Introduction to Political Science

Similar documents
Falsification of Popper and Lakatos (Falsifikace podle Poppera a Lakatose)

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Module 1: Science as Culture Demarcation, Autonomy and Cognitive Authority of Science

Sydenham College of Commerce & Economics. * Dr. Sunil S. Shete. * Associate Professor

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

A Brief History of Scientific Thoughts Lecture 5. Palash Sarkar

Popper s Falsificationism. Philosophy of Economics University of Virginia Matthias Brinkmann

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

Ilija Barukčić Causality. New Statistical Methods. ISBN X Discussion with the reader.

Revista Economică 66:3 (2014) THE USE OF INDUCTIVE, DEDUCTIVE OR ABDUCTIVE RESONING IN ECONOMICS

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Introduction to Deductive and Inductive Thinking 2017

Lectures and laboratories activities on the nature of Physics and concepts and models in optic: 1. Scientific sentences

ECONOMETRIC METHODOLOGY AND THE STATUS OF ECONOMICS. Cormac O Dea. Junior Sophister

Philosophy and Methods of the Social Sciences

Lecture 9. A summary of scientific methods Realism and Anti-realism

Philosophy of Economics versus Methodology of Economics

Kant s Copernican Revolution

FINAL EXAM REVIEW SHEET. objectivity intersubjectivity ways the peer review system is supposed to improve objectivity

Debate Vocabulary 203 terms by mdhamilton25

PHILOSOPHIES OF SCIENTIFIC TESTING

The poverty of mathematical and existential truth: examples from fisheries science C. J. Corkett

METHODENSTREIT WHY CARL MENGER WAS, AND IS, RIGHT

On the futility of criticizing the neoclassical maximization hypothesis

Causation and Free Will

Falsification or Confirmation: From Logic to Psychology

Scientific errors should be controlled, not prevented. Daniel Eindhoven University of Technology

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

The Human Science Debate: Positivist, Anti-Positivist, and Postpositivist Inquiry. By Rebecca Joy Norlander. November 20, 2007

Learning from Mistakes Karl Popper and Thomas Kuhn

Lecture 6. Realism and Anti-realism Kuhn s Philosophy of Science

Building Your Framework everydaydebate.blogspot.com by James M. Kellams

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Revision Guide (all topics)

Karl Popper & The Philosophy of Science. What Makes a Theory Scientific?

Science and Pseudoscience (transcript)

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Consciousness might be defined as the perceiver of mental phenomena. We might say that there are no differences between one perceiver and another, as

Writing Module Three: Five Essential Parts of Argument Cain Project (2008)

Scientific Method and Research Ethics

Theoretical Virtues in Science

Religion and Science: The Emerging Relationship Part II


FEYERABENDCRITIQUE OF FALSIFICATION PRINCIPLE OF KARL POPPER: WITH SPECIAL REFERENCE TO AGAINST METHOD A PHILOSOPHICAL ANALYSIS

Unit. Science and Hypothesis. Downloaded from Downloaded from Why Hypothesis? What is a Hypothesis?

Arguing with Libertarianism without Argument : Critical Rationalism and how it applies to Libertarianism

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

Two Ways of Thinking

THE SCIENTIFIC PROCESS C H A P T E R 3

The Exemplar Approach to Science and Religion

Business Research: Principles and Processes MGMT6791 Workshop 1A: The Nature of Research & Scientific Method

imply constrained maximization. are realistic assumptions. are assumptions that may yield testable implications. A and C above.

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

PHILOSOPHICAL RAMIFICATIONS: THEORY, EXPERIMENT, & EMPIRICAL TRUTH

Absolutism. The absolutist believes mathematics is:

ABSOLUTISM. The absolutist believes mathematics is:

Teaching Portfolio. 1 Introduction to the Philosophy of Causation. 2 Introduction to Classical Logic. Michael Baumgartner.

