arguments

Mr Vibrating: Yes I did. Man: You didn t Mr Vibrating: I did! Man: You didn t! Mr Vibrating: I m telling you I did! Man: You did not!!

Arguments. 1. using good premises (ones you have good reason to believe are both true and relevant to the issue at hand),

INDUCTION. All inductive reasoning is based on an assumption called the UNIFORMITY OF NATURE.

Tutorial A02: Validity and Soundness By: Jonathan Chan

Logical (formal) fallacies

! Introduction to the Class! Some Introductory Concepts. Today s Lecture 1/19/10

A R G U M E N T S I N A C T I O N

3. Good arguments 3.1 A historical example

Answers to Practice Problems 6.5

CRITICAL THINKING (CT) MODEL PART 1 GENERAL CONCEPTS

Logic for Computer Science - Week 1 Introduction to Informal Logic

LOGIC Lesson 10: Univocal, Equivocal, Analogical Terms. 1. A term in logic is the subject or the predicate of a proposition (a declarative sentence).

2. Refutations can be stronger or weaker.

A Judgmental Formulation of Modal Logic

C. Exam #1 comments on difficult spots; if you have questions about this, please let me know. D. Discussion of extra credit opportunities

Lecture 4.2 Aquinas Phil Religion TOPIC: Aquinas Cosmological Arguments for the existence of God. Critiques of Aquinas arguments.

Hume. Hume the Empiricist. Judgments about the World. Impressions as Content of the Mind. The Problem of Induction & Knowledge of the External World

Introduction Symbolic Logic

Critical Thinking 5.7 Validity in inductive, conductive, and abductive arguments

PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS

Proofs of Non-existence

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

Lecture 3 Arguments Jim Pryor What is an Argument? Jim Pryor Vocabulary Describing Arguments

Lecture 2.1 INTRO TO LOGIC/ ARGUMENTS. Recognize an argument when you see one (in media, articles, people s claims).

IDHEF Chapter 2 Why Should Anyone Believe Anything At All?

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

Relevance. Premises are relevant to the conclusion when the truth of the premises provide some evidence that the conclusion is true

Is Epistemic Probability Pascalian?

2016 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

As noted, a deductive argument is intended to provide logically conclusive support for its conclusion. We have certainty with deductive arguments in

Basic Concepts and Skills!

A Solution to the Gettier Problem Keota Fields. the three traditional conditions for knowledge, have been discussed extensively in the

Conditionals II: no truth conditions?

Logic Appendix: More detailed instruction in deductive logic

Russell s Problems of Philosophy

Lecture 4: Deductive Validity

Do we have knowledge of the external world?

THE LARGER LOGICAL PICTURE

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

What we want to know is: why might one adopt this fatalistic attitude in response to reflection on the existence of truths about the future?

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo

1. True or False: The terms argument and disagreement mean the same thing. 2. True or False: No arguments have more than two premises.

SHORT ANSWER. Write the word or phrase that best completes each statement or answers the question.

1.5 Deductive and Inductive Arguments

PHILOSOPHY 102 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC PRACTICE EXAM 1. W# Section (10 or 11) 4. T F The statements that compose a disjunction are called conjuncts.

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS

Validity & Soundness LECTURE 3! Critical Thinking. Summary: In this week s lectures, we will learn! (1) What it is for an argument to be valid.

24.01: Classics of Western Philosophy. Hume on Causation. I. Recap of Hume on impressions/ideas

CHAPTER THREE Philosophical Argument

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

Transcription:

Handout 2 Argument Terminology 1. Arguing, Arguments, & Statements Open Question: What happens when two people are in an argument? An argument is an abstraction from what goes on when people arguing. An argument is a set of propositions arranged in such a way that one proposition (the conclusion) is supposed to follow from another set of propositions (the premises). Premise (Proposition) Premise (Proposition) Conclusion (Proposition) Arguments are differentiated from other kinds of linguistic behavior e.g. prayers, yelling at people, asking questions, reading a book aloud by the fact the premises of an argument purportedly support the conclusion. Philosophers of language and logic disagree about the definition of a proposition, but we will define it a proposition as the content expressed by a sentence that is capable of being true or false. Sentence Proposition: While all propositions are expressed by sentences, not all sentences express propositions, e.g. commands, questions, exclamations do not express propositions. Many Sentences Can Express One Proposition: A single proposition can be expressed in a variety of different ways o Example 1: John loves Liz vs. Liz is loved by John. o Example 2: A single proposition expressed in two different languages One Sentence Can Express Many Propositions: A single sentence does not always express the same proposition, e.g. I ate breakfast Being T or F vs. Knowing T of F: While a proposition must express content that is true or false (or can be true or false), it is not necessary that you know the truth value of a sentence (or know how to confirm the truth value) in order for the sentence to be a proposition, e.g. there are 50,304 trees in State College. 2. Premises, Conclusions, and Identifying Arguments An argument has two parts: the premises and the conclusion. The conclusion of an argument is the proposition that is said / claimed / represented as to follow from (or be supported by) a set of 1

