Ajdukiewicz on analyticity

Similar documents
Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010).

Katarzyna Gan Krzywoszyńska. Piotr Leśniewski. Archives Poincaré University of Nancy 2 France

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

BOOK REVIEWS. About a new solution to the problem of future contingents

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

TRUTH-MAKERS AND CONVENTION T

Overview. Is there a priori knowledge? No: Mill, Quine. Is there synthetic a priori knowledge? Yes: faculty of a priori intuition (Rationalism, Kant)

Alan W. Richardson s Carnap s Construction of the World

Predicate logic. Miguel Palomino Dpto. Sistemas Informáticos y Computación (UCM) Madrid Spain

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

ON QUINE, ANALYTICITY, AND MEANING Wylie Breckenridge

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

145 Philosophy of Science

Necessity and Truth Makers

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

FROM THE ACT OF JUDGING TO THE SENTENCE

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

Varieties of Apriority

1. Lukasiewicz s Logic

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

TABLE OF CONTENTS. Comments on Bibliography and References

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Inductive Inference, Rationality and Pragmatism: Peirce and Ajdukiewicz

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

1/12. The A Paralogisms

SYNTHESE LIBRARY MONOGRAPHS ON EPISTEMOLOGY, LOGIC, METHODOLOGY, PHILOSOPHY OF SCIBNCE, SOCIOLOGY OF SCIENCE AND OF KNOWLEDGE,

semantic-extensional interpretation that happens to satisfy all the axioms.

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

Phil/Ling 375: Meaning and Mind [Handout #10]

An Introduction to. Formal Logic. Second edition. Peter Smith, February 27, 2019

PHI2391: Logical Empiricism I 8.0

Definite Descriptions and the Argument from Inference

1/9. The First Analogy

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

A Generalization of Hume s Thesis

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Class 4 - The Myth of the Given

Tuomas E. Tahko (University of Helsinki)

Dumitrescu Bogdan Andrei - The incompatibility of analytic statements with Quine s universal revisability

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

TYPES, TABLEAUS, AND GODEL' S GOD

Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

Analytic Philosophy IUC Dubrovnik,

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT David Hume: The Origin of Our Ideas and Skepticism about Causal Reasoning

DEFINING ONTOLOGICAL CATEGORIES IN AN EXPANSION OF BELIEF DYNAMICS

PHILOSOPHICAL RAMIFICATIONS: THEORY, EXPERIMENT, & EMPIRICAL TRUTH

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Analyticity, Reductionism, and Semantic Holism. The verification theory is an empirical theory of meaning which asserts that the meaning of a

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

1 Why should you care about metametaphysics?

The distinction between truth-functional and non-truth-functional logical and linguistic

Chadwick Prize Winner: Christian Michel THE LIAR PARADOX OUTSIDE-IN

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice

Putnam on Methods of Inquiry

Supplementary Section 6S.7

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

Gary Ebbs, Carnap, Quine, and Putnam on Methods of Inquiry, Cambridge. University Press, 2017, 278pp., $99.99 (hbk), ISBN

Carnap s notion of analyticity and the two wings of analytic philosophy. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle

Intersubstitutivity Principles and the Generalization Function of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh. Shawn Standefer University of Melbourne

The Appeal to Reason. Introductory Logic pt. 1

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Chapter Summaries: A Christian View of Men and Things by Clark, Chapter 1

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Theory of Knowledge. 5. That which can be asserted without evidence can be dismissed without evidence. (Christopher Hitchens). Do you agree?

Intuitive evidence and formal evidence in proof-formation

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence

A Judgmental Formulation of Modal Logic

WHAT IS HUME S FORK? Certainty does not exist in science.