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

SAMPLE ESSAY 1: PHILOSOPHY & SOCIAL SCIENCE (1 ST YEAR)

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

A Quick Review of the Scientific Method Transcript

Are Miracles Identifiable?

THE ROLE OF COHERENCE OF EVIDENCE IN THE NON- DYNAMIC MODEL OF CONFIRMATION TOMOJI SHOGENJI

Scientific Dimensions of the Debate. 1. Natural and Artificial Selection: the Analogy (17-20)

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action

On Popper, Problems and Problem-Solving: A Review of Cruickshank and Sassower's Democratic Problem-Solving

Baha i Proofs for the Existence of God

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

What Is Science? Mel Conway, Ph.D.

Hoong Juan Ru. St Joseph s Institution International. Candidate Number Date: April 25, Theory of Knowledge Essay

The Enlightenment Programme and Karl Popper

Classroom notes for: Radiation and Life Professor: Thomas M. Regan Pinanski 206 ext 3283

Karl Popper ( )

David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature ( ), Book I, Part III.

Demarcation of Science

Ladies and Gentlemen, welcome to my talk. My topic is "Theory of knowledge - Thomas S. Kuhn and Paul Feyerabend" I want to tell you simple story

Religious Instruction, Religious Studies and Religious Education

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

RATIONAL RECONSTRUCTION IN THE NATURE OF SCIENTIFIC TRUTH. Md. Abdul Mannan *

We aim to cover in some detail a number of issues currently debated in the philosophy of natural and social science.

Skepticism is True. Abraham Meidan

14 IS THERE CAUSALITY IN HISTORY?

AKC Lecture 1 Plato, Penrose, Popper

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Philosophy of Mind. Introduction to the Mind-Body Problem

EPISTEMOLOGY for DUMMIES

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics

Analyticity, Reductionism, and Semantic Holism. The verification theory is an empirical theory of meaning which asserts that the meaning of a

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

VI. CEITICAL NOTICES.

Could i conceive being a brain in a vat? John D. Collier a a

Sheldrake's "Hypothesis"

Class 6 - Scientific Method

DO WE NEED A THEORY OF METAPHYSICAL COMPOSITION?

Instructor's Manual for Gregg Barak s Integrating Criminologies. Prepared by Paul Leighton (Boston: Allyn & Bacon, 1997) * CHAPTER 4

Putnam on Methods of Inquiry

Transcription:

Introduction to Political Science What is Science? Reading Ole J. Forsberg, Ph.D. University of Tennessee What is Science? Ole J. Forsberg What is a science? Science is a method of inquiry whose objectives are to describe observed reality and predict outcomes. A discipline cannot be a science, only scientific in nature. When is a discipline scientific? A discipline is a science if the sole accepted modes of inquiry are scientific in nature. That does not mean that one cannot do science in a non-scientific discipline, only that those scientific methods are not the norm. Physics is a scientific discipline because those who practice physics and work in the discipline utilize scientific modes of inquiry to create scientific theories and hypotheses. Political Science, while it can be studied scientifically, is not a scientific discipline yet, since there are still several non-scientific methods of inquiry that fail to create scientific theories and hypotheses. What are scientific theories? In science, theories serve as the primary means of understanding the world. These scientific theories provide a general understanding of the relationships between observables. Theories are general; that is, they seek to give empirical meaning to a wide scope of observations. Scientific theories produce falsifiable hypotheses against which they can be tested. If testable hypotheses are not a result of the theory, then the theory is neither scientific nor useful. What is the difference between scientific laws and theories? Scientific laws are much narrower, much more specific in scope. They apply to one (or very few) class(es) of observations. In science, they are treated as facts. Furthermore, laws cannot be broken cannot, not are not. Example. According to the Law of Conservation of Momentum, in any collision in a closed system, the total momentum of that closed system remains constant. While this seems to be general, it only applies to calculations of momentum in a collision its scope is very limited. Also, it can never be violated. Once a violation is detected, it is no longer a law. Theories cannot be laws, as they seek to give broader meaning to a greater number of cases. Furthermore, the life cycle of theories is completely different than that of laws. Theories are more robust; that is, they can withstand counterexamples. Laws cease to exist at the discovery of a single counterexample.