propositions, while the premises of an argument are the propositions (or reasons) that are said to support (or entail) the conclusion. One key critical-thinking capacity is the ability to identify arguments from non-arguments. In some cases, it is easy to identify what is and is not an argument and easy to identify the premises/conclusion of an argument, but sometimes it is not so easy. Here are some tips to keep in mind: Tip #1: Arguments tend to have arguments indicators like therefore, since, due to the fact that, it follows that, consequently which indicate the presence of an argument. Often, these argument indicators mark the conclusion or premises. EXAMPLE: If the stock market crashes, I will be broke. Yesterday, I received an insider s tip that the stock market will crash. Therefore, I will be broke. Tip #2: While arguments do not have a single order of presentation, a standard way of presenting arguments is as follows: STANDARD ORGANIZATION FOR ARGUMENTS First Second Third (1) Premises/Assumptions Argument Indicator Conclusion This sometimes shows up in how people present their arguments (but not always). EXAMPLE: John told me that David is a bad teacher. Frank also told me that David is a bad teacher. John and Frank are never wrong about who is a good or bad teacher because they have failing grades. Therefore, David must be a bad teacher. Tip #3: It is helpful to think about what is not an argument. This will help you to identify what is an argument. Grocery lists, lists in general, narratives, a description of a sequence of events, a series of questions, and many other uses of language are not arguments. EXAMPLE: Yesterday, I saw a little bunny. He was so white and fuzzy and cute. I tried to walk up to him and pet him, but he cowered in fear. Yes, I had just eaten a delicious piece of rabbit meat not too long ago, but how would that little bunny know that? 3. Two Kinds of Arguments There are two different ways to characterize how the premises of an argument relate to the conclusion. An argument can be said to (i) simply explicate or draw out the information contained in the premises, and (ii) go beyond the information contained in the premises by making the conclusion more probable. 2

The two different ways that the premises of the argument relate to a conclusion correspond to two different types of arguments. A deductive argument is one that is intended by the arguer to draw out the information contained in the premises, i.e. it draws out the premises implications or what is entailed by the premises. An inductive argument is one that is intended by the arguer to make the conclusion more probable. Example #1: All criminals are evil. John is a criminal. Therefore, John is evil. Example #2: Sally told me that John once kicked a puppy. John is a criminal. Therefore, John is evil. Notice that both arguments have the same conclusion but (1) is deductive as it appears that the conclusion is simply drawn from the information contained in the premises, while (2) is inductive as it appears that the premises are used to render the conclusion probable. The distinction between deductive and inductive argument is problematic since it relies upon the arguer s intent. Sometimes, it is hard to determine whether an individual is putting forward a bad deductive argument or an inductive argument. Because this distinction is so problematic, we will focus on another way of classifying how the premises relate to the conclusion. 3.2. Deductively Arguments: Valid or Invalid Arguments are deductively valid or deductively invalid. An argument is deductively valid if and only if it is impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false. In other words, assuming the premises of an argument are true, the conclusion must be true. An argument is deductively invalid if and only if it is possible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false. Two important points: (1) You are not considering whether the premises are in fact true. (2) You are considering a certain relation between the premises and the conclusion, namely you are considering whether it is impossible for all of the premises to be true and the conclusion to be false. If it is impossible for all of the premises to be true and the conclusion false, then the argument is valid. There are several ways to test whether an argument is valid or invalid (some better than others). We will consider a test called The Imagination Test for Validity. Step #1: Start by assuming that all of the premises are true. If you cannot, then the argument is valid because it will be impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false. If you can, then move to Step #2. 3

