A Reply to Serena Feloj on The Powers of Pure Reason

Similar documents
Alfredo Ferrarin: The Powers of Pure Reason. Kant and the Idea of Cosmic Philosophy. University of Chicago Press, 2015, 352 pp.

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

FIL 4600/10/20: KANT S CRITIQUE AND CRITICAL METAPHYSICS

Kant on Biology and the Experience of Life

The Groundwork, the Second Critique, Pure Practical Reason and Motivation

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law

1/5. The Critique of Theology

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

KANT'S PROLEGOMENA TO ANY FUTURE METAPHYSICS CHICAGO DR. PAUL CARUS THE OPEN COURT PUBLISHING COMPANY

The Boundaries of Hegel s Criticism of Kant s Concept of the Noumenal

The CopernicanRevolution

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought

Thursday, November 30, 17. Hegel s Idealism

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

1/6. The Resolution of the Antinomies

Kant On The A Priority of Space: A Critique Arjun Sawhney - The University of Toronto pp. 4-7

Tuesday, November 11, Hegel s Idealism

ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis

THE CRISIS OF THE SCmNCES AS EXPRESSION OF THE RADICAL LIFE-CRISIS OF EUROPEAN HUMANITY

Between The Bounds of Experience and Divine Intuition: Kant s Epistemic Limits and Hegel s Ambitions

Descartes: A Guide for the Perplexed

Practical Reason and the Call to Faith: Kant on the Postulates of Immortality and God

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

Some Pragmatic Themes in Kant s Critique of Pure Reason

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

A Priori Knowledge: Analytic? Synthetic A Priori (again) Is All A Priori Knowledge Analytic?

1/9. The First Analogy

INVESTIGATING THE PRESUPPOSITIONAL REALM OF BIBLICAL-THEOLOGICAL METHODOLOGY, PART II: CANALE ON REASON

1/8. Introduction to Kant: The Project of Critique

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Absolute Totality, Causality, and Quantum: The Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason. Kazuhiko Yamamoto, Kyushu University, Japan

THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781)

Honors Ethics Oral Presentations: Instructions

Hegel's Critique of Contingency in Kant's Principle of Teleology

Denis Seron. Review of: K. Mulligan, Wittgenstein et la philosophie austro-allemande (Paris: Vrin, 2012). Dialectica

Michael Rohlf curriculum vitae

Kant s insight and kant s concept of a

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition:

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Response to The Problem of the Question About Animal Ethics by Michal Piekarski

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Online version of this review can be found at:

Kant and his Successors

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S

Wisdom in Aristotle and Aquinas From Metaphysics to Mysticism Edmond Eh University of Saint Joseph, Macau

Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth

Absolute Totality, Causality, and Quantum: The Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason

Immanuel Kant. Great German philosophers whose influence was and continues to be immense; born in Konigsberg East Prussia, in 1724, died there in 1804

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

Accessing the Moral Law through Feeling

Summer Preparation Work

THE FICHTEAN IDEA OF THE SCIENCE OF KNOWLEDGE. by Jean Hyppolite*

The Idealism of Life: Hegel and Kant on the Ontology of Living Individuals

1/8. The Schematism. schema of empirical concepts, the schema of sensible concepts and the

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

Lecture 18: Rationalism

Logical Mistakes, Logical Aliens, and the Laws of Kant's Pure General Logic Chicago February 21 st 2018 Tyke Nunez

The Challenge of God. Julia Grubich

Critique of Practical Reason

2006 by Marcus Willaschek

KANT ON THE UNITY OF THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL REASON.

Critical Discussion of A. W. Moore s Critique of Kant

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

Kant s Transcendental Idealism

Henry of Ghent on Divine Illumination

Kant s Copernican Revolution

Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial.

Consciousness might be defined as the perceiver of mental phenomena. We might say that there are no differences between one perceiver and another, as

The Construction of Empirical Concepts and the Establishment of the Real Possibility of Empirical Lawlikeness in Kant's Philosophy of Science

Introduction. 1 Bertrand Russell, The Problems of Philosophy (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, n.d.), 7.

IMMANUEL KANT Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals [Edited and reduced by J. Bulger, Ph.D.]