What is a scientific hypothesis? A hypothesis is a proposed answer to a research question that fits three requirements: falsifiable, empirical, and general. 1 To be falsifiable, there must exist some empirical manner of proving the hypothesis wrong. In more precise language, a hypothesis is falsifiable if it divides the universe of conceivable observations into two non-empty sets, those that contradict the hypothesis and those that do not. To be empirical, the manner of testing the hypothesis must be done through observation and measurement. Finally, hypotheses must apply to more than just a single case; that is, the hypothesis must speak to more than just one example. Example. The statement Democracies do not go to war with other democracies is, indeed, a scientific hypothesis. It meets the three requirements above: It is falsifiable, for it could be observed that there are two democracies that went to war. Second, under certain operationalizations, all aspects of the hypothesis are measurable (empirical). One can easily define both democracy and war in ways that can be measured. In fact, a great deal of the research on war has done just this. Finally, the hypothesis is general. It applies to more than just one pair of democracies in one time period. Furthermore, it is not a theory. It speaks solely to those things called democracies and their conflict paths towards war (it does not incorporate a vast number of hypotheses into a simple framework). Had the statement been Norway did not go to war with Luxembourg in 1990, it would have been neither a theory nor a hypothesis; it would have been a fact. It lacks any suggestion of generality. What is a fact? A fact is an agreed-upon interpretation of an observation made by competent observers. Is it a fact that the rebels won the American War of Independence? Yes. Competent observers (historians) have interpreted observations made (through reading first-hand accounts of the war or through experiencing the war) and have agreed that the statement is true. Interestingly enough, facts have the ability to change; facts are not perfectly portable. This means that facts can change if the examining discipline is changed. This often occurs when the information travels into a different realm with different competency requirements. Be aware of this when you use facts in your writings. Example. Is it a fact that my parent s living room was blue? To the average person, the answer is yes. If that question is asked of an interior decorator, however, the answer might be no; the color is Fifth Avenue Blue. To a physicist, the answer might also be no; the color is 4500Å. 2 If facts can change, what s the point? One option is to throw up our hands and never attempt to find order in the world. The other option is to continue searching, because the facts we find are the best we can do at that point. This 1 2 For a more complete discussion of the requirements of science and pseudo-science, see Karl R. Popper. 1959. The Logic of Scientific Discovery. (New York: Basic Books). The wavelength of pure blue light is 4000Å. Interestingly enough, the Ångstrom is no longer used as a measure of wavelength, being deprecated in favor of the nanometer (nm).

