by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB

Similar documents
by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB

The Five Ways of St. Thomas in proving the existence of

The Divine Nature. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 3-11) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian J.

The Names of God. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 12-13) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006)

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

On Being and Essence (DE ENTE Et ESSENTIA)

270 Now that we have settled these issues, we should answer the first question [n.

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Aristotle and Aquinas

Chapter Six. Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality

Knowledge according to Bavinck and Aquinas

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII

What We Are: Our Metaphysical Nature & Moral Implications

The Trinity, The Dogma, The Contradictions Part 2

Essays in Systematic Theology 45: The Structure of Systematic Theology 1

PART TWO EXISTENCE AND THE EXISTENT. D. The Existent

REVIEW. St. Thomas Aquinas. By RALPH MCINERNY. The University of Notre Dame Press 1982 (reprint of Twayne Publishers 1977). Pp $5.95.

Wisdom in Aristotle and Aquinas From Metaphysics to Mysticism Edmond Eh University of Saint Joseph, Macau

Anthony P. Andres. The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic. Anthony P. Andres

AQUINAS S FOURTH WAY: FROM GRADATIONS OF BEING

QUESTION 56. An Angel s Cognition of Immaterial Things

WHAT ARISTOTLE TAUGHT

QUESTION 44. The Procession of Creatures from God, and the First Cause of All Beings

general development of both renaissance and post renaissance philosophy up till today. It would

From Aristotle s Ousia to Ibn Sina s Jawhar

QUESTION 54. An Angel s Cognition

ACTA PHILOSOPHICA, vol. 8 (1999), fasc. 1/recensioni

Henry of Ghent on Divine Illumination

William Ockham on Universals

QUESTION 3. God s Simplicity

Questions on Book III of the De anima 1

SCHOOL ^\t. MENTAL CURE. Metaphysical Science, ;aphysical Text Book 749 TREMONT STREET, FOR STUDENT'S I.C6 BOSTON, MASS. Copy 1 BF 1272 BOSTON: AND

On the Relation of Philosophy to the Theology Conference Seward 11/24/98

Jewish and Muslim Thinkers in the Islamic World: Three Parallels. Peter Adamson (LMU Munich)

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination

The question is concerning truth and it is inquired first what truth is. Now

P. Weingartner, God s existence. Can it be proven? A logical commentary on the five ways of Thomas Aquinas, Ontos, Frankfurt Pp. 116.

QUESTION 45. The Mode of the Emanation of Things from the First Principle

Essays in Systematic Theology 17: Shorter Version of System Seeking Method: Reconciling System and History

The Unmoved Mover (Metaphysics )

Thomas Aquinas The Treatise on the Divine Nature

William Hasker s discussion of the Thomistic doctrine of the soul

The Five Ways. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Question 2) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006) Question 2. Does God Exist?

Thomas Aquinas on the World s Duration. Summa Theologiae Ia Q46: The Beginning of the Duration of Created Things

Thomas Aquinas The Treatise on the Divine Nature

Saint Thomas Aquinas Summa Theologiae Selections III Good and Evil Actions. ST I-II, Question 18, Article 1

THE PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE. jennifer ROSATO

QUESTION 55. The Medium of Angelic Cognition

First Treatise <Chapter 1. On the Eternity of Things>

Russell s Problems of Philosophy

On Truth Thomas Aquinas

Contemplating Procession: Thomas Aquinas Analogy of the Procession of the Word in the Immanent Divine Life

The Idea of God: On the Divine Names

QUESTION 90. The Initial Production of Man with respect to His Soul

Review of Aristotle on Knowledge and Learning: The Posterior Analytics by David Bronstein

KNOWLEDGE AND OPINION IN ARISTOTLE

Aristotle. Aristotle was an ancient Greek Philosopher who made contributions to logic, physics, the

The Bavinck Review Volume

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

SOME CONSEQUENCES OF MICHAEL THOMSON S LIFE AND ACTION FOR SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY SUPPLEMENTARY VOLUME LIFE AND ACTION IN ETHICS AND POLITICS ITALO TESTA

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things:

What Must There be to Account for Being?

Alexander of Hales, The Sum of Theology 1 (translated by Oleg Bychkov) Introduction, Question One On the discipline of theology

A Very Short Primer on St. Thomas Aquinas Account of the Various Virtues

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford.

out in his Three Dialogues and Principles of Human Knowledge, gives an argument specifically

QUESTION 87. How Our Intellect Has Cognition of Itself and of What Exists Within It

Prof Paul O Grady 16 th January, What is Wisdom?

PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE LET THOMAS AQUINAS TEACH IT. Joseph Kenny, O.P. St. Thomas Aquinas Priory Ibadan, Nigeria

On the Soul. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 75-76) by Thomas Aquinas (~1274 AD) translated by Robert Pasnau (2014)

God and Creation, Job 38:1-15

QUESTION 55. The Essence of a Virtue

Introduction: Discussion:

Alexander and Arius in Alexandria. Controversy Erupts. homoousios. Council of Nicea 325. A Battle At Night Positions Develop

St. Thomas quotes the opening lines of Avicenna s Metaphysics: ens and essentia are what is first conceived by the intellect. 2

Aquinas, Hylomorphism and the Human Soul

Self-Evidence in Finnis Natural Law Theory: A Reply to Sayers

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Augustine s famous story about his own theft of pears is perplexing to him at

The thought of St. Thomas Aquinas continues to exercise and fascinate. Aquinas Medalist s Address. Anthony Kenny

Plotinus and Aquinas on God. A thesis presented to. the faculty of. the College of Arts and Sciences of Ohio University. In partial fulfillment

McKenzie Study Center, an Institute of Gutenberg College. Handout 5 The Bible and the History of Ideas Teacher: John A. Jack Crabtree.

EUTHYPHRO, GOD S NATURE, AND THE QUESTION OF DIVINE ATTRIBUTES. An Analysis of the Very Complicated Doctrine of Divine Simplicity.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

The Five Ways THOMAS AQUINAS ( ) Thomas Aquinas: The five Ways

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

QUESTION 58. The Mode of an Angel s Cognition

ST. THOMAS AQUINAS SUMMA THEOLOGICA

The Human Soul of Christ. St. Augustine wrote that by Christ s joining of Himself to created nature there was

Robert Kiely Office Hours: Tuesday 1-3, Wednesday 1-3, and by appointment

IDOLATRY AND RELIGIOUS LANGUAGE

Peter L.P. Simpson January, 2015

Disputation 20. On the First Efficient Cause and on His First Action, Which Is Creation

Plato s Concept of Soul

A Comparative Study between St. Thomas Aquinas s Concept of Ipsum Esse Subsistens and the Concept of Qi in the Guanzi s Four Daoist Chapters CONTENTS

Philosophy of Nature, Philosophy of the Soul, Metaphysics

THE ESSENTIAL CONNECTION BETWEEN COMMON SENSE PHILOSOPHY AND LEADERSHIP EXCELLENCE

Aristotle and the Definition of Man

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

Aristotle on the Principle of Contradiction :

Transcription:

1 1Aristotle s Categories in St. Augustine by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB Because St. Augustine begins to talk about substance early in the De Trinitate (1, 1, 1), a notion which he later equates with essence in 1, 1, 4, before delving into what could be Augustine s understanding of substance or essence, one might begin with a look at St. Augustine s understanding of Aristotle s ten categories since substance ranks as one of these categories even as it is the first of these categories. A useful starting point presents itself in how St. Thomas Aquinas understood these categories because of the influence that Aristotle s Categories exercised on Aquinas s own mind. And so, when directly responding to a question which asks if the human mind receives knowledge from sensible things, Aquinas replies affirmatively when he argues that the senses play a vitally constitutive role when they apprehend properties which are to be identified as material coordinates. 1 More specifically, in Book 4 of the Summa Contra Gentiles (composed in 1264-65), Aquinas notes that sense grasps a thing in its exterior accidents, which are color, taste, quantity and others of this kind. 2 Through the exterior senses and from their derivative descriptions, one employs categories which are drawn from the world of sense experience in order to describe any object which comes within the range of one s experience. 3 As an apt example of this, Aristotle s logical treatise, the Ten Categories, accordingly lists ten attributes or predicamenta 4 (predicaments) which can be used to speak about anything which engages one s interest to become an object of scientific investigation. Substance denotes a subject or thing in terms of what exists in itself and not in another; it cannot be attributed to another subject or thing. It is an ens per se (a being by itself). 5 The other categories (denoted by quantity, quality, relation, action, passion, place, time, posture, and habit) are then used to speak about a thing which has been identified as a substance. These last nine categories either inhere or exist in a substance as a substance and are affirmed of it (for instance, the quantity and quality of a given thing given the matter and form of a given thing 6 ); or they refer to external causes and circumstances that should be noted in talking about any given 1 Aquinas, De Veritate, q. 10, a. 6, ad 2; 2, p. 29. 2 Aquinas, Summa Contra Gentiles, 4, 11, 15; 9, p. 86. 3 Bernard Lonergan, Insight: A Study of Human Understanding, eds. Frederick E. Crowe and Robert M. Doran (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1988), p. 420; Caring About Meaning: patterns in the life of Bernard Lonergan, eds. Pierrot Lambert, Charlotte Tansey, and Cathleen Going (Montreal: Thomas More Institute Papers, 1982), pp. 65-6. 4 Augustine, The Confessions of St. Augustine, trans. John K. Ryan (New York: Doubleday, 1960), p. 380, nn. 1-2 (hereafter cited as the Confessions followed by technical reference to the original, and if a translation has been used, by the volume and page of the English translation); Bernard Lonergan, Understanding and Being: The Halifax Lectures on Insight, eds. Elizabeth A. Morelli and Mark D. Morelli; rev and aug. by Frederick E. Crowe with the collaboration of Elizabeth A. Morelli, Mark D. Morelli, Robert M. Doran, and Thomas V. Daly (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2000), p. 8.. 5 Hardon, Substance, Modern Catholic Dictionary, p. 523. 6 Aquinas, Sententia super Metaphysicam, 5, 9, 892.

