Does the Third Man Argument refute the theory of forms?

Similar documents
Plato's Epistemology PHIL October Introduction

SOCRATES, PIETY, AND NOMINALISM. love is one of the most well known in the history of philosophy. Yet some fundamental

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

EPITAPH FOR THE THIRD MAN. Debra Nails

2. Refutations can be stronger or weaker.

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

404 Ethics January 2019 I. TOPICS II. METHODOLOGY

Unpacking the City-Soul Analogy

C. Exam #1 comments on difficult spots; if you have questions about this, please let me know. D. Discussion of extra credit opportunities

Russell s Problems of Philosophy

Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

- 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance

Leibniz, Principles, and Truth 1

Edinburgh Research Explorer

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

5 A Modal Version of the

Socrates Young and Old: From the Parmenides to the Phaedo. The Parmenides is the earliest of Plato s Socratic dialogues (I mean the dialogues in which

4AANA001 Greek Philosophy I Syllabus Academic year 2015/16

Reductio ad Absurdum, Modulation, and Logical Forms. Miguel López-Astorga 1

Intro to Ground. 1. The idea of ground. 2. Relata. are facts): F 1. More-or-less equivalent phrases (where F 1. and F 2. depends upon F 2 F 2

The Recurring Problem of the Third Man

The Trinity and the Enhypostasia

latter case, if we offer different concepts by which to define piety, we risk no longer talking about piety. I.e., the forms are one and all

Ethical Consistency and the Logic of Ought

Every simple idea has a simple impression, which resembles it; and every simple impression a correspondent idea

Aboutness and Justification

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Bart Streumer, Unbelievable Errors, Oxford: Oxford University Press, ISBN

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is

Overview Plato Socrates Phaedo Summary. Plato: Phaedo Jan. 31 Feb. 5, 2014

Plato BCE Republic, ca BCE

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

6AANA040 Greek Philosophical Texts I: Plato Syllabus Academic year 2013/4

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

Plato s Legacy: Whether the Republic or the Timaeus Reigns Supreme. Thomas Arralde, 2013

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

A primer of major ethical theories

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

4AANA001 Greek Philosophy I Syllabus Academic year 2013/14

Ibn Sina on Substances and Accidents

Abstraction for Empiricists. Anti-Abstraction. Plato s Theory of Forms. Equality and Abstraction. Up Next

Topics and Posterior Analytics. Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey

Nathaniel Goldberg. McTAGGART ON TIME

Plato and the art of philosophical writing

Knowledge and True Opinion in Plato s Meno

4AANA001 Greek Philosophy I Syllabus Academic year 2014/15

THE FORM OF REDUCTIO AD ABSURDUM J. M. LEE. A recent discussion of this topic by Donald Scherer in [6], pp , begins thus:

Primary and Secondary Qualities. John Locke s distinction between primary and secondary qualities of bodies has

(1) A phrase may be denoting, and yet not denote anything; e.g., 'the present King of France'.

ON DENOTING BERTRAND RUSSELL ORIGINALLY PUBLISHED IN MIND 14.4 (1905): THIS COPY FROM PHILOSOPHY-INDEX.COM.

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988)

The belief in the existence of an omniscient, omnipotent and benevolent God is inconsistent with the existence of human suffering. Discuss.

GREAT PHILOSOPHERS series TRINITY COLLEGE DUBLIN

PHILOSOPHY ESSAY ADVICE

Kihyun Lee (Department of Philosophy, Seoul National University)

MENO. We must first define Platonic Dialogue and then consider the Meno.