1/8. Reid on Common Sense

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

To link to this article:

Writing Your Doctoral Thesis with Word This document is an example of what you can do with the POLITO Template

Kant Lecture 4 Review Synthetic a priori knowledge

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

PHILOSOPHY IAS MAINS: QUESTIONS TREND ANALYSIS

Kate Moran Brandeis University

Is Kant's Account of Free Will Coherent?

Sufficient Reason and Infinite Regress: Causal Consistency in Descartes and Spinoza. Ryan Steed

1/8. The Third Analogy

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Phenomenology, Empiricism, and Science

Transcription:

A Reply to Serena Feloj on The Powers of Pure Reason Alfredo Ferrarin 1 University of Pisa I wish to thank Serena Feloj for her generous discussion of my book. I will try to answer her questions by beginning with the issue of influence. Serena asks if my interpretation of Kant is indebted to phenomenology (with regard to the dependence on givenness), and later she claims, this time without questions, that I reveal a debt to Hegel s philosophy (on the notion of form). However intriguing and fruitful I may find relating Hegel and Husserl, 2 there are certain discrepancies and theoretical differences in their respective views on the relation between thought and reality that are too obvious to ignore. I am not claiming that the motives of inspiration coming from these two philosophers are incompatible and thereby preemptying Serena s questions of content. I am instead shifting ground and admitting that in my reading of Kant as in all my thinking I am indeed inspired by Hegel and Husserl, but not in the way one could infer if such a statement were taken at face-value. In my reading of Kant I consider Hegel and Husserl as negative models precisely insofar as I want to steer away from what I think is their simplification of Kant s reason. At the same time, I believe their simplification is worth keeping well in mind because it highlights certain possible reductions that start surfacing (and partly are eventually realized) in the development of Kant s philosophy. Differently stated, I take their simplification, rather than as the result of an arbitrary or fanciful reading, as the onesided solution to a basic ambivalence regarding pure reason s powers on Kant s part. It was only well into the writing of my book that I realized that I was often trying to rebut the main gist of Hegel s reading of Kant. In fact, after I finished the book I wrote a essay on Hegel s critique of Kant intended to complement it in which I developed a thorough and detailed analysis of the reasons why Hegel is so unsympathetic in his take on Kant. 3 My intention was not that of defending Kant from Hegel s attack, but of showing the tacit presuppositions and bias at work in Hegel s reading which end up partly vitiating his criticisms. It is because I learned from Hegel the distinction between different modes of subjectivity, and in particular between reason and consciousness or finite I, that I came to see how he conflates these distinct terms in Kant and charges him with subjectivism. It is because I learned Estudos Kantianos, Marília, v. 5, n. 1, p. 435-440, Jan./Jun., 2017 435

FERRARIN, A. from Hegel the shortcomings of separation, the understanding s paramount procedure, that I came to see how he neglects the unity of reason in Kant and charges him with reducing it to the understanding, ignoring the distinction between style and content, i.e., between a dichotomic exposition and a fundamental unity to the subject-matter to analyze. It is because I learned from Hegel to value the Transcendental Dialectic and the difference between organism and aggregate that I find it disappointing that he should be so unfair in his assessment of reason s ideas (as opposed to the understanding s concepts) and neglect not only the Appendix to the Dialectic but above all the Doctrine of Method altogether (the Architectonic in particular being conspicuous in its absence). I could continue along these lines, but I should turn to Serena s question on Kant and phenomenology. Here, too, I would distance myself from Husserl s partial reading of Kant, which to me is in stark contrast with all that one can learn from phenomenology, beginning with the notion of intuition and the denounciation of a sterile opposition between discursive reason s regressive analysis and a blind sensibility. 4 Unlike Husserl who traces this opposition back to Kant, I find Husserl s discussion of its limits consonant with, indeed even inspiring for, my own study of intuition in Kant (from the notion of mathematical construction as a method that transcendental philosophy either strives to imitate or stay away from to the notion of exhibition in concreto [Darstellung] to the emphasis on the relative independence of intuition, which as many reviewers have correctly perceived puts me at odds with contemporary conceptualist readings). To be honest, however, I would hasten to point out that rather than the Sixth Logical Investigation, Ideas I or Experience and Judgment (or Heidegger s Logik. Die Frage nach der Wahrheit) texts I find important and brilliant the heart of this concern for me stems from years of study of the exegetical tradition of commentaries on Aristotle s intellect and of the history of imagination and mathematics. Incidentally, Serena is right in finding a parallelism between Kant s reason as organism and the teleology stressed by Hegel in the Preface to the Phenomenology, except that regrettably, once again Hegel would not agree. Another sign of what I take to be a missed opportunity for a fair discussion of Kant s reason on Hegel s part is the fact that as he there defines reason as a purposive activity (ein zweckmässiges Tun) he ascribes this thought to Aristotle in contrast with Kant s reason, which Hegel thinks is powerless and finite inasmuch as he has reduced it to the understanding. I find it instead difficult to see how Serena s suggestion to include Kant s notion of force as yet another way to highlight a purposive reason can be viable. In the First Metaphysical Principles of a Science of Nature Kant uses force in the Mechanics to denote corporeal nature, after the discussion of attractive and repulsive forces in matter in the Dynamics. If force is invoked to explain external causality in material movement, there cannot be any purpose or teleology to it. Unlike desire, impulse and ends, force can hardly lend itself to an analogy with reason as organism and spontaneous and free activity. On the other hand I do not find it problematic to safeguard freedom if reason is intrinsically and necessarily embodied. Freedom is a stratified concept in Kant and has several 436 Estudos Kantianos, Marília, v. 5, n. 1, p. 435-440, Jan./Jun., 2017

