Arthur W. Foshay is professor of educa tion and is director. Bureau of Educa tional Research, Ohio State University, / Columbus.

Similar documents
Seeing, Is Behaving. October 1958

SYSTEMATIC RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY. Contents

Children of today will be making reservation* to uiher in the next century. Science Exhibit, Glencoe, Illinois,

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Action in Special Contexts

Values: What Impact on Educating for Judgment Making James K. Uphoff

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Building Systematic Theology

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information

LAWRENCE E. METCALF. The Challenge to Intellect

Predicate logic. Miguel Palomino Dpto. Sistemas Informáticos y Computación (UCM) Madrid Spain

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

The Changing of the Grad

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

A-LEVEL Religious Studies

Creative Teaching for Creative Thinking and Living

World Religions. These subject guidelines should be read in conjunction with the Introduction, Outline and Details all essays sections of this guide.

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send to:

Calisthenics June 1982

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Conclusion. up to the modern times has been studied focusing on the outstanding contemporary

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

COPLESTON: Quite so, but I regard the metaphysical argument as probative, but there we differ.

- 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance

The Giving Tree by Shel Silverstein. Caring, Friendship, Reciprocity

A European Philosophy of Congregational Education Edwin de Jong Gottmadingen, Germany. Introduction