BOOK REVIEWS. The arguments of the Parmenides, though they do not refute the Theory of Forms, do expose certain problems, ambiguities and

Modal Realism, Counterpart Theory, and Unactualized Possibilities

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Adapted from The Academic Essay: A Brief Anatomy, for the Writing Center at Harvard University by Gordon Harvey. Counter-Argument

Why the Traditional Conceptions of Propositions can t be Correct

7AAN2026 Greek Philosophy I: Plato Syllabus Academic year 2016/17

4AANA001 Greek Philosophy I Syllabus Academic year 2016/17

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5

Chapter 2: Reasoning about ethics

Self-Evidence in Finnis Natural Law Theory: A Reply to Sayers

Collection and Division in the Philebus

PRACTICAL REASONING. Bart Streumer

Helpful Hints for doing Philosophy Papers (Spring 2000)

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

Parmenides PHIL301 Prof. Oakes Winthrop University updated: 9/5/12 3:03 PM

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology

The Role of Inconsistency in the Death of Socrates 1

12. A Theistic Argument against Platonism (and in Support of Truthmakers and Divine Simplicity)

5: Preliminaries to the Argument

Plato s Euthyphro. G. J. Mattey. Winter, 2006 / Philosophy 1. Our first text will be from Plato and centered around his teacher Socrates ( BC).

McKenzie Study Center, an Institute of Gutenberg College. Handout 5 The Bible and the History of Ideas Teacher: John A. Jack Crabtree.

Anthony P. Andres. The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic. Anthony P. Andres

Tutorial A03: Patterns of Valid Arguments By: Jonathan Chan

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

Reading Euthyphro Plato as a literary artist

7AAN2026 Greek Philosophy I: Plato Syllabus Academic year 2014/15

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Phil Aristotle. Instructor: Jason Sheley

SWINBURNE ON THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA. CAN SUPERVENIENCE SAVE HIM?

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Plato's Introduction of Forms (review)

PLATO S EXPLANATORY PREDICATION

Ancient Philosophy. Cal State Fullerton Instructor: Jason Sheley

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics

Lecture 2.1 INTRO TO LOGIC/ ARGUMENTS. Recognize an argument when you see one (in media, articles, people s claims).

Transcription:

Does the Third Man Argument refute the theory of forms? Fine [1993] recognises four versions of the Third Man Argument (TMA). However, she argues persuasively that these are similar arguments with similar tacit premises, though with different emphases. Consequently, we will consider only that in Parmenides 132 a 1- b 2. Fine s translation runs as follows, with Parmenides speaking to Socrates: I suppose it is because of the following sort of thing that you think that (1) each form is one: (2) Whenever many things seem large to you, there perhaps seems to you to be, when you have looked at them all, some one and the same idea. Hence you think (3) the large is one.. (4) What, then, if in the same way you look in your soul at all these at the large itself and the other large things? (5) Will not some one large appear again, by which all these will appear large?. So another form of largeness will appear besides the large itself and its participants. (6) And in addition to these, yet another, by which all these will be large. (7) And so each of the forms will no longer be one for you, but infinitely many. There are two things we need to address in this essay. Firstly, we need to understand the TMA itself, determining its premises, logical structure and validity. Secondly, we need to determine what Plato wants us to learn from it, and what its consequences are for his theory of Forms. The Argument Vlastos [1954] generalises Fine s steps (2) and (5) as: (V2) (V5) If a number of things a, b, c, are all F, there must be a single Form F-ness, in virtue of which we apprehend a, b, c as all F. If a, b, c, and F-ness are all F, there must be another Form F-ness 1, in virtue of which we apprehend a, b, c and F-ness as all F. Since (V5) evidently does not follow from (V2), Vlastos provides two premises that he considers the simplest to legitimate the conclusion: (SPV) Self-predication: Any Form can be predicated of itself. Largeness is itself large. F-ness is itself F. (NIV) Non-Identity: If anything has a certain character, it cannot be identical with the Form that explains its having that character. If x is F, x cannot be identical with F-ness. In addition, Fine reformulates step (1) as the uniqueness assumption (U): theotodman@lineone.net 29/03/07 13:44 Page 1 of 7