is pragmatism we do the best we can with what we are given. This also leads to exposure of the greatest myth about science: objective reality. What is objective reality? D Oliveiro, a philosopher, defined objective reality as whatever remains true whether you believe in it or not. 3 In essence, this definition specifies that objective reality is the world out there, the world that exists in reality. As such, subjective reality is the world we perceive. 4 It is how we interpret the objective reality (if it exists). Many people think science is objective, that it focuses on the object of study the real world. Some hold, however, that since we must interpret (through our senses, our brains, and our theories) the world, then science must be subjective. As subjective reality varies from one person to the next, it is relative. If one holds to the belief that reality is relative to the observer, then relativism (and all of its weaknesses) invariably results. The reality of the situation is that science is neither objective nor subjective; it is intersubjective. Recall that science uses facts that depend on the agreement of many competent observers. Inter-subjectivity accepts the reality created by this agreement. It denies both that it has perfectly described the objective world and that it is completely subjective. This shows the importance of those competent observers, of checking the facts yourself. What is the life cycle of a theory? Whenever a discussion of scientific inquiry takes place, three names must be mentioned. The holy trinity of the philosophy of science is Karl Popper, Thomas Kuhn, and Imre Lakatos. These three have written extensively on what makes an enterprise scientific and how a scientific enterprise differs from a non-scientific one. The summary of each of the three is presented here. Karl Raimond Popper focused on what constituted scientific exploration. 5 His primary concentration was to determine the line of demarcation between physics and metaphysics. What makes a hypothesis scientific, and what makes it pseudo-scientific? Popper knew of Kant s line of demarcation, induction, but Popper saw the inherent logical inconsistencies in Kant s line of demarcation. After much though, Popper decided the line of demarcation was falsifiability of the statements. About falsifiability, Popper wrote, According to this criterion, a statement, or a system of statements, convey information about the empirical world only if they are capable of clashing with experience; or more precisely, only if they can be systematically tested, that is to say, if they can be subjected (in accordance with a methodological decision ) to tests which might result in their refutation. 6 3 4 5 6 Lawrence D Oliveiro. 2000. The Nature of Objective Reality. March 27. http://www.geek-central.gen.nz/peeves/objective reality.html (January 10, 2005). An interesting side note: The terms objective and subjective come from grammar placement. The object of the sentence receives the action, while the subject of the sentence performs the action. This discussion is from Karl R. Popper. 1959. The Logic of Scientific Discovery. (New York: Basic Books). Popper: 315.

Thus, a statement is scientifically, is empirically valuable if it is testable. Non-testable statements are either tautologies (like mathematics) or metaphysics (like philosophy). Either way they convey no new information about the world. They may be useful in other ways, but they are not science. When he was forced to describe the life cycle of a theory, Popper centered it on the concept of falsifiability. If a theory had been falsified, i.e. if a counter example existed, then the theory had to be abandoned. This obviously did not happen. Thomas Samuel Kuhn realized that theories were never easily abandoned. He focused his thoughts on creating a general theory of scientific development that showed the process of science. 7 For Kuhn, there were two different kinds of science: normal and revolutionary. Normal science occurs when scientific progress is marked with a generally accepted paradigm, the research agenda for the discipline focuses on this paradigm, and the practitioners tests the paradigm. The tests of the theories will not always support the theory. The paradigm is found lacking. But, scientists do not throw away the paradigm because of a few negative results. However, eventually, those negative results become the focus of exploration. As they become less and less the exception and more the rule, the paradigm is replaced; the benefits from adhering to it are vastly outweighed by the wrong answers it gives in addition to the loss of elegance. 8 During the time between when the paradigm is found all but worthless until the time it is successfully replaced with another paradigm, there is no single direction in the discipline. This period is called revolutionary science. This is how science advances for Kuhn. Imre Lipschitz Molnár Lakatos was a rationalist, someone who believed that Reason can and will prevail over Will. 9 As he grew up under the occupation of Nazi Germany in Hungary, and who lived under the Soviet system, he understood the dangers of dogmatism. He also read Popper thoroughly and understood that the idea of falsification was not the appropriate line of demarcation between science and pseudo-science. 10 All scientific theories, according to Lakatos, are falsified innumerable times by data that does not fully fit them. Thus, if we assert Popper s views on current theories of physics, they would all be falsified. 11 In place of falsification, and in 7 8 9 10 11 This discussion is from Thomas S. Kuhn. 1996. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press) A theory is elegant if it can be concisely stated. In both science and mathematics, elegance is desirable. The inclusion of too many ad hoc additions not only reduces elegance, but it also demonstrates the number of exceptions to the theory that have yet to be included. Brendan Larvor. 1998. Lakatos: An Introduction. (New York: Routledge, 1). This discussion is from Imre Lakatos. 1978. The Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes. (New York: Cambridge University Press) and from Brendan Larvor. 1998. Lakatos: An Introduction. (New York: Routledge). This argument overstates Popper s original intent and replaces it with dogmatic falsificationism. If one adheres to dogmatic falsificationism, any finding that contradicts a scientific theory disproves it fully. Popper did not hold this extreme view. In its place, he held that counterexamples merely weaken a theory something called methodological falsificationism.

