Must we have self-evident knowledge if we know anything?

Similar documents
Topics and Posterior Analytics. Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey

First of all, I will describe what I mean when I use the terms regularity (R) and law of

Review of Aristotle on Knowledge and Learning: The Posterior Analytics by David Bronstein

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Critical Thinking 5.7 Validity in inductive, conductive, and abductive arguments

Review. Philosophy; Page 1 of The Royal Institute of Philosophy,

A Priori Bootstrapping

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Can a behaviourist admit that we have feelings or thoughts that we keep hidden?

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

WHAT IS HUME S FORK? Certainty does not exist in science.

Free will & divine foreknowledge

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT

Unit. Science and Hypothesis. Downloaded from Downloaded from Why Hypothesis? What is a Hypothesis?

PHI2391: Logical Empiricism I 8.0

Varieties of Apriority

PRACTICAL REASONING. Bart Streumer

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

The logic of the success/failure system

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

1/8. The Schematism. schema of empirical concepts, the schema of sensible concepts and the

The Principle of Sufficient Reason and Free Will

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

Epistemology. Diogenes: Master Cynic. The Ancient Greek Skeptics 4/6/2011. But is it really possible to claim knowledge of anything?

The Unbearable Lightness of Theory of Knowledge:

Henry of Ghent on Divine Illumination

It is not at all wise to draw a watertight

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo

Is the Identity of Indiscernibles refuted by Max Black's thought experiment? What is the Principle of Identity of Indiscernibles (PII)?

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER VI CONDITIONS OF IMMEDIATE INFERENCE

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER IX CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE

Hume. Hume the Empiricist. Judgments about the World. Impressions as Content of the Mind. The Problem of Induction & Knowledge of the External World

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2010

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

Introduction to Philosophy

Justified Inference. Ralph Wedgwood

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought

GREAT PHILOSOPHERS: Thomas Reid ( ) Peter West 25/09/18

Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work on

Self-Evidence in Finnis Natural Law Theory: A Reply to Sayers

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

1/8. Descartes 3: Proofs of the Existence of God

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Theory of Knowledge Series

An Inferentialist Conception of the A Priori. Ralph Wedgwood

Is there a distinction between a priori and a posteriori

From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy

ON THE TRUTH CONDITIONS OF INDICATIVE AND COUNTERFACTUAL CONDITIONALS Wylie Breckenridge

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

Consciousness might be defined as the perceiver of mental phenomena. We might say that there are no differences between one perceiver and another, as

CHAPTER THREE ON SEEING GOD THROUGH HIS IMAGE IMPRINTED IN OUR NATURAL POWERS

Logic and the Absolute: Platonic and Christian Views

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5

John Buridan on Essence and Existence

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

Revista Economică 66:3 (2014) THE USE OF INDUCTIVE, DEDUCTIVE OR ABDUCTIVE RESONING IN ECONOMICS

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Lecture 4.2 Aquinas Phil Religion TOPIC: Aquinas Cosmological Arguments for the existence of God. Critiques of Aquinas arguments.

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Nested Testimony, Nested Probability, and a Defense of Testimonial Reductionism Benjamin Bayer September 2, 2011

Business Research: Principles and Processes MGMT6791 Workshop 1A: The Nature of Research & Scientific Method

- 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance

Department of Philosophy. Module descriptions 2017/18. Level C (i.e. normally 1 st Yr.) Modules

MCQ IN TRADITIONAL LOGIC. 1. Logic is the science of A) Thought. B) Beauty. C) Mind. D) Goodness

Rationalist-Irrationalist Dialectic in Buddhism:

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

Basic Concepts and Skills!

FACULTY OF ARTS B.A. Part II Examination,

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori


DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON

I Don't Believe in God I Believe in Science

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Nozick and Scepticism (Weekly supervision essay; written February 16 th 2005)

The British Empiricism

CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to

Is rationality normative?

Aquinas' Third Way Modalized

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

Induction and Natural Necessity in the Middle Ages

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics


complete state of affairs and an infinite set of events in one go. Imagine the following scenarios:

LOGIC LECTURE #3: DEDUCTION AND INDUCTION. Source: A Concise Introduction to Logic, 11 th Ed. (Patrick Hurley, 2012)

Transcription:

1 Must we have self-evident knowledge if we know anything? Introduction In this essay, I will describe Aristotle's account of scientific knowledge as given in Posterior Analytics, before discussing some of the ways in which it might be criticised and defended, in order to show that self-evident knowledge is essential before anything can be known. Aristotle's account of knowledge A conventional definition of knowledge is justified true belief (Dancy 1985:23). Aristotle, in Posterior Analytics, talks about how we can formulate explanations, and so his definition of scientific knowledge requires not only justified true belief, but also understanding: We think we understand a thing... whenever we think we are aware both that the explanation because of which the object is is its explanation, and it is not possible for this to be otherwise (PoA 71b10). According to Aristotle, there are two ways in which we can acquire such knowledge. The simplest, and least controversial way, is to learn it, in which case All teaching and all intellectual learning come about from already existing knowledge (PoA 71a1). Learning is a process by which we combine knowledge that we already have in order to construct more elaborate or useful knowledge. In Prior Analytics, Aristotle lays down the principles of logical deduction, or demonstration by syllogism, using which one can advance from premises to conclusion, and it is this model