(U) There is exactly one form corresponding to every predicate that has a form. The regress Vlastos s premises successfully maintain the regress: 1. Take a, b, c, particular F things. 2. There is a single form F-ness, in virtue of which they are F. (from 1 & (V2)) 3. F-ness is F. (from (SPV)). 4. So, a, b, c, & F-ness are all F (from 1 & 3). 5. So, there is a single form F-ness 1, in virtue of which they are F. (from 4 & (V2)). 6. F-ness 1 is F. (from (SPV)). 7. F-ness 1 cannot be F-ness, because F-ness cannot be F in virtue of F-ness. (from 4 & (NIV)) 8. a, b, c,, F-ness & F-ness 1 are all F (from 4 & 6). 9. So, there is a single form F-ness 2, in virtue of which they are F. (from 8 & (V2)). 10. F-ness 2 is F. (from (SPV)). 11. F-ness 2 cannot be F-ness 1, because F-ness 1 cannot be F in virtue of F-ness 1. (from 8 & (NIV)) 12. Similarly, F-ness 2 cannot be F-ness, because F-ness cannot be F in virtue of F-ness. (from 8 & (NIV)) 13. a, b, c,, F-ness, F-ness 1 & F-ness 2 are all F (from 8 & 10). 14. and so on The regress in the TMA is vicious. The Forms are supposed to explain how we know things. We know something is F by acquaintance with the Form of F. But if this Form requires a further Form to explain it, and so on ad infinitem, we ll never know anything. Refining the premises Vlastos s premises are inconsistent. According to (SPV), F-ness is F. Consequently, (NIV) says that F-ness is not identical with F-ness, a contradiction since anything is identical with itself. While (SPV) and (NIV) take us from (V2) to (V5), their inconsistency will take us anywhere. Additionally, if (SPV) and (NIV) are essential to the theory of Forms, then it is inconsistent also. Our question would be quickly answered and the TMA would refute the theory of Forms. However, Self-Predication and Non-Identity assumptions are required, since: Step (4) refers to other large things, in addition to the Large, showing that the Form of Large is itself large. Step (5) refers to another form of largeness, indicating non-identity. Fine suggests the following, which are intentionally less explicit to make them consistent: theotodman@lineone.net 29/03/07 13:44 Page 2 of 7

(SP) Any form of F is itself F. (NI) Nothing is F in virtue of itself. This doesn t lead to an immediate contradiction, because it s not claimed that a form of F is F in virtue of itself. However, Vlastos s (V2) still causes problems for, if we formulate (2) as (V2) and assume (SP) and (NI), we have an inconsistent triad. This is because (SP) and (V2) imply that the unique form of Large must be large in virtue of itself, which (NI) denies. Refining the One-Over-Many assumption Strictly, step (2) is not an instance of (U), but of a more general one-over-many assumption, and hence need not be read as (V2). The literature provides a sequence of attempts to improve on (V2), which space prohibits our discussing here. All but Cohen s [1971] fail either to generate a regress or to suggest (U). For Cohen s proposal, we need the concept of a maximal set of level n. The set of all sensible Fs is the maximal set of Fs of level 0. The maximal set of Level 1 consists of the members of this set, together with the unique Form at level 1 in virtue of which they are F. In general, the maximal set of level n contains all the Fs at that level, together with all those of lower levels. With this in place, we have: (OM-TMA) For any maximal set of Fs at level n, there is exactly one Form of F at level n+1 over 1 it. Fine concludes that (SP), (NI) and (OM-TMA) are the premises of the TMA. They are mutually consistent and generate a regress. (OM-TMA) assigns a unique form to explain the F-ness of any set of Fs. It does not imply (U), but its use of exactly one makes it look as though it might. The point is that the TMA argues that (U) is false, so the premises need to make the thought that (U) tempting, without strictly implying it. We might have reservations that (OM-TMA) is more in the spirit of Russell than Plato. However, while it is far from the surface of Plato s writings, it might just be the sort of thing he had in mind and could have explicated if pressed. Is Plato vulnerable to the TMA? Having now got a version of the TMA with consistent premises that validly generates a regress, we have to ask ourselves what it proves. There seem to be three main alternatives: 1. The premises of the TMA are central to Plato s theory of Forms, which he was forced to abandon. 1 Participated in by all and only the members of. theotodman@lineone.net 29/03/07 13:44 Page 3 of 7

