Epistemic Utility and Theory-Choice in Science: Comments on Hempel

Similar documents
Philosophy Of Science On The Moral Neutrality Of Scientific Acceptance

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

MARK KAPLAN AND LAWRENCE SKLAR. Received 2 February, 1976) Surely an aim of science is the discovery of the truth. Truth may not be the

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

Class 6 - Scientific Method

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

On The Logical Status of Dialectic (*) -Historical Development of the Argument in Japan- Shigeo Nagai Naoki Takato

Gary Ebbs, Carnap, Quine, and Putnam on Methods of Inquiry, Cambridge. University Press, 2017, 278pp., $99.99 (hbk), ISBN

Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of

what makes reasons sufficient?

Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence

Logic: inductive. Draft: April 29, Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of premises P1,

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

1/8. Introduction to Kant: The Project of Critique

Skepticism and Internalism

Christ-Centered Critical Thinking. Lesson 6: Evaluating Thinking

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

A DILEMMA FOR JAMES S JUSTIFICATION OF FAITH SCOTT F. AIKIN

2014 THE BIBLIOGRAPHIA ISSN: Online First: 21 October 2014

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Who Has the Burden of Proof? Must the Christian Provide Adequate Reasons for Christian Beliefs?

Lost in Transmission: Testimonial Justification and Practical Reason

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Pihlström, Sami Johannes.

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View


Detachment, Probability, and Maximum Likelihood

Why Good Science Is Not Value-Free

From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge Gracia's proposal

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

A Warning about So-Called Rationalists

Varieties of Apriority

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

Jeffrey, Richard, Subjective Probability: The Real Thing, Cambridge University Press, 2004, 140 pp, $21.99 (pbk), ISBN

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Bayesian Probability

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Review of Nathan M. Nobis s Truth in Ethics and Epistemology

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

PHIL 155: The Scientific Method, Part 1: Naïve Inductivism. January 14, 2013

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

The Qualiafications (or Lack Thereof) of Epiphenomenal Qualia

The Illusion of Scientific Realism: An Argument for Scientific Soft Antirealism

Against Coherence: Truth, Probability, and Justification. Erik J. Olsson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xiii, 232.

What should I believe? What should I believe when people disagree with me?

THE PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE. jennifer ROSATO

Analogy and Pursuitworthiness

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Non-Naturalism and Naturalism in Mathematics, Morality, and Epistemology

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to The Theory of Knowledge, by Robert Audi. New York: Routledge, 2011.

Deflationary Nominalism s Commitment to Meinongianism

Skepticism is True. Abraham Meidan

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026

Prisoners' Dilemma Is a Newcomb Problem

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work on

Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness

or,sdteno PhiIosophjM THE SCIENTIST QUA SCIENTIST MAKES VALUE JUDGMENTS*

The Human Science Debate: Positivist, Anti-Positivist, and Postpositivist Inquiry. By Rebecca Joy Norlander. November 20, 2007

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

THE ROLE OF COHERENCE OF EVIDENCE IN THE NON- DYNAMIC MODEL OF CONFIRMATION TOMOJI SHOGENJI

Louisiana Law Review. Cheney C. Joseph Jr. Louisiana State University Law Center. Volume 35 Number 5 Special Issue Repository Citation

Reviewed Work: Why We Argue (and How We Should): A Guide to Political Disagreement, by Scott Aikin and Robert Talisse

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

Scientific Method and Research Ethics Questions, Answers, and Evidence. Dr. C. D. McCoy

A Contractualist Reply

INTRODUCTION: EPISTEMIC COHERENTISM

Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology

ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis

Induction, Rational Acceptance, and Minimally Inconsistent Sets

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

How Subjective Fact Ties Language to Reality

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Epistemology Naturalized

Kelly James Clark and Raymond VanArragon (eds.), Evidence and Religious Belief, Oxford UP, 2011, 240pp., $65.00 (hbk), ISBN

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Transcription:

Wichita State University Libraries SOAR: Shocker Open Access Repository Robert Feleppa Philosophy Epistemic Utility and Theory-Choice in Science: Comments on Hempel Robert Feleppa Wichita State University, robert.feleppa@wichita.edu Recommended citation Feleppa, Robert. 1981. Epistemic Utility and Theory-Choice in Science: Comments on Hempel. Synthese Vol. 46, pp. 413-420. (Proceedings of the Richard Rudner Memorial Symposium, Washington University, April, 1980.) This paper is posted in Shocker Open Access Repository http://soar.wichita.edu/dspace/handle/10057/3459