2 which he is alluding to here: he believes that by adhering to a strict set of rules, we can derive new knowledge (conclusions) from pre-existing knowledge (premises). If we accept this definition of learning, then it is obvious that it cannot be the only way that we acquire knowledge, for we must have something to start the whole process off: there must be some starting points of knowledge on top of which new knowledge can be built. Aristotle believes that these starting points of knowledge (archai) must be true and primitive and immediate and more familiar than and prior to and explanatory of the conclusion (PoA 71b21). By primitive, Aristotle means that there is no other knowledge from which it is derived (in other words, a starting point cannot be learned ); prior to and explanatory of the conclusion means that a conclusion relies on it, and immediate and more familiar is generally taken to mean that they are already known, or self-evident. If these starting points are not learned, then where do they come from? One possibility is that we have them inside us to start with: our knowledge of them is innate. Plato suggests that this is the case and that we simply need to be prompted to recollect them. But this view is discounted by Aristotle. He says of the starting points if we have them, it is absurd; for it results that we have pieces of knowledge more certain than demonstration and yet this escapes notice. But if we get them without having them earlier, how might we become familiar with them and learn them from no pre-existing knowledge (PoA 99b26). In other words, if they were innate, it would not be possible for us to be unconscious of them. Aristotle's explanation of this foundational knowledge is that we acquire it as a result of

3 the way that we perceive the world: from perception there comes memory... and from memory (when it occurs often in connection with the same thing), experience;... and from experience... a principle of skill and of understanding (PoA 104a). Aristotle is saying that by repeated exposure to a particular type of situation, we have a capacity for generalising the memories of all these events into a new piece of knowledge (which can subsequently be combined with other knowledge in the learning process). the mind is such as to be capable of undergoing this (PoA 113a). The term nous which is often translated as intuition is used by Aristotle to refer to the process by which this occurs. In contrast to learning, which is a deductive process that results in understanding through reasoning, we acquire foundational knowledge through an inductive process: once sufficient evidence has been observed, our minds can comprehend a general foundational truth. In contrast to Plato, who says that what we experience are shadows of pre-existing universals, Aristotle has us inferring universal concepts from the common features of a set of experiences. According to Aristotle then, it is necessarily true that anything we know is either selfevident knowledge (archai) or else something derived from it: we cannot know anything unless we have self-evident knowledge. Discussion Aristotle's position that without self-evident knowledge we cannot know anything seems open to challenge when we consider the way that I come to know things such as there is

4 a Beatles record playing on the radio at the moment. I haven't learned this knowledge by combining knowledge I already had, but does it count as self-evident knowledge? It doesn't seem to fit into the structure that Aristotle describes. I think that I know that killing people is wrong, but what is the source of the archai on which this knowledge is based? There are various other aspects of Aristotle's account which we might want to take issue with. For example, it appears that nous is something more than simple inference, but it is not entirely clear how it operates: how many observations are enough? It does seem a plausible explanation for certain types of ideas; for example, we can see how it might be possible to comprehend the idea of a circle after seeing a number of circular shapes, even if none of them was a perfect circle. But when it comes to observations of the natural world (which is one of the things that Aristotle is trying to formulate a structure of knowledge for), it would seem than generalisation is a shaky way to derive foundational knowledge. For example, assume I notice trees shedding their leaves one autumn. In subsequent years, I see the same phenomenon again, and at some point the memories of all the occasions when this has happened are synthesised into a comprehension of the general principle that trees shed their leaves because it is autumn (I am also assuming that there exist some other observations which demonstrate a causal link in this direction). This selfevident knowledge can then serve as a component for future learning, but it seems more fragile than it ought to be: if I come across an evergreen tree for example, my knowledge will need revising. At the least, what I previously conceived of as a proposition concerning all trees must be revised to a term such as all deciduous trees. And once we allow this, then it seems we have opened the door to the possibility that future observations will

5 eventually result in us knowing no more than all trees that shed their leaves in autumn, shed their leaves in autumn, which doesn't seem very useful. Unlike geometry and logic, the natural world seems fraught with irregularities. I think that the answer to many of these criticisms lies rooted in the fact that Aristotle is talking about knowledge with understanding. When I acquire self-evident knowledge, I am not simply (or even) memorising a proposition such as trees shed their leaves because it is autumn. Rather, I have acquired some archai which involves comprehension: although what I comprehend may be articulated as trees shed their leaves because it is autumn, this is only a verbal attempt to state my understanding; later observations I make may lead me to alter my verbal account, but the archai I originally held concerning the relationship between trees and leaves remains valid. When I know that the radio is playing a Beatles track, I don't have the same kind of understanding as is the case when I know that trees (of a certain type) shed their leaves. The experience of hearing music on the radio might serve as the raw ingredients for a future instance of nous, but it doesn't in itself count as knowledge in the sense which Aristotle has in mind. It seems to me that the most fragile aspect of Aristotle's position is the trust I need to place in my senses, which I have to use to make the observations which will subsequently be used to construct archai. Presumably I know that my senses are accurate, but it is difficult to see how I can have acquired that knowledge. Conclusion

6 For the kind of knowledge which Aristotle is talking of, it is necessarily true that we must have self-evident knowledge in order to know anything. However, Aristotle's account in Posterior Analytics is limited in scope to a specific kind of knowledge, namely that which includes an understanding of cause. Given this limitation, the question of whether selfevident knowledge is required in order to know contingent facts, or whether moral knowledge can be self-evident, is not something that he addresses. Nick Hudson 2004 nick@nickoh.com

7 REFERENCES PoA : Barnes, J (1975) Aristotle's Posterior Analytics. Translated with notes by Jonathan Barnes. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Dancy, J (1985) An Introduction to Contemporary Epistemology. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers Ltd.