2. The TMA shows how it s possible to misconstrue the theory of Forms so that it s subject to the regress, but Plato himself never held this view. 3. The TMA showed Plato that he needed to tighten up what he meant by his premises, after which the theory is sound or at least not refuted. We should reject (1) for three reasons. Firstly, there s no evidence that Plato abandoned the theory of Forms in his later writings 2, and Aristotle treated it as a live doctrine of the Academy after Plato s death 3. Secondly, as both Meinwald [1992] and Cohen point out, the TMA cannot be a reductio ad absurdum of Plato s theory of Forms because, if it were, the premises and logic would be clear so that we could tell what conclusions to draw. Since, the argument is notoriously obscure, it fails to fit the paradigm of a reductio. Finally, (1) doesn t seem to be the lesson Plato draws; the abandonment of the theory would destroy dialectic; rather, Socrates needs more training in philosophy 4. To determine whether Plato ought to have abandoned the theory 5, or alternatively to choose between (2) and (3), we need to examine the premises and Plato s commitment to them. According to Fine s analysis, Plato has to accept all of (SP), (NI) and (OM-TMA) to be vulnerable to the TMA, so rejecting or seriously modifying one of these would liberate Plato. We treat them in turn. Self-Predication Meinwald argues that the second part of the Parmenides demonstrates an innovation on Plato s part a distinction between two kinds of predication: Predication in relation to itself reveals something of the structure of a thing s nature, explaining what makes a property what it is. Predication in relation to the others concerns the subject s display of some feature, predicating a property of a particular. Predication in relation to self shows that the As and Bs are so related that being B is part of what it is to be A. Eg. The Just is virtuous because being virtuous is part of what it means to be just. The Just is just is the limiting case; uninformative but safe. Meinwald thinks that Platonism has been taken to involve the ridiculous mistake of supposing that properties do their job by possessing the very properties they are. Beauty is taken to be the most beautiful thing, Largeness the largest, and so on. What Meinwald calls super-exemplification assimilates self-predication sentences to true ordinary predications in relation to the others. Saying Bravery is brave is false or nonsense, taken in relation to the others, as Bravery isn t the sort of thing that can stand firm in fearsome circumstances. However, self-predication sentences are always true when taken 2 See, eg. Sophist 254c Let s not talk about every form let s choose some of the most important ones. Also Philebus 15a, where problems are raised, but the theory isn t rejected. 3 Eg. In Peri Ideon, from whence (84.21-85.3) comes one of the four versions of the TMA noted by Fine. 4 Parmenides 135 c -135 d. 5 Noting, with Annas [1981], that Plato never presents a theory as such. theotodman@lineone.net 29/03/07 13:44 Page 4 of 7