Step #2: Given this assumption in Step #1, consider whether you can (while imaging the premises to be true) also imagine the conclusion as false. If this is not possible, then the argument is valid because it will be impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false. If you can imagine this, then the argument is invalid because it is possible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false. THE IMAGINATION TEST FOR VALIDITY / INVALIDITY Yes, then invalid If yes, then (step #2): is it possible given that all of the premises are true for the conclusion to be false Step #1: Is it possible for all of the premises to be true No, then valid If no, then valid Let s look at some examples. Example 1 Either John is president of the U.S.A. or Liz is the president. Liz is not the president. Therefore, John is the president. 2 Barack Obama is the president of the U.S.A. Barack Obama supports Obamacare. Therefore, Obamacare was declared constitutional. Analysis Both of the premises of the argument are false (and the conclusion is false) but the argument is deductive valid. Why? Both of the premises of the argument are true (and the conclusion is true) but the argument is deductively invalid. Why? Why should you care about deductive validity? Well, the nice thing about a deductively valid argument is that they are truth preserving: provided the premises are true, the conclusion will be true as well. That is, if an argument is deductively valid, then you won t (no, can t!) go from true premises to a false conclusion. This is great in any area where you think you have true premises, e.g. physics, math, your personal opinions about x, y, or z. Deductively Valid Argument using Newton s First Law of Motion 1. T = Newton s First Law of Motion (an object travels at a constant velocity unless it is otherwise acted upon by an external force) 2. ic 1 = there exists an object planet u that is in motion and not being acted upon by an external force. 3. p = planet u should remain in motion. P1. For every object n, if n is in motion and there is no external force, then n will remain in motion. P2. u is an object n that is in motion and is not being acted upon by an external force. C. Therefore, u should remain in motion. 4

3.3. Deductive Arguments: Sound or Unsound But, whether the premises of an argument are true, however, is a different question. An argument is sound if and only if the argument is both deductively valid and all of its premises are true. An argument is unsound if and only if the argument is either deductively invalid or deductively valid yet has at least one false premise. Soundness Deductively Valid + All True Premises 3.4. Inductive Arguments: Strong or Weak Earlier, we noted that an inductive argument is an argument that is intended by the arguer merely to render the conclusion probable. This characterization of an argument is problematic because it relies upon the arguer s intent. However, there is another way of thinking about arguments distinct from the validity/invalidity and sound/unsound distinctions. An argument is inductively strong if and only if the premises provide significant support for the conclusion. That is, if the premises were true, then it is very likely that the conclusion is true. Another way of putting this is that the truth of the premises makes the conclusion very probable. An argument is weak if and only if the premises provide little (or no support) for the conclusion. That is, the truth of the premises does not make it very likely that the conclusion is true. Another way of putting this is that the truth of the premises does not make the conclusion very probable. To test whether an argument is strong or weak, start by assuming that the premises are true (if it is possible to do so), then, given this assumption, consider whether the conclusion is very likely. If it is, then the argument is strong. If not, then the argument is weak. Weak Inductive Argument 1. There is a bag on the table filled with 50 beans. 2. I randomly drew 5 beans from a bag and they were black. 3. Therefore, all of the beans in the bag are black. Strong Inductive Argument 1. There is a bag on the table filled with 50 beans. 2. I randomly drew 40 beans from the bag and they were all black. 3. Therefore, all of the beans in the bag are black. Whereas an argument is either valid or invalid (all or nothing), the strength of an argument admits of degrees. That is, if the premise were I randomly drew 49 beans from the bag and they were all black, then we would have a stronger argument than either of those one above. In 5