place of Popper s and of Kuhn s centrality of the theory in science, Lakatos employed what he called the research programme. To Lakatos, the research programme consisted of a logical collection of ideas, theories, and paradigms which comprised the hard core of the programme, along with a protective belt of hypotheses which, in essence, shield the core from falsification. The hypotheses get falsified, but the theory does not. The protective belt constantly changes to account for hypotheses that were falsified, but the hard core remains intact. When a programme changes in response solely to external forces, it is degenerating. When it changes in response to internal forces, it is progressing. That is, if the programmes are changed ad hoc to account for anomalous outcomes, it is degenerative. If the change in the programme explains past theories and predicts future ones, it is progressive. For Lakatos, a discipline is scientific as long as progressive programmes tend to triumph over degenerating ones. So, which view is correct? To me, disciplines are neither science nor non-science. Methods can be categorized in such a manner, but disciplines cannot. Advancing disciplines use scientific methods to achieve results. The pluralization on the word methods indicates a definite support methodological pluralism. There is no problem with a discipline that uses a historico-traditional method, a behavioralist method, and a post-behavioralist method as long as the created theories are testable in the Popperian sense and the discipline advances in the Lakatosian sense. How does all this affect this course (if this course had a research paper)? The only questions that can be explored in the research paper are questions that can be answered in an empirical manner. Proposed answers to the research question (hypotheses) must meet the three requirements of scientific theories. These hypotheses must reflect the current theories and literature on the topic. That means that the hypotheses must be the answers to the research question according to the extant literature. Finally, the hypotheses must be operationalizable. How does one operationalize a hypothesis? When a hypothesis is operationalized, each of the concepts in the hypothesis is clearly defined and they have an explicit manner of measurement. To operationalize a hypothesis, one must first be completely aware of the concepts mentioned in the hypothesis. One must then propose measures and methods of measure of those concepts. Simple Example. Hypothesis: Democracies do not go to war against other democracies. The two main concepts here are war and democracy. War is defined as a protracted conflict with 1,000 or more battle deaths. This is the normally accepted empirical definition. It is also easily measured. 12 Democracy is not as easily defined. Several measures of democracy are currently available. One method focuses on the structures of the government (constraints on the executive 12 In this sense, easy is a synonym for straight-forward.

and regular elections). To measure democracy, we would then examine the constitutions for effective limits on the executive and combine that with the existence of regularly held, competitive elections. If a country has both, then it is a democracy. If it lacks either, then it is not. Note what was done. The concepts were pulled from the hypothesis. Those concepts were reduced to the point of observation. That process of reduction is connected to the original concepts; that is, the measures actually seem, prima facie, 13 to measure what they are supposed to measure. A quick check to determine if your hypothesis was properly operationalized is to determine if one can readily determine how to test it and what results would disprove the hypothesis. For instance, is the above operationalization satisfactory? Can we tell what a democracy is? Can we tell what a war is? Can we tell if a democracy has gone to war with another democracy? The answer to each of these three questions is yes. Therefore, the hypothesis is properly operationalized. An Example of a Bad Operationalization. Hypothesis: The Electoral College does not work like the framers of our Constitution intended. Operationalization: Work Performing a duty or task. Intended To have in mind or plan. The Electoral College does not perform its task like the framers of our constitution had in mind. Why is this not a good operationalization? The terms are properly defined, at least according to Webster. So, what is it missing? This: How can we tell if the Electoral College works like the framers of our Constitution intended? From what was provided, we cannot tell. Thus, we cannot determine before hand what it would take to falsify the hypothesis. Another Example. Hypothesis: Minorities are more likely to have jobs and a higher education in states that enforce Affirmative Action than those that do not. Operationalization: Affirmative Action is a policy or a program that seeks to redress past discrimination through active measures to ensure equal opportunity, as in education and employment. Minorities are a group having little power or representation relative to other groups within a society. The state is the body politic, especially one constituting a nation. To enforce is to compel observance of or obedience to. The socioeconomic status (SES = GSP per capita/cost of living) and the unemployment rate of minorities in a state will reveal if Affirmative Action is economically effective in the state or not. The education levels will reveal if Affirmative Action has impact on the amount of education that minorities receive in a state. Is this a good operationalization or not? Can we tell if minorities have jobs and higher education using the operationalization? Can we tell if a state enforces Affirmative Action using the operationalization? If the answer to both is yes, then it is a good operationalization. Why is operationalization important? At this point, the answer should be obvious. It would also make a good test question. 13 The term prima facie is Latin for first sight.