2 thing (as for instance, habit, time, and place). 7 These later properties come and go as accidents while the subject or thing to which they refer remains substantially the same. Some categories, however, refer to relations or connections which can exist between a substance and its external environment (as in the action and passion of a given substance: what a given substance does as a subject, and what it receives from as an object of activity coming from another source). In his Confessions, St. Augustine speaks of these categories in a way which reveals their descriptive heuristic character as this would be derived from an analysis of ordinary linguistic usage in terms on how subjects and verbs are related to each other. The book [The Ten Categories] seemed to me to speak clearly enough of substances, such as a man is, and of what are in them, such as a man s figure; of what quality he is; his stature; how many feet tall he is; his relationships, as whose brother he is; where he is placed; when he was born; whether he stands or sits; whether he is shod with shoes or armed; whether he does something or has something done to him; and the innumerable things that are found in these nine categories, of which I have set down some examples, or in the category of substance. 8 7 Aquinas, Sententia super Physicam, 3, 5, 322; Sententia super Metaphysicam, 5, 9, 889-894; Confessions, trans. Ryan, p. 380, n. 2. 8 Confessions, 4, 28; p. 110. In his Insight: A Study of Human Understanding, p. 420, Bernard Lonergan also speaks about Aristotle s ten categories or predicaments in a way which attests to their heuristic descriptive character. A naturalist will assign the genus, species, and instance (substance) of an animal, its size and weight (quantity), its color, shape, abilities, propensities (quality), its similarities to other animals and its differences from them (relation), its performance and susceptibilities (action and passion), its habitat and seasonal changes (place and time), its mode of motion and rest (posture), and its possession of such items as claws, talons, hooves, fur, feathers, horns (habit). Later, in his Understanding and Being, p. 199, Lonergan speaks about Aristotle s categories in the following terms: We arrive at Aristotle s categories most simply by going into the woods, meeting animals, and asking, What kind of an animal is this? How big is it? What is its color? What relations does it have? and so on. They are categories of descriptive knowledge, and descriptive knowledge is science in a preliminary stage. It is something entirely different from science that has reached its explanatory stage. Aristotle himself had a very clear idea of the difference between these descriptive categories, which he sets up in an elementary work, and causes; consequently, he thinks of science as knowledge through causes. However, there has been a tendency to conceive of metaphysics as knowledge, not through causes, but

3 Then, by applying this schema to the study of St. Augustine as a substantive being, as an autonomous subject, a combination of the following details emerges: Thus Augustine himself through the course of his life grew in size: an instance of the category of quantity. He acquired certain vicious habits that were in time replaced by virtues. He acquired great skill as a writer and great learning: virtues, vices, skill, and the like come under the heading of quality, as do colors and certain other aspects of our being. Augustine was taught by other men (passion) and he in turn instructed students (action). He existed at different moments (time) and in many places (place). He had countless relations with others; men and other things. He was a son, a brother, a father, a disciple, a master, a priest, and a bishop (relation). He was clothed in various ways and equipped with tools or armor at different times (habit, in the sense of wearing a monk s habit or a soldier s uniform). He assumed various positions, such as kneeling in prayer (posture). 9 However, as Aquinas argues, descriptive conjugates, which he refers to as external accidents [exteriorum accidentium], 10 do not reveal why a thing exists as it exists with the descriptive conjugates that it has. They fail to reveal a thing s inner essence or nature (its quiddity or whatness ): what a thing is with respect to its inherent intelligibility, its meaning or form, why it is what it is. When sense knows a thing through a form received from things, it does not know it as effectively as the intellect. Sense is led through it to a knowledge of external accidents but the intellect reaches to the essential quiddity of a thing. 11 In turning to Augustine s use of Aristotle s ten categories in his study of the Trinity elaborated in the De Trinitate, it is only in Book 5, chapter 2 that Augustine refers to Aristotle s ten categories but in a way which cannot be regarded as explicit or complete. In speaking about God, substance can be used as a meaningful category in order to refer to God as a distinct, subsistent through the predicaments. On the other hand, if one conceives metaphysics as concerned with the total heuristic structure of proportionate being [being defined as what of reality can be known by human acts of experiencing, understanding, and judging], one must be concerned with causes and not at all with predicaments, because a heuristic structure aims at what is known through understanding. In other words, while Aristotle s categories talk about being, they do not talk about the causes of being, and for any talk about causes, a more basic set of terms is needed. Cf. B. Lonergan, The Ontological and Psychological Constitution of Christ, trans. Michael G. Shields (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2001), p. 49. 9 Confessions, pp. 380-1, n. 2. 10 De Veritate, q. 10, a. 6, ad 2; 2, p. 29; Summa Contra Gentiles, 4, 11, 15. 11 De Veritate, q. 10, a. 6, ad 2; my translation. In the Summa Theologiae 2a-2ae, q. 8, a. 1 & ad 3; 3, p. 1198, Aquinas reiterates this thesis when he argues that sensitive knowledge is concerned with external sensible qualities while intellectual knowledge penetrates into the very essence of a thing.