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome

Alternative Conceptual Schemes and a Non-Kantian Scheme-Content Dualism

Metaphysical Problems and Methods

Ayer and the Vienna Circle

Wittgenstein s Logical Atomism. Seminar 8 PHIL2120 Topics in Analytic Philosophy 16 November 2012

Response to The Problem of the Question About Animal Ethics by Michal Piekarski

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

Transcription:

Stud East Eur Thought (2016) 68:5 10 DOI 10.1007/s11212-016-9243-z Ajdukiewicz on analyticity Jan Woleński 1 Published online: 16 February 2016 The Author(s) 2016. This article is published with open access at Springerlink.com Abstract This paper presents the development of Ajdukiewicz s conception of analytic sentences. Starting from his pre-war radical conventionalism, the presentation proceeds to Ajdukiewicz s moderate aposteriorism and, finally, to radical aposteriorism. Various accounts of analyticity by Ajdukiewicz are mentioned and briefly commented on. At the end of the paper, Ajdukiewicz s influence on Polish philosophy in regard to the issue of analyticity is pointed out. Keywords Epistemology Analytic sentences Synthetic sentences A priori A posteriori Meaning rules In the works he published in the interwar period Kazimierz Ajdukiewicz did not use the label analytic sentence (proposition, etc.). On the other hand, we can associate analyticity with his theory of meaning as an essential part of radical conventionalism. According to Ajdukiewicz, (see Ajdukiewicz 1934a, b) the meaning of expressions determines so-called meaning rules (meaning directive). These rules dictate acts of assertion of propositions by the users of a given language. We have three distinct kinds of such directives. Firstly, there are axiomatic meaning rules, which require the unconditional assertion of sentences (I will use the term sentence and propositions as equivalent). For example, an axiomatic rule forces assertion of the sentence a = a. Secondly, if someone asserts the proposition b = a on the basis of previously asserting the proposition a = b, he or she appeals to a deductive directive. Thirdly, the assertion of the sentence London is the capital of the UK depends on the fact that London is the capital of England and being conscious of that fact. This situation is organized by an empirical meaning rule falling under the scheme a sentence A should be asserted in empirical & Jan Woleński wolenski@if.uj.edu.pl 1 Kraków, Poland

6 J. Woleński circumstances E. In perfect scientific languages (I omit details of their definition), not only does meaning determine meaning rules, but the reverse dependence holds as well: the directives define meaning. In other words, in such languages we have parity between meaning and meaning rules. A simple way to define analytic sentences in the context of meaning rules consists in saying that they are asserted on the basis of axiomatic and deductive meaning rules. Why did Ajdukiewicz avoid the label analytic proposition? His attitude in this respect seems surprising, because he was very well versed in Kant s philosophy and debates around the foundations of mathematics in the years 1900 1930; the problem of analyticity played a crucial role in both cases. Ajdukiewicz s actual reason to stay away from the term analytic proposition was probably a consequence of his general conventionalist position. Poincaré, the master of conventionalism, did not attach a special importance to analytic sentences. Roughly speaking, to qualify conventions as analytic propositions adds nothing particularly interesting to the way the former function in science. Moreover, Ajdukiewicz thought that the world-picture could always be changed by adopting a new language framework. This point of radical conventionalism is at odds with the view that analytic sentences are stable elements of every language and should be unconditionally protected against abandonment by science. These remarks about Ajdukiewicz s motives are merely guesses. In fact, to regard sentences as asserted on the basis of axiomatic and deductive rules as analytic appears quite natural. Ajdukiewicz himself supported such treatment in (Ajdukiewicz 1947: 173/174) and in his polemics with Adam Schaff (see Ajdukiewicz 1953: 161). 1 However, this change came after he had recognized the significance of the problem of analyticity. Anyway, irrespective of whether we qualify sentences asserted via axiomatic and deductive meaning rule as analytic, at least one idea remains constant during Ajdukiewicz s academic career: he always explicitly connected the problem of analyticity with the epistemological question about the sources of knowledge. Perhaps it is significant to some extent that Ajdukiewicz sometimes tried to eliminate the category of empirical meaning rules by reducing them to axiomatic and deductive directives. This move can be interpreted as a step towards a kind of apriorism. As far as I know, Ajdukiewicz s first substantial appeal to the concept of analyticity appears in (Ajdukiewicz 1946: 12). He writes: One must admit that logical empiricists did not provide a proof that every a priori proposition has to be analytic (in Kant s sense), and, thereby, that such a proposition is an expression of the linguistic usage. I think, however, that it would not be very difficult to come up with such a proof. A more adequate clarification of the concept of analytic proposition is required to perform this task. This passage should be carefully interpreted. One possible reading points out that Ajdukiewicz is close to the co-called moderate methodological empiricism (the view defended by logical empiricism), that is, the position according to which 1 Page-references are to translations or reprints, if they are listed in references at the end of this paper.