as predications in relation to self. Failing to make this distinction is what made the immature Socrates (and hence the early Plato) misinterpret his own theory. With (SP) understood in this way, the TMA fails. It crucially depends on the claim The Large is large being taken in the same way as Mont Blanc is large. However, taken as predication in relation to self, (SP) doesn t claim that The Large is large in this way, and so we don t end up with a new set of large things that require a new Form. In response, if Forms don t display super-exemplification, we might ask what it is about them that allows them to do their job. We ve noticed that self-predication is uninformative, so what is it about the Form of Large that explains why large things are large? If the Form is itself large, we have an informative explanation, but otherwise we have only a pseudo-explanation. While it may appear that the Form explains the property, it does so no more than the appeal to the dormitive faculty of opium explains its soporific properties. We need a mechanism. Additionally, there are passages outside the Parmenides that show that Plato, at least initially, accepted (SP). For instance Phaedo 100 c 5 If anything else is beautiful besides the beautiful itself, it is beautiful for no other reason at all than that it participates in that beautiful. Cases where (SP) is problematic will result in a reduction in the number of Forms. We see that Plato was concerned about this from Parmenides 130 c. Non-Identity We must distinguish weak- from strong-ni. Weak-NI only claims that non-forms are not F in virtue of themselves because they are F in virtue of the Form F. Strong-NI claims that the Form F is also not F in virtue of itself. We saw at Phaedo 100 c 5 that Plato accepted weak-ni. However, strong-ni is essential to the TMA. Plato must reject strong-ni on theoretical grounds. If each Form required a Form at a higher level to explain it, knowledge would be impossible, because we would have an explanatory regress, which is what makes the TMA-regress vicious. Since knowledge is possible, there must be Forms accessible to us that are F in virtue of themselves. Forms have to explain something other than themselves, so this rules out further Forms above the one Form which explains the sensibles, which is F in virtue of itself. This gives Plato (U). Passages such as Symposium 211 b, where the Form of the Beautiful is itself by itself with itself and which is independent of things that participate in it, and suffers no augmentation, diminution or change when they come to be or perish, gives no indication that Forms depend on other things, as of course does the uniqueness requirement (Republic 507 b a single form of each ). One-Over-Many theotodman@lineone.net 29/03/07 13:44 Page 5 of 7

Nor is Plato committed to (OM-TMA), because Forms only arise for imperfectly-f things 6, and a group containing a Form hasn t all its members imperfectly F, so requires no further Form over it. Not every group of F-things is F in virtue of some thing external to the group, for it may contain the paradigm Form, which is intrinsically F. Conclusion We should reject (2). Socrates is usually Plato s mouthpiece, but in this dialogue it is Parmenides who speaks for Plato. This indicates that Plato has been challenged to modify his views so that we have Plato correcting his former self. To re-read the earlier dialogues as though Socrates were speaking only for himself, with Plato secretly holding more developed views all along, undermines the literary skill with which Plato presents his thoughts. Hence, we should accept (3). The TMA does not refute the theory of Forms. Plato rejects both (NI) and (OM-TMA), two of the premises of the TMA, to which he is consequently not vulnerable. Alternatively, he might modify the meaning of (SP). The TMA is neither a record of honest perplexity nor a reductio of his theory, though the theory has many other problems to contend with 7. Instead, it s an invitation for us to clarify what we mean by self-predication, non-identity and the one-over-many principle 8. 6 See, eg., Phaedo 74 d -74 e, where equal things strive to be like, but fall short of, and are inferior to, the Equal, whereas the Equal is perfectly equal. 7 As Parmenides 130 a -134 e points out. Eg. What the Forms are (paradigms, thoughts, ), how particulars partake of the Form, how Forms are known. 8 Word count: 2,620 including 124 for the question (10), bibliography (99) & this footnote (15). theotodman@lineone.net 29/03/07 13:44 Page 6 of 7

Bibliography Annas, Julia. 1981. The Theory of Forms. Chapter 9 of An Introduction to Plato s Republic. OUP. Cohen, S.M. 1971. The Logic of the Third Man. Philosophical Review. Vol.80, No.4. Fine, G. 1993. On Ideas, Chapters 15-16. Clarendon Press, Oxford. Meinwald, C.C. 1992. Good-bye to the Third Man. In The Cambridge Companion to Plato, R. Kraut, (Ed.). Sellars, W. 1955. Vlastos and the Third Man. Philosophical Review. Vol.64, No.3. Vlastos, G. 1954. The Third Man Argument in the Parmenides. Philosophical Review. Vol.63, No.3. Vlastos, G. 1969. Plato s Third Man Argument (Parmenides 132a1-b2): Text and Logic. Philosophical Quarterly. Vol.19, No.77. theotodman@lineone.net 29/03/07 13:44 Page 7 of 7