Causation Causation is a concept in both philosophy and science. The concept of causality refers to the set of all particular causal or cause-and-effect relations. Unfortunately, a neutral definition is hard to provide, as every aspect of causation has been subject to much philosophical debate, including its very existence. For us, causation is a relationship that holds between events, properties, variables, or states. Causality always implies at least some dependent relationship between the cause and the effect. For example, deeming something a cause may imply that, all other things being equal, if the cause occurs, then the effect does as well (absolute causation), or at least that the probability of the effect occurring increases (probable causation). It is also usually presumed that the cause chronologically precedes the effect (temporal precedence). The concept of causation in science is quite similar. However, one cannot prove causation. This should not be surprising, as nothing is proven in science; hypothesized relationships are only supported. However, causation does offer something that mere correlation does not. It allows one to suggest a manner of changing the outcomes. Showing causation is quite simple in theory. In an absolute sense of causality, if Event A causes Event B, then every time we observe Event A, we will also observe Event B; Event A always precedes an Event B; and there must be a theoretical reason for Event A to cause Event B. In a probabilistic sense of causality, the same three requirements exist (correlation, temporal precedence, and theoretical feasibility), only without the requirement of it always happening, only that the probability of the effect happening increases significantly. Example. It has been shown that increases in temperature always precede increases in the violent crime rate. Is causation shown? No. Correlation is shown: when Event A occurs (higher temperatures), then Event B always occurs (higher violent crime rates). Temporal precedence is shown: Event A (higher temperatures) happens before Event B (higher crime rates). However, there is no solid theory as to why Event A causes Event B. The reality is that there is an intervening cause, people are out later in the day in the summers (higher temperatures), which increases the chances that a violent event will take place. Example. It has also been shown that people with larger shoe sizes (Event A) also tend to score higher on the SAT (Event B). Is causation shown? No. Again, the first two requirements are made. There lacks, however, a theoretical reason for the causation. Here, there is a common factor: age. Older people tend to have larger feet (compare a toddler with a college student). Older people also tend to do better on the SAT (again, compare a toddler with a college student). Example. It has been shown that terrorist groups are less active under left-leaning governments than under right-leaning governments. Is causation shown? Yes. There are fewer terrorist attacks under left-leaning governments than under right-leaning governments (Correlation). When a left-leaning government is elected, the number of terrorist attacks drops in that state (Temporal Precedence). Left-leaning governments are more willing to negotiate with a terrorist group, thus terrorist groups are more willing to have a left-leaning government in power. Right-leaning governments tend to eschew negotiations in place of military action, which terrorist groups do not want to happen (Theoretical Feasibility).

Questions 1. Why is it important to operationalize a hypothesis? 2. Discuss the problems associated with objective reality and subjective reality. How does inter-subjective reality solve those problems? 3. In science, is it a good thing to call something a theory? How does that compare to every-day life? 4. What does it mean to know something in science? Does science offer answers? 5. A famous person once said that science spends its time proving itself wrong, whereas religion spends its time assuming itself right. What does this mean? 6. Which is primary, science or politics? 7. Give examples of three causal relationships in the real world. Are there any intervening variables or common factors in your examples?