meanings, but it never pertains, even in its moral sense, to an incorporeal mind or a separate cogito. Let me now come to the main point raised by Serena in the latter part of her discussion, the continuity between the regulative idea of reason in the first Critique and the teleological power of judgment in the third. I would certainly agree that unity of nature and unity of reason are intimately related, even though I am not sure we can speak of a logical necessity or objective validity to the rational idea of a unity of nature. What complicates the issue considerably is that the unity of nature and of the world are distinct, and while the former, qua necessary conformity to laws (natura formaliter spectata), is the product of the understanding (Prolegomena 16-17, KrV B 165), only for the world is the rational idea an indispensable guidance. This is not to downplay Kant s groundbreaking notion that even empirical laws and a criterion of empirical truth are impossible without ideas, as he writes in the Appendix to the Dialectic, but it does tell us that in nature as a thoroughgoing unity of appearances in conformity to laws the systematic unity is that of the understanding with its rules, not of reason with its ideas. If anything, the strength of reason s purposive activity in the Critique of Pure Reason lies in its complete independence of nature. Reason s teleology has nothing natural, and here lies the distance reason marks between itself and all organic model. This is why the paradigms of the architect building an edifice and of personality setting itself wholly unnatural ends integrate and correct the organic inspiration of Kant s description of reason. The lawful order of nature and the intelligible order of the world are as opposed as the understanding s rules for appearances are to the unconditional. Unlike the systematic unity of nature, reason aims at a purposive unity of things which satisfies the speculative and the practical interests of reason at once insofar as it assumes a supreme intelligence as the sole cause of the world, if in the idea only (KrV, A 687/B 715). If this shows that the plan of an ethico-theology figuring prominently in the third Critique is by no means a late concern for Kant, it also must be added that this picture holds only up to a point. The third Critique brings to light many new themes, and as certain issues are redefined, certain others are more or less abandoned as the idea of a system of transcendental philosophy is recast over the years. In my book, especially in Chapter Three, I have followed this complex transformation, the more relevant (or, better, pertinent to Serena s discussion) aspects of which amount to this: In the third Critique purposiveness acquires central stage and becomes the a priori principle of reflection, itself guiding the search for systematic unity. Here the concept of a system of nature has no longer to do with either the understanding or reason but is the transcendental principle of the power of judgment, the new faculty intermediate between them. Systematicity is subordinated to formal purposiveness as one of its aspects, and reason s idea of totality is now subordinated to reflective judgment. In this new light, purposiveness comes to guide the search for systematic unity, so that the several heuristic principles guiding empirical sciences that the Appendix to the Transcendental Dialectic called the laws of homogeneity, specification, and continuity (KrV A 657-58) are no longer reason s regulative ideas but become the transcendental expression of the power of judgment facing a now particular and contingent nature replete with heterogeneous forms. Estudos Kantianos, Marília, v. 5, n. 1, p. 435-440, Jan./Jun., 2017 437