Ajdukiewicz on analyticity 7 human knowledge consists of synthetic a posteriori propositions (empirical science) and analytic propositions (logic and mathematics). Consequently, synthetic a priori sentences do not exist. The second reading implies that Ajdukiewicz considers the proof that synthetic apriora do not exist as based on a better elucidation of analyticity, but abstains from deciding whether the analysis based on a new concept of analytic sentence should be regarded as ultimate or even satisfactory to some extent. In any case, looking at the quoted passage from the perspective of Ajdukiewicz s later philosophy, it seems that he was much closer to moderate empiricism in the 1930s. Ajdukiewicz (1947) offers an interesting classification of possible views concerning the methodological controversy over the sources of knowledge. He distinguishes (see also Chapter 3 in Ajdukiewicz 1949): (a) radical apriorism (methodological rationalism) (Plato); (b) moderate apriorism (methodological rationalism) (Kant); (c) radical aposteriorism (methodological empiricism) (Mill); (d) moderate aposteriorism (methodological empiricism) (logical empiricism). This classification correlates these epistemological standpoints with the kinds of sentences present (legitimate) in knowledge (see also Nowaczyk 1979). Ajdukiewicz uses Kant s division of propositions: analytic (they are always a priori), synthetic a priori, and synthetic a posteriori. Ajdukiewicz explicitly defines analytic sentences (Ajdukiewicz 1973: 173/174) as the axioms of the language in question, that is, accepted via axiomatic rules or those which are inferred from the axioms. He adds (1973: 174): Such a definition of [analytic] sentences seems to be a better expression of the intention which induced Kant to introduce the notion of analytic sentences than his own which, as is well known, can be applied only to affirmative subjectpredicate sentences, and which is, therefore, not general enough. It also seems that the above definition of the term analytic sentence is more in accord with Kant s intentions than the somewhat different definition proposed by Carnap. It is plausible to think that the definition presented in this passage is the one that Ajdukiewicz had in mind in 1946. Although Ajdukiewicz points out a discord with Carnap (probably taking into account the purely syntactic definition of analyticity in Carnap s Logical Syntax of Language), both philosophers shared the view that analytic sentences require no appeal to experience for their acceptance The correlation between epistemological views and kinds of sentences present in knowledge is the following: radical apriorism sentences a priori (analytic, synthetic a priori); moderate apriorism all kinds of sentences (analytic, synthetic a priori, radical aposteriorism synthetic a posteriori; moderate aposteriorism analytic (logic and mathematics), synthetic a posteriori (empirical science). This account is very effective. It shows (among other thing) that the real battle between apriorism and aposteriorism concerns synthetic a priori propositions and analytic sentences inside the empiricist camp. Moreover, radical apriorism (in particular, Plato s case) makes a distinction between demonstrative knowledge and intuitive knowledge. In Ajdukiewicz s scheme, the latter finds its proper expression

