Matter and Consciousness

Similar documents
Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle

The Quest for Knowledge: A study of Descartes. Christopher Reynolds

Cartesian Dualism. I am not my body

What am I? An immaterial thing: the case for dualism

What do you think happens to you when you die? The answer always leads somewhere meaningful.

Many Minds are No Worse than One

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first.

Critical Realism and Reality

Against the Vagueness Argument TUOMAS E. TAHKO ABSTRACT

I Found You. Chapter 1. To Begin? Assumptions are peculiar things. Everybody has them, but very rarely does anyone want

Department of Philosophy TCD. Great Philosophers. Dennett. Tom Farrell. Department of Surgical Anatomy RCSI Department of Clinical Medicine RCSI

The nature of consciousness underlying existence William C. Treurniet and Paul Hamden, July, 2018

Is Innate Foreknowledge Possible to a Temporal God?

BonJour Against Materialism. Just an intellectual bandwagon?

Aristotle and the Soul

In his pithy pamphlet Free Will, Sam Harris. Defining free will away EDDY NAHMIAS ISN T ASKING FOR THE IMPOSSIBLE. reviews/harris

Philosophy of Mind (MIND) CTY Course Syllabus

VERIFICATION AND METAPHYSICS

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

Cartesian Dualism. I am not my body

Different kinds of naturalistic explanations of linguistic behaviour

Personal Identity and the Jehovah' s Witness View of the Resurrection

Hindu Paradigm of Evolution

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

Disclaimer. Copyright Notice

Reality. Abstract. Keywords: reality, meaning, realism, transcendence, context

Logical behaviourism

Wittgenstein s The First Person and Two-Dimensional Semantics

Searle vs. Chalmers Debate, 8/2005 with Death Monkey (Kevin Dolan)

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Dualism: What s at stake?

DISCUSSIONS WITH K. V. LAURIKAINEN (KVL)

From the waves to the ocean: how the discovery of deeper levels of our human being can help us to collaborate.

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 4 : I M M A T E R I A L I S M, D U A L I S M, & T H E M I N D - B O D Y P R O B L E M

Sounds of Love Series. Mysticism and Reason

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

Wittgenstein: Meaning and Representation

Louisiana Law Review. Cheney C. Joseph Jr. Louisiana State University Law Center. Volume 35 Number 5 Special Issue Repository Citation

A Graphical Representation of the Reconstructionist World-View (with a Mixture of Science Thrown in for Good Measure) by Ronald W. Satz, Ph.D.

Stephen Mumford Metaphysics: A Very Short Introduction Oxford University Press, Oxford ISBN: $ pages.

9 Knowledge-Based Systems

Neurophilosophy and free will VI

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

Resolutio of Idealism into Atheism in Fichte

William Meehan Essay on Spinoza s psychology.

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

What I am is what I am, Are you what you are, Or what?

Magic, semantics, and Putnam s vat brains

Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness

TEACHER NOTES GOING DEEPER SESSION 6: APPLYING THE WORD. Devotional Accountability:

Debate on the mind and scientific method (continued again) on

Behavior and Other Minds: A Response to Functionalists

A Cartesian critique of the artificial intelligence

Realism and instrumentalism

The Ontological Argument

A-LEVEL Religious Studies

Time, Self and Mind (ATS1835) Introduc;on to Philosophy B Semester 2, Dr Ron Gallagher Week 5: Can Machines Think?


Can machines think? Machines, who think. Are we machines? If so, then machines can think too. We compute since 1651.

Written by Rupert Sheldrake, Ph.D. Sunday, 01 September :00 - Last Updated Wednesday, 18 March :31

Reading Euthyphro Plato as a literary artist

The Self and Other Minds

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

Nancey Murphy, Bodies and Souls, or Spirited Bodies? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006). Pp. x Hbk, Pbk.

Examining the nature of mind. Michael Daniels. A review of Understanding Consciousness by Max Velmans (Routledge, 2000).