FERRARIN, A. Naturally this complete transformation of the architectonic of reason s faculties upsets the general architectonic of 1781, and definitely it is hardly a misunderstanding we can blame Hegel or others for. In this sense I said at the beginning that Hegel s simplification is not a complete invention on his part, for in the third Critique Kant forgets the positive character of ideas of the first Critique and tends to dismiss its Transcendental Dialectic and Doctrine of Method much as Hegel thought. In turn, this is not itself Kant s last word, because in the Fortschritte the backbone of the Transcendental Analytic of the first Critique will be directive again, and in the Opus Postumum the ideas of God and world will return as a distinct pair in all its importance. However it may be, this shows how radically Kant has changed the tenets of his system. And this shows the extent to which I think Serena is justified in taking the teleological power of judgment as an expression of the more general teleological nature of reason itself. Bibliography FERRARIN, Alfredo MAGRÌ, Elisa MANCA, Danilo (2015), Hegel e la fenomenologia trascendentale, Pisa: ETS. FERRARIN, Alfredo (2015 1 ), A Efetividade do pensar [transl. by F. Orsini], in Revista Opinião Filosófica 6:02, pp. 326-42. FERRARIN, Alfredo (2015 2 ), From the World to Philosophy, and Back, in BLOECHL, Jeffrey - DE WARREN, Nicolas, Phenomenology in a New Key. Essays in Honor of Richard Cobb-Stevens, Cham Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 63-92. FERRARIN, Alfredo (2016 1 ), Hegel and Husserl on the Emergence of the I out of Subjectivity, Hegel Bulletin 38:1, pp. 7-23. FERRARIN, Alfredo (2016 2 ), Reason in Kant and Hegel, Kant Yearbook. Kant and German Idealism 8, pp. 1-15. FERRARIN, Alfredo (2016 3 ), Il pensare e l io. Hegel e la critica di Kant, Roma: Carocci, Roma. FERRARIN, Alfredo (forthcoming), Hegel, Husserl and Imagination, in FERRARIN, Alfredo - MORAN, Dermot - MAGRÌ, Elisa - MANCA, Danilo, Hegel and the Phenomenological Movement, Cham-Dordrecht: Springer. GAVA, Gabriele (2015), Review to A. Ferrarin, The Powers of Reason, Studi Kantiani 28, pp. 177-182. NIETZSCHE, Friedrich (1988), Der Wille zur Macht, Fragment 419, in Friedrich Nietzsche. Sämtliche Werke, hrsg. v. G. Colli und M. Montinari, Berlin: De Gruyter. Note / Notes 1 Alfredo Ferrarin is Professor in theoretical philosophy at the State University of Pisa and was Assistant Professor at Boston University. He is author of many books and articles, mainly about Kant, but also about Hegel, Aristotle and Husserl. His latest publication is: Il pensare e l io. Hegel e la critica di Kant (Thinking and the I. Hegel s Critique of Kant), Carocci, Roma 2016. 2 See my essays Hegel and Husserl on the Emergence of the I out of Subjectivity (Ferrarin 2016 1 ) and Hegel, Husserl and Imagination (Ferrarin forthcoming), as well as the volume I co-edited with Elisa Magrì and Danilo Manca in Italian Hegel e la fenomenologia trascendentale, (Ferrarin Magrì - Manca 2015). 438 Estudos Kantianos, Marília, v. 5, n. 1, p. 435-440, Jan./Jun., 2017

3 The essay came to constitute the fifth chapter of my subsequent book on thinking and the I in Hegel (Ferrarin 2016 3, 171-239). For an excerpt in English, see my Reason in Kant and Hegel (Ferrarin 2016 2, pp. 1-15). For a brief overview in Portuguese, see my A Efetividade do pensar (Ferrarin 2015 1, pp. 326-42). 4 See my From the World to Philosophy, and Back, (Ferrarin 2015 2, pp. 63-92). Recebido / Received: 30.07.16 Aprovado / Approved: 04.12.16 Estudos Kantianos, Marília, v. 5, n. 1, p. 435-440, Jan./Jun., 2017 439