contrast, if the premise were I randomly drew 2 beans from the bag and they were all black, we would have a weaker argument than either of those above. Calling an argument strong or weak concerns the relation between the premises and the conclusion and is unrelated to whether the premises or the conclusion are in fact true. An argument can be extremely strong but have false premises and a false conclusion. Strong Inductive Argument 1. There is a bag on the table filled with 50 beans. False, there are actually 100 2. I randomly drew 40 beans from the bag and False, a couple of these were blue. they were all black. 3. Therefore, all of the beans in the bag are black. False, some beans were orange. In short, saying that an argument is strong just means that if the premises were true, then the conclusion would be very likely, it does not mean that the premises are actually true. 3.5. Inductive Arguments: Cogent or Uncogent Inductive arguments are cogent or uncogent. An inductive argument is cogent if and only if the argument is strong and its premises are true. An inductive argument is uncogent provided the argument is either weak or strong but its premises are not true. Cogent Strong Inductive Argument + All True Premises Argument Deductive Inductive Valid Invalid Strong Weak Sound Unsound Cogent Uncogent A. Identify Propositions: For the following sentences, state which express propositions and which do not express not propositions. 1. Let the dog out. 2. In a fixed rate par bond, the issuer issues the bond at par value. 3. Brandon has Finance 301 at 11:15PM on Thursdays. 4. Recycling bins are blue. 5. Let s Go Pens! 6. Mike goes to the University of Miami. 7. Billboards are a great way to advertise for your company. 8. Can you pass me the pepper? 9. Finance is awesome. 10. Isaac Newton discovered gravity when he dropped a piano on his brother s head. B. Identify Arguments: For the following sets of sentences, state which express arguments and which do not express not arguments. 1. If Jimmy goes to school, he will get a good grade. His mom would be really happy if Jimmy gets a good grade. Therefore, Jimmy should go to school. 6

2. I really like elephants. They have super big ears and a really long nose. What a cool animal! 3. Going to the doctor is hard enough but the cost of health care is making it even harder. People got by before all these medical advances. I wish health insurance was more affordable. 4. You should read the review of the new restaurant that was in the paper this morning. It had great information on the types of food available. From the way it sounds, it could be a pretty neat place. It also describes the environment pretty well. Definitely check out the paper when you get a chance. 5. If T is the case, where T = Newton s Law of Universal Gravitation and Newton s Three Laws of Motions. AND IF all of the following are the case: ic 1 = there exists a planet u, and ic 2 = planet u is at position p 1, and ic 3 = there exists only n number of bodies that are close enough and massive enough to exert non-negligible gravitational force on u; these are x, y, and z, and ic 4 = Body x is at position p 1, at time t 1, and has a mass of m 1, THE planet u should be at position p 7 at time t 7.BUT, p = Planet u and it was not at position p 7 at time t 7.Therefore, it is not the case that T. C. Identify Deductively Valid or Invalid Arguments: For the following arguments, state which are deductively valid and which are deductively invalid. 1. All men are mortal. Socrates is a man. Therefore, Socrates is mortal. 2. All unicorns are pink. Frankie is a unicorn. Therefore, Frankie is pink. 3. Someone loves Liz. Liz loves someone. Therefore, everyone loves Liz. 4. Liz gave Jon five dollars yesterday. Jon is a good guy. Therefore, Jon will return Liz s five dollars tomorrow. 5. Some bicyclists smoke. Some bicyclists give to charity. Therefore, there are some bicyclists that both smoke and give to charity. D. Identify Inductively Strong or Weak Arguments: For the following arguments, state which are inductively strong and which are inductively weak. 1. I once was robbed by a white male in his 40s. Therefore, everyone who is a white male in his 40s is a robber. 2. The earth rotated around the sun yesterday. Therefore, the earth will rotate around the sun for the next week. 3. The earth rotated around the sun yesterday, the day before that, and for the last couple million years. Therefore, the earth will rotate around the sun for the next week. 4. Men should always ask women to school dances and not the other way around. It has always been a tradition for the men to ask the women and it is the gentlemanly thing to do. More and more men are moving away from this grand and glorious tradition. This is not good. Guys should also keep in mind that girls are not going to readily ask them to dances. 5. My doctor told me, upon inspection, that I have a skin disease. But I didn t believe him and so I asked for them to test to make sure. The lab results confirmed this. But, I m still skeptical. So, I got a second and third opinion. The second and third doctors (and lab tests) told me I had the same skin disease. But, Uncle Jon told me not to believe them and Uncle Jon once won the lottery (he is a lucky guy). Therefore, I do not have the skin condition that the doctors claim that I have. E. Key Terms: In your own words, define each term and give an example that represents its meaning. 1. Proposition 2. Argument 3. Deductive Argument 4. Inductive Argument 5. Deductively Valid Argument 6. Deductively Invalid Argument 7. Sound Argument 8. Unsound Argument 9. Inductively Strong Argument 10. Inductively Weak Argument 11. Cogent Argument 12. Uncogent Argument 7