8 J. Woleński in synthetic a priori propositions, but the former in analytic sentences. Ajdukiewicz s own view consisted in a certain compromise between moderate and radical apriorism. On the one hand, he considers the category of analytic sentences as fairly significant for epistemology, but he rejects the view that such sentences have nothing to do with experience. The second point concerns the role of logic in science. For Ajdukiewicz, logical theorems act as auxiliary hypotheses connected with the empirical theories. This means that they are accepted or rejected together with genuine empirical hypotheses. This account explains why analytic sentences, in particular, logical rules, do not require a direct reference to experience for their assertion. However, it does not exclude an indirect appeal to experiential data. Ajdukiewicz formulates a kind of linguistic holism in this view. It bears explicit affinities with Quine s holistic approach to language. The main difference between both philosophers consists in the fact that Quine s view is global (holism applies to the entire language as a unit) and Ajdukiewicz s holism is local, that is, restricted to concrete theories. In other words, experience influences the whole language in Quine s case, but only its fragments in Ajdukiewicz s epistemological analysis. A slightly different approach is offered in Ajdukiewicz (1949). He defines analytic sentences as those explicating the meaning of their constituents and their logical consequences, and this approach is perhaps the closest to moderate empiricism in Carnap s sense (analytic sentences serve as meaning postulates). However, Ajdukiewicz thought that this explanation would be didactically optimal (Ajdukiewicz 1949 was conceived as a rather elementary textbook). Ajdukiewicz worked on the relation between analytic sentences and experience until the end of his life. He gradually moved towards more radical methodological empiricism (see Ajdukiewicz 1958, 1964b). This evolution also influenced his account of analyticity. In the former paper, he introduced two concepts of analytic sentences given by the definitions: (i) A is an analytic sentence in the semantic sense in a language L if and only if A is a meaning postulate of L or A is a logical consequence of such postulates; (ii) A is an analytic sentence in the syntactic sense if and only if A is a logical truth (a truth invariant) under substitution of descriptive (extralogical) constituents occurring in A, or it is reducible to logical truth in virtue of the syntactic conventions of L. The second definition is influenced by the Bolzano-Tarski-Quine account of logical truth as being invariant under substitution of extralogical elements in sentences. As far as definition (i) is concerned, Ajdukiewicz probably followed Carnap s idea of meaning postulates and their logical consequences (Ajdukiewicz did not refer to Carnap in his paper). He understood syntactic conventions as rules of transformation of expressions. However, Ajdukiewicz introduced a novelty in his understanding of analyticity as compared with that of logical empiricism. Contrary to Carnap and other representatives of the Vienna Circle, Ajdukiewicz maintained that justification of analytic sentences sometimes requires an appeal to experience. In particular, it can happen that we need to check whether individual constants are not empty. This occurs in the case of the formula (a theorem of first-order logic): ð ÞFa! X xfx;

Ajdukiewicz on analyticity 9 which can be illustrated (Ajdukiewicz s own example) by the following case. Define Polyphemus as the tallest man whose height is over 100 m (Polyphemus = the tallest man whose height is over 100 m). This definition should be regarded as an analytic sentence. Using (*) we easily conclude that there is a person whose height is over 100 m. However, this conclusion is false and derived from the true analytic sentence. The example shows that we sometimes need to check empirical facts (in this case, the height of so defined Polyphemus) in order to justify our inferences. The paper (Ajdukiewicz 1964b) was published posthumously. In a sense, it can be considered as Ajdukiewicz s philosophical last will. He essentially radicalised his earlier empiricism. Returning to his early philosophy of language, Ajdukiewicz outlined a semantic project in which empirical meaning rules function as the only directives regulating the use of language. However, since Ajdukiewicz did not develop this idea, nothing more is known about how this task could be achieved. How influential was Ajdukiewicz s account of analyticity in Poland? At first, let me note that Ajdukiewicz s views on analyticity provoked some criticism (see Czerwiński 1964). The main argument against Ajdukiewicz points out that it is hard to consider the definition of Polyphemus as the tallest person whose height is over 100 m as a true analytic sentence. Since every individual constant has a fixed reference according to classical logic, the same concerns Polyphemus. Furthermore, the identity Polyphemus = the tallest man whose height is over 100 m does not need to be interpreted as analytic. Since it is false, there is nothing wrong about (*). Disregarding this criticism (its full treatment requires a closer analysis of how analyticity is related to various logics, for instance, to free logic, that is, logic without existential posits), all Polish authors dealing with this problem followed Ajdukiewicz and relativized analytic sentences to a language L. A more concrete influence can be summarized in the following way. Maria Kokoszyńska (see Kokoszyńska 1947) defined analytic sentences as analytic theorems of a language L or a negation of such a theorem. Roughly speaking, analytic sentences are generated by procedural rules similar to axiomatic and deductive meaning rules in Ajdukiewicz s sense. Borkowski (1966) distinguished three kinds of analytic sentences: (i) in the semantic sense, that is, true in all non-empty domains; (ii) in the syntactic sense, that is, derivable exclusively by logical inference rules; (iii) in the pragmatic sense, that is, asserted by axiomatic and deductive directives. Proposal (i) is a model-theoretic definition, (ii) is essentially Fregean, and (iii) uses concepts introduced by Ajdukiewicz. Przełęcki and Wójcicki (1977) developed the idea of analytic components of synthetic sentences (definitions, in particular) starting from Ajdukiewicz s observation that, in view of the problem of justification, the boundary between analytic and synthetic sentences is not absolutely sharp. Adam Nowaczyk used Ajdukiewicz s distinctions developed in (Ajdukiewicz 1958) in order to show that they offer a new perspective on analysing the old problem of apriorism. My own attempt (see Woleński 2004) continued the aforementioned ideas of Borkowski, but I supplemented his tripartite distinction by adding the categories of absolute and relative analytic sentence. Analytic sentences in the pragmatic sense (they are always relative) are a good area in which one can look for empirical foundations of analyticity. This brief survey shows that Ajdukiewicz s thoughts on the concept of analyticity were fairly productive in Poland. One might