4 reality. God is a distinct being or ousia who does not exist in some other kind of being. God possesses his own reality or existence. However, with respect to the other categories that can be used to talk about God, the other categories which are included in Aristotle s list can only be used in a suggestive or metaphorical way. God is not a datum of sense and so he cannot be talked about as if he possessed any external accidents which can be sensed by any of the human senses. Quoting early on from St. Augustine s De Trinitate, it is said that divinity cannot be seen by human sight in any way whatever. 12 Other means must be used. In terms of a deeper understanding of substance in Augustine, an Aristotelian notion of substance should be distinguished from a Thomist notion of it if we are to more fully appreciate the meaning that Augustine is probably working with. The key to a difference between an Aristotelian, Augustinian notion of substance and a Thomist notion of it lies early in the De Trinitate (1, 1, 4) where Augustine refers to substance in a way which is in apposition with essence. The two terms are used interchangeably although, admittedly, in his work, Augustine speaks more frequently about substance than essence. However, the apposition reveals an Aristotelian understanding of substance which emphasizes the primacy of form in understanding the being of any given thing. For Aristotle, being is form and form is being (cf. Aristotle, Metaphysics, 7, 17; Lonergan, Insight, pp. 390-1) since nothing exists apart from its specific determination through the agency of an active, intelligible principle which refers to the causality of a form. This form unites itself to what is able to receive it, and so some kind of passive principle is indicated. The result is a specific kind of being or thing, a specific kind of substance. A this rather than a that comes into existence. With respect to finite things which exist within the physical or material order of things, form causes being by giving being or reality to matter (cf. Aquinas s Sententia super Metaphysicam, cited in English as the Commentary on the Metaphysics of Aristotle, 5, 2, 775 which summarizes the Aristotelian position by simply saying that form gives being, and matter receives it ). Distinct beings or substances are brought into existence in a way which shows that essence is the same as substance since, in essence, a union of matter and form is what constitutes the existence of a particular kind of thing. 13 A human being, for instance, is a substance or thing that is composed of a human soul that is united with the matter which is needed if a human being is to exist. When speaking about matter in a generic way, Aristotle speaks about common matter since he wants to distinguish this type of matter from any specific matter which exists in an individual and unique way in a particular thing. Each of us has a distinct set of bones and flesh which is peculiar to ourselves and so our own bones and flesh refers to specific matter. But, the bones and flesh of any human being is what is meant by common matter. In Aristotle, only one explanatory principle accordingly accounts for the existence of things as a principle of activity, and this is the form of a given thing. This position is to be contrasted, however, with Aquinas s understanding of things since Aquinas postulated not one but two explanatory principles which are to be identified as causes or principles of activity: the principle of form, and the principle of act (which refers to an act of being or existence that confers reality on what had not existed and which is invoked to account for the existence of any contingent thing). 12 Augustine, De Trinitate, 1, 2, 11. 13 For a full explanation of the reasoning which led Aristotle to identify substances in terms of essences, see Michael Novak, A Key to Aristotle s Substance, Substances and Things: Aristotle s Doctrine of Physical Substance in Recent Essays, ed. M. L. O Hara (Washington, D.C.: University Press of America, 1982), pp. 188-208.

However, like Aquinas, Aristotle acknowledged the existence of separated substances which refer to things which do not exist in any kind of union with matter. These substances exist in a Platonic way: separately, as subsistent forms apart from matter. One might refer to them as instances of pure intelligibility, or as pure forms which possess a purely spiritual or intellectual nature. They can never be apprehended by any act of sense, although their purely spiritual or intellectual nature does not preclude the fact that they can be known by acts of understanding which, as acts of understanding, also possess a purely spiritual nature. Through acts of understanding which are joined to acts of faith and belief, one best moves toward apprehending the meaning of meanings in a way that can reveal something of the light or intelligibility which belongs to the inner life of God present within the Trinity. 5