Mind s Eye Idea Object

Consciousness might be defined as the perceiver of mental phenomena. We might say that there are no differences between one perceiver and another, as

Please remember to sign-in by scanning your badge Department of Psychiatry Grand Rounds

STANISŁAW BRZOZOWSKI S CRITICAL HERMENEUTICS

The British Empiricism

Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work on

Engaging God Pathway of relationship that leads to deeper intimacy with God Flowing from inside out - heaven to our gateways of spirit, soul, body to

Rationality in Action. By John Searle. Cambridge: MIT Press, pages, ISBN Hardback $35.00.

Unit 3: Philosophy as Theoretical Rationality

Phenomenal Knowledge, Dualism, and Dreams Jesse Butler, University of Central Arkansas

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics

Mind and Body. Is mental really material?"

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

Written by Debbie Shapiro Saturday, 01 December :00 - Last Updated Thursday, 26 February :29

Lecture 38 CARTESIAN THEORY OF MIND REVISITED Overview. Key words: Cartesian Mind, Thought, Understanding, Computationality, and Noncomputationality.

Rudolf Steiner s The Philosophy of Freedom. A Few Examples of Exercises for individuals and groups which are Implicit in

EMPIRICISM & EMPIRICAL PHILOSOPHY

Lecture 8 Property Dualism. Frank Jackson Epiphenomenal Qualia and What Mary Didn t Know

someone who was willing to question even what seemed to be the most basic ideas in a

1/12. The A Paralogisms

SWINBURNE ON SUBSTANCE DUALISM

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

Concepts of God: Yielding to Love pages 24-27

FOREWORD: ADDRESSING THE HARD PROBLEM OF CONSCIOUSNESS

Session One: Identity Theory And Why It Won t Work Marianne Talbot University of Oxford 26/27th November 2011

Class #13 - The Consciousness Theory of the Self Locke, The Prince and the Cobbler Reid, Of Mr. Locke's Account of Our Personal Identity

On the Problem of Human Dignity

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

Philosophy 1100 Introduction to Ethics. Lecture 3 Survival of Death?

Rationalist-Irrationalist Dialectic in Buddhism:

Transcription:

Matter and Consciousness I want to use figures used in the experiments by Shepard and Metzlar to clarify a couple of really simple, but invariably very confusing distinctions about mind and matter. Shepard and Metzlar showed subjects pairs of figures like those below and asked people whether the two solid shapes depicted were the same, or mirror images of each other, by mentally rotating one so that they could see the two side by side. (Try it!) The surprising thing about the experiment was that the time taken to solve the problem reflected the magnitude of the angular and linear moves required, as if they were real solid objects. But that is not our concern here. Now I want to ask you, the solid objects which you manipulated in your imagination, are they material? If you say yes I would be asking what you mean by material and if these mental objects (which are not even images of really existing objects) are material, then what in your way of speaking is not material? If you were to answer everything is material, then all you have done is transformed material into a meaningless word. So the claim that they are material is equally meaningless. No, if we are going to use the word material in a meaningful way, then we have to indicate by it some distinction, some property of things which they may or may not have, or at least have in a great or lesser measure. (But to say your mental images are partly material would hardly be satisfactory, would it? ) Perhaps you will argue that the mental objects are material because they are the product of a material process, namely, the activity of a human brain. There is no doubt that the human brain is a material object if has a weight and a volume and a location in space and is connected by gravity, radiation and other natural processes to every other material object in the universe. Likewise, all the processes taking place in the brain are also material processes, obedient to all the laws of biology and physics and instantiated in the movement of material objects albeit very small ones. But to be the product of a material process is not the same as to be a material object or process. Now, I am not talking about material or matter in the sense the word is used in modern physics, as distinct from wave. I am interested in material as a philosophical category. Waves or particles, all natural processes, I take to be material. So let s turn the question around: what could I mean by material and not material? I mean by material everything that is outside of my consciousness. That seems to be the wrong way around, defining matter relative to consciousness, and my consciousness, to boot. But it makes sense. Whatever may have caused me to have a thought, my consciousness is the only starting point I have for any act of thought I do. If I were to

start with the material world, and then define consciousness, for example, as derivative of material processes, and subject to its laws, not only would I be faced with explaining how consciousness manifests Free Will in apparent defiance of natural law, but I would have made no progress in explaining conscious awareness, the essential property of consciousness which makes it possible to even discuss it. The important thing is to know the difference between what is just in my mind and what really exists outside of my mind, independently of my consciousness. So, sure, matter, the material world is always the important thing, it is what we want to know about, but for that very reason, I have to be able to distinguish between what only exists in my consciousness, and what exists outside of my consciousness, that is, the material world. What marks something as material is that it is interconnected with every other material thing in the universe. That is the central property of matter that is not a property of my consciousness. But those objects, the Shepard-Metzlar blocks I am rotating in my mind, are not material, they are not subject to the laws of mechanics, despite discoveries of Shepard and Metzlar which showed how our ability to manipulate them in our mind was still tied to our experience with moving material objects around. Being interconnected and existing outside of my consciousness, matter moves and changes in ways which we have found to be regular and even predictable, and through Natural Science, it has been possible to get to know these regularities, called laws of Nature. The objects in my mind are not bound by the laws of Nature I can think anything I wish to. All other objects, all material objects are. Let s just clear up some difficult questions which arise from this. Are unicorns material objects? For that matter, are Mr. Henchard, Father Christmas and God. Yes, all these are material, in the precise sense that they exist independently of my mind; I didn t make them up, I learnt about them from other people. But there aren t any horses with pointy horns running around anywhere and there never were. Unicorns do not exist, they are not real. All these kind of things are ideals, that is to say, they exist only in and through the actions of people who give reality to them through their actions. Like Melbourne University or the price of a cinema ticket. These are material things whose existence is only implicit in human activity. But they are not mental, they are not phantoms or illusions or dreams I am experiencing. They are material. Some ideals have a more substantial basis in reality than others, but they are all material. What I m thinking at the moment; that is not material. But as soon as I say a word, or make a gesture or produce a trace on a brain scan betraying this thought these actions do exist, they are material, and as material things they give both you and me the opportunity to see something of what I was thinking. It is a very limited class of things which are not material just those things which exist only in my mind. So what about your thoughts? This is where it gets tricky. Being material or not is actually relational. From my point of view your thoughts are material. If I want to understand your actions, then I absolutely have to take account of your consciousness, what may have motivated you to do this or that; I have to take account of your past experience, your prejudices, and so on, which has formed your consciousness. I have to have a theory of mind. And in that respect, I have to go on the theory that your

consciousness is the product of material processes, and inasmuch as it is responsible for further actions by you, continues to be part of a material process, your activity. If I m on the jury and you re accused of a murder, I take into account your lousy upbringing, your failure to understand certain social norms and so on. I may come to the view that you ought to be given a minimum sentence because of extenuating circumstances. But in treating you like that, as just part of a chain of cause and effect, for all my honourable intentions, I am actually de-humanising you. I am denying your free will, your moral responsibility for your actions. I am putting myself on a higher level and you on a lower level. And if you are a human being you will not be extending to yourself those extenuating circumstances. You will take moral responsibility for your actions and not simply ascribe them their causes. So by taking the world as being material, but setting my own thoughts aside as not material, I am not setting up a dualist world. Everything outside my own consciousness is interconnected and material, and in that very strong sense unitary. But I cannot take my own thoughts in the same way. I cannot step out of my mind and look at it as if it were under the microscope. My thoughts are not caused by my experiences, even though my experiences are the basis for my thinking. I cannot regard my thoughts and therefore my actions as simply the effects of material causes, that is to say, the effects of processes outside of my consciousness (even though you may think so!) because I still have to decide on every action I take and I can be capricious. But if I understand the world well, then indeed I will have no choice; I will know what I have to do, but I still have to decide to do it. But also, my thoughts are nothing like the material processes which led me to them. The images I have of those Shepard/Metzlar figures are nothing like a bunch of neurons. If you ask me what I am thinking now, I am not going to give you a description of the relevant neuronal activity and indeed I could not, and nor could anyone else! The blocks I have in my mind have no neurons in them, any more than an image of me in the mirror weighs 85 kg or has any weight at all for that matter. I may have a location in mind for these blocks (for example, in my hand 500cm in front of my eyes), but they are not there in my hands. Just as when my cat looks behind the mirror to find the other cat, he is surprised to find nothing there. And the images are not located in my head either, any more than a mirror image is located in the mirror. We cannot mix up the reflecting device with the image it produces. No, these images simply do not have a location. This relation between the mental and the material, between what is in my mind and what exists outside of my mind, between mind and matter, is an ontological relationship. It is a necessary premise for a theory of knowledge, recognising that the thinker, or subject, is an individual human being, who can know the world only by means of his thinking body. But it is not in itself a theory of knowledge. It sets up the basis for scepticism, for a rational and sceptical attitude to the world. Unless I recognise that my thoughts are just thoughts, and I enquire into what basis they have in the world outside my mind, unless I recognise that the laws governing the behaviour of material processes may have little relation to my ideas of them, and start from what I find has a firm basis in the material world and not what I find inside my head, then there can be no science.

Now, a lot of confusion arises from the conviction that such a sharp division, such a dichotomy between the mental and the material, just has to be wrong. Even if the world beyond my own consciousness is all one, it is still a dualism. There can t be such a sharp line between the mental and the material! After all, everything in my consciousness arose through material processes, both physiological and behavioural (through experience). How can I say that there is one room out here in the material world, and another room there in my mind, etc.? That is a dualism! Duplicate worlds, one inside the head and one outside. Surely this is the most naïve and outrageous dualism! No, no, no. I am not saying this at all. The ontological relation I put forward, takes account of the fact that I am a thinking human being, and draws a line between my ideas and the material world as a whole. The epistemological problem of the relation between what I take a certain process or object to be and what it is in itself, so to speak, that is to say, the subject-object relation, is a different matter entirely. Vygotsky (1928) cites the Danish philosophy Høffding: We must not mix up the relation between subject and object with the relation between mind and body, as Høffding splendidly explains. The distinction between mind and matter is a distinction in the content of our knowledge. But the distinction between subject and object manifests itself independently from the content of our knowledge. Both mind and body are for us objective, but whereas mental objects are by their nature related to the knowing subject, the body exists only as an object for us. The relation between subject and object is an epistemological problem, the relation between mind and matter is an ontological problem. The subject-object relation is not a dichotomy. The conception of subject and object is that of a relation between two material systems (be they human beings, organisations, a camera or even a computer) interacting with one another, each reflecting properties of the other within its own system of activity, each interpenetrating and constituting one another. The subject-object relation is not primarily about individuals, but rather about systems of activity by means of which we all come to know the world. It expresses the epistemological problem. My idea of the thing is indeed just an idea and not a material thing. But the epistemological problem is that there is no sharp line between what I take that thing to be, and what it is in itself, or what someone else takes it to be, for that matter. In the process of investigating something, we peel off the layers of the onion, so to speak; our first impression is replaced by a different view which is in turn replaced by a still deeper view. Equally, there are many points of view about any given object, and we don t claim that there some real material object out there somewhere which belongs to a different realm of reality. No! The epistemological problem is not that of the distinction between mind and matter, but how very object is constituted by a multiplicity of different forms of activity in relation to it, a multiplicity of subjects, each constituting an object uniquely for itself. What is objective, that is to say, beyond any particular stance, which transcends all difference, is ultimately only the materiality of the object, that the object is part of the material world, and all its processes. But that may not tell us very much. In connection

with the life of a given community, that is objective which is not subject to transformation by that community. But in general, that is not very much. Every concept we have is in some degree objective and in some degree subjective; nothing material is just subjective. Every idea or theory we come across has some basis in the material world, is to some degree objective. But equally no idea or theory or conception is completely objective, completely free of a subjective component. So all the work of science takes place in respect to the subject-object relation, continuously transforming what was unknown into something known and malleable to our purposes, discovering behind appearances what something really is, its essence, and again, discovering that essence to be nothing but an appearance. But at each end of this epistemological process is the ontological position. That the subject is a thinking individual, and that all the processes of the natural world are an interconnected whole, a material world, which goes on independently of us. Andy Blunden, January 2015