10 J. Woleński even speak about a Polish conception of analytic sentences having the following main ingredients: a satisfactory definition of analytic sentences is possible; there are many kinds of analytic propositions; analytic sentences must be relativised to a language or/and perhaps logic; analytic sentences sometimes refer to experience; analytic sentences are not always tautologies; the category of analytic propositions is significant for epistemology. Open Access This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons license, and indicate if changes were made. References Ajdukiewicz, K. (1934a). Sprache und Sinn, Erkenntnis, IV: 100 138; Eng. tr. in Ajdukiewicz (1979: 35 66). Ajdukiewicz, K. (1934b). Das Weltbild und die Begriffsapparatur, Erkenntnis, IV: 259 287; Eng. tr. in Ajdukiewicz (1979: 69 87). Ajdukiewicz, K. (1946). O tzw. neopozytywizmie (On so-called neo-positivism), Myśl współczesna, II: 155 176; reprinted in Ajdukiewicz (1964: 9 33). Ajdukiewicz, K. (1947). Logika i doświadczenie (Logic and experience), Przegląd filozoficzny, XLIII: 3 22. Eng. tr. in Ajdukiewicz (1979: 165 181). Ajdukiewicz, K. (1949). Zagadnienia i kierunki filozofii (Warszawa: Czytelnik); Eng. tr., Ajdukiewicz (1973). Ajdukiewicz, K. (1953). W sprawie artykułu prof. A. Schaffa o moich poglądach filozoficznych (Reply to Professor Schaff s article concerning my philosophical views), Myśl filozoficzna, 2: 292 334; reprinted in Ajdukiewicz (1964: 155 191). Ajdukiewicz, K. (1958). Le problème du fondement des propositions analytiques, Studia logica, VIII: 259 272; Eng. tr. in Ajdukiewicz (1979: 254 268). Ajdukiewicz, K. (1964a). Język i poznanie ( Language and Knowledge ), v. II. Warszawa: Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe. Ajdukiewicz, K. (1964b). Zagadnienie empiryzmu a koncepcja znaczenia (The problem of empiricism and the concept of meaning). In Ajdukiewicz (1964: 388 400); Eng. tr. in Ajdukieweicz (1979: 306 319). Ajdukiewicz, K. (1973). Problems and theories of philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Ajdukiewicz, K. (1979). The scientific world perspective and other essays 1931 1965. Dordrecht: D. Reidel. Borkowski, L. (1966). Deductive foundations and analytic propositions. Studia Logica, XIX, 59 72. Czerwiński, Z. (1964). Zdania analityczne, logika i doświadczenie (Analytic sentences, logic and experience). In Rozprawy logiczne. Księga Pamiątkowa ku czci profesora Kazimierza Ajdukiewicza (Festschrtift in Honor of Professor Kazimierz Ajdukiewicz) (Warszawa: Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe), pp. 23 30. Kokoszyńska, M. (1947). O ró_znych rodzajach zdań (On various kinds of sentences ). Przegląd Filozoficzny, XLIII, 22 51. Nowaczyk, A. (1979). Analyticity and apriority. In J. Pelc (Ed.), Semiotics in Poland (pp. 464 483). Warszawa: PWN Polish Scientific Publishers. Przełęcki, M., & Wójcicki, R. (1977). The problem of analyticity. In M. Przełęcki & R. Wójcicki (Eds.), Twenty-five years of logical methodology in Poland (pp. 589 614). Warszawa: PWN Polish Scientific Publishers. Woleński, J. (2004). Analytic vs. synthetic and a priori vs. a posteriori. In I. Niiniluoto, M. Sintonen, & J. Woleński (Eds.), Handbook of epistemology (pp. 781 839). Dordrecht: Kluwer.