ROBERT FELEPPA EPISTEMIC UTILITY AND THEORY ACCEPTANCE: COMMENTS ON HEMPEL Professor Hempel has sketched a number of turns in the problem of induction, showing us in the process that the traditional problem of justifying inductive inference is inextricably bound up with problems concerning rational criteria of hypothesis and theory acceptance. In taking us through these various turns he surveys, and provides us valuable insights into, several of the guiding trends of a vast and often highly technical literature. In the interests of highlighting this valuable feature of his paper and to provide some focus for our subsequent discussion, I shall briefly review some of these turns, placing emphasis on what Hempel notes as the central relevance of certain questions raised by Richard Rudner concerning the character of scientific criteria of hypothesis acceptance. There are a number of, to my mind unsettled, issues concerning the task of the scientist qua scientist-particularly, the range of considerations that figure in the acceptance of hypotheses, and, indeed, how such "acceptance" is to be construed-and I shall direct the latter part of my commentary to these issues. In his opening remarks, Hempel correctly points out that adequate solutions to the problem of justifying the method of inductive acceptance, or MIA, depend on a clear characterization of the proposed method and the rules of inference that comprise it. Unlike the relatively unproblematic cases of deductive validity, when we apply an inductive rule to a premise such as 'All examined instances of A have been B', it is not clear what we mean when we say that 'All A are B' inductively follows from it. We cannot, of course, say this conclusion follows invariably, nor can we make the initially more plausible-sounding claim that when this sort of premise is true it is rational to accept the conclusion, or to act as if it were true: for adherence to the rule, thus construed, can lead us to the reductio predicament of "rationally" accepting logically incompatible conclusions that are supported by the same body of evidence. One way to avoid this problem, and thus bring us a step closer to Synthese 46 (1981) 413-420. 0039--7857[81/0463--0413 $00.80. Copyright 1981 by D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland.

414 ROBERT FELEPPA solving the twofold problem of characterizing, and then justifying rules of inductive inference, is to reconstrue the original problem as one of determining criteria for making precise probability assignments to the conclusions of inductive arguments. However, rather than reconstrue the problem this way, Hempel argues that it is better to see this as half of yet another twofold division of labor: we need to concern ourselves with the problem of characterizing and justifying rules of probability assignment and rules of acceptance of these conclusions, based in part on these determinations of probability. The problem of probability assignment demands, and has received, rigorous mathematical treatment; and it is certainly not entirely settled. However, the core of the original problem seems to be in the rational acceptability of these conclusions, and Hempel sets the probability problem aside to focus on this latter question. (Although he subsequently considers grounds for questioning whether dealing with this problem of acceptance is indeed a proper part of our philosophical inquiry into the bases of scientific validation.) And here too the intuitively most direct acceptance rule, i.e., accepting an hypothesis on the basis of its exceeding some stipulated probability runs, via the lottery paradox, into another reductio consequence similar to that just noted. So the current focal point of the problem of induction does not thus yield so easily to solution, but, rather, involves problems over and above those that concern the assignment of probabilities. In fact, this turn in the problem of induction connects it to a wider context of questions of hypothesis- and theory-acceptance, and to the turn that will be my main concern here: the degree to which value-judgments function in the validation of theory. That is, if the problem of induction is in part a problem of delineating rational criteria of hypothesis acceptance, then resolution of the controversy surrounding Richard Rudner's 'The scientist qua scientist makes value judgments' is a necessary task. For the thesis in this article is that considerations of social cost, governed in part by moral standards, figure in how high a probability will be demanded by a scientist of an hypothesis before accepting it. Hempel sets up Richard Jeffrey's 'Valuation and acceptance of scientific hypotheses' as an antithesis to Rudner's article. Here Jeffrey argues that Rudner has conflated the scientist qua scientist's type of acceptance with the practical application of an hypothesis-i.e., its

COMMENTS ON HEMPEL 415 "acceptance" in the sense of making commitments to practical courses of action. Indeed, Jeffrey concedes that acceptance in this latter sense involves moral value judgments, but that this sort of acceptance is no proper part of the task of the scientist qua scientist, whose objective, though we typically call it hypothesis acceptance, is not really to accept hypotheses at all, but only to assign them degrees of probability. These assignments are in turn taken into consideration, along with considerations of social cost, by those who would apply the scientist-qua-scientist's results to particular problems: but while scientists themselves may make such applications, or may have them on their mind when engaged in theory-validation, these considerations are outside the purview of "pure science". The synthesis that Hempel offers involves conceding to Rudner that the pure scientist makes value judgments but in maintaining, on the other hand, in essence the fact-value dichotomy that Jeffrey favors by circumscribing the range of pertinent values to purely epistemic varieties. That is, while the assignment of utilities to the success or failure of hypotheses should figure in the justification of their acceptance (and in our general consideration of the justifiability of the MIA), it is only the epistemic utilities that need be included and not the wider range of practical utilities that figure in the Rudner account of rational acceptability. If we take the increase of scientific knowledge as our rational objective, then relative to that we may ascertain the epistemic utility of truth, high information content, simplicity, explanatory power, etc. Thus considerations of epistemic utility will figure in the determination of inductive acceptance rules (although success will still not come easy), without breaching the intuitive divide between science and practical or moral concerns. The subsequent turns that Hempel discusses extend the original problem of induction into still wider contexts of problems raised by Thomas Kuhn concerning theory-adoption and change and particularly to what Hempel calls the "historic pragmatist" strategy of justification of scientific acceptability-i.e., by reference to the intuitive judgments of scientific experts-that Kuhn offers. There are two lines of development from here: (1) Insofar as the generally accepted desiderata of scientific theories cannot be given precise specification or ordering, they cannot be rationally justified at all (although Kuhn contends otherwise) - that is, for a wide range of important cases we never escape the problem that has been with us

416 ROBERT FELEPPA from the outset, namely, of not having a clear idea of what is being justified. (2) The historic pragmatist account that Kuhn gives is significantly analogous to Nelson Goodman's account of the justification of deductive and inductive rules, and this accountdoes avail us of a justification of inductive practice for the range of cases in which clear specification of the rules can be given. What enables genuine rational justification here, but not in Kuhn's account, is a rational vindication of inductive procedure. According to Professor Goodman's account (which, by the way, has close affinities with the epistemological views of W. V. Quine and Pierre Duhem, and which has been significantly extended to the context of ethical justification by Morton White and John Rawls), the principles governing inductive practice exist, if I may adapt Rawls's terminology, in "reflective equilibrium" without strong, presystematic intuitive judgments regarding the inductive validity of certain kinds of arguments. Although the principles generally "govern" our judgments on particular cases, the principles may indeed be modified if they conflict with our strong intuitive judgments. The justification of inductive rules comes in seeing them as arising from the codification of inductive practice, a codification which achieves certain systematic advantages over the uncodified practice in promoting the growth of knowledge-and here is the important vindicatory step, I believe Hempel sees as missing from Kuhn's account. In the spirit of Quine and Duhem, we are not seeking to provide some transcendant basis for inductive rules: their grounding comes in part from their conformance to the practices and presystematic judgments they serve to codify and in part from the systematic advantages codification provides. Thus we have, in I hope fairly clear outline, the survey Hempel has given us, and I think it is evident that various questions of hypothesis acceptance turn up in important places throughout the evolution of the problem of induction. However, as I indicated at the outset, I have some difficulty in getting an adequate understanding of what hypothesis acceptance is, given the significantly different construais of this notion that various of the philosophers discussed here seem to give it. And, although the questions I shall raise here directly concern the scientist-qua-scientist dispute, I wonder if the conceptual difficulties here (if they are not entirely mine) may not also affect the subsequent turns Hempel discusses. As you will recall, Hempel was in substantial agreement with

COMMENTS ON HEMPEL 417 Jeffrey's point that Rudner's examples are insufficient to make the point that the pure scientist must make moral value judgments. This seems to follow, they argue, only if we conflate concerns with the practical application of hypotheses with the purely scientific objective of improving our body of scientific knowledge. Where Hempel disagrees with Jeffrey, and agrees, in part, with Rudner, is in claiming that the scientist does, indeed, accept hypotheses (but, qua pure scientist, only with respect to the epistemic utilities). However, it is not clear to me that Rudner's point that moral value judgments figure in scientific acceptance has been fully refuted. The general applicability of his examples is, I agree, made questionable by the objections Jeffrey raises to the effect that the scientist, on this view, would be unable to assign any one level of acceptance to most hypotheses. Withholding acceptance of hypotheses with their potential high-cost applications in mind might well be detrimental to other potential areas of application where the social cost factor is lower. With regard to these sorts of cases there seems to be good reason to modify Rudner's claim-perhaps in the way Hempel suggests. In these cases it does not seem to be the proper business of the scientist qua scientist to take the non-epistemic utilities into account, and, indeed, it seems that in these sorts of cases scientists don't in fact do so. What hinders my acceptance of Hempel's position, however, are a number of the cases that initially lend credence to Rudner's viewe.g., that of the Manhattan Project which is not discussed by either Hempel or Jeffrey. Granted that there are problems in generalizing from this example (although there is also Rudner's adaptation of Quine's critique of Carnap's distinction between internal and external questions to be taken into account), but this example resists, I think, an adequate accounting on the epistemic utility view. No doubt the social cost of failure figured in the determination of the acceptance level of hypotheses assigned by the Manhattan Project physicists; yet it seems, on the present view, that we must say that insofar as they took such non-epistemic utilities into account in accepting these hypotheses, they were not accepting them qua scientists, but rather qua practical appliers of theory. Yet, these hypotheses did, during the course of the Manhattan Project research, get accepted into physical theory; and, one would think, they were accepted just at the point at which enough evidence was in to assign a probability level suitably high enough to offset the social cost of failure. However, it seems that

418 ROBERT FELEPPA on the present view there was another sort of acceptance involvedone that was not governed by this non-epistemic utility and which was, undeniably, a full acceptance of the hypotheses in question into physical theory. What I cannot get clear is what this latter kind of acceptance was like and at what point in the historical development of the Manhattan Project research it occurred. It does not seem that it occurred at the point at which the scientists said the hypotheses were accepted: surely they withheld such pronouncement until the social cost factor was fully taken into account. If anything, one would think this non-epistemic utility would drive the acceptance level upward, leading one to think that if epistemic utility were all that figured in hypothesis acceptance, this latter act of acceptance would have occurred earlier, when tess evidence was in. But then, for some time during the course of the development of that project the hypotheses were accepted parts of scientific theory, yet were not accepted in the fuller sense: and this fuller sense would involve,! think, their announcing their full and unmitigated acceptance to their superiors. Am 1 to understand the purely scientific act of acceptance as a private or secret one? I would expect that if I polled the Manhattan Project scientists on this, they would recollect no such private decision. And even if they did, couldn't we still quite justifiably ask if they, or anyone, can be said to accept hypothesis if they refuse to admit this because they aren't yet sure enough of the likelihood of its truth. In any construal of a notion of acceptance wouldn't we want to preserve the truth value of the claim 'Jones does not accept p if he refuses to say that he accepts p because he isn't quite sure'? If a scientist develops a theory about atomic fission and applies more rigorous standards of acceptance because of the immense social cost of one sort of hypothesis failure (a small, but annoyingly open possibility of an atmospheric chain reaction), I do not see how it can be claimed that this contemplation of social cost can be said to be figuring only in some context of application of theory and not, inextricably, in the process of adding hypotheses to theory. Now, again, I agree that it is difficult to generalize from this sort of case to all other types of hypothesis acceptance. The scientist needn't always make moral value judgments. But I cannot yet see how we can say that such judgments never figure in the validation of theory if we do indeed admit that hypothesis acceptance is a proper part of the pure scientist's task.

COMMENTS ON HEMPEL 419 Of course Jeffrey needn't be concerned with this problem because he also insists that the scientist qua scientist doesn't really accept hypotheses at all. On his account I think one can clearly delineate those aspects of the Manhattan Project research that belonged to pure science. The research scientists were acting qua scientists in assigning probabilities to hypotheses on certain evidential bases and qua theory-appliers when deciding whether or not to announce acceptance of them. However, this view has other problems which Hempel has noted here and in the earlier paper of his which he cites, and I will not recount them here: except to point out that these objections turn on Jeffrey's overly stretching the notion of acceptance in the opposite direction- that is, in asking us to refrain from regarding as hypothesis-acceptance a wide variety of uses of and dispositions towards hypotheses (such as the evidence statements which are used in the very determinations of probability). Perhaps there is an easy enough solution of these problems in an adequate explication of 'hypothesis acceptance'. But aside from this, one must keep in mind the Quinean-Duhemian background of Rudner's thesis which presents general considerations that run counter to a number of the sharp delineations that Hempel is making. (And, indeed, as Hempel notes in his earlier article, the Duhemian view of theories also conflicts with the implication of Jeffrey's view that the analysis of the experimental testing and validation of hypotheses need take into account only the isolated hypothesis and its confirming evidence and not the other theoretical hypotheses that are assumedand, thus, accepted-in the process.) For in extending Quine's critique of Carnap's delineation of internal and external questions (the former, on Carnap's view, being the factual ones that it is the business of genuinely scientific hypotheses to answer, and the latter being the practical ones answered in a prior act of scheme adoption), Rudner challenges the proposed fact-value distinction as well. If scientific hypotheses, as Quine argues, serve to answer these practical, "external" questions, and if practical questions involve making value judgments in a wide sense, then iris not clear that we free the scientist qua scientist from the task of making moral, as well as epistemic, value judgments in validating hypotheses. As Professor Leach notes in a penetrating commentary on this dispute, as it might be argued in Quinean fashion both that no observational statements are quite free from theory, and that no theoretical statements are quite free of experimental

420 ROBERT FELEPPA considerations, so it might also be argued in extension that no hypotheses are quite free of practical consequences. ( 'Explanation and Value Neutrality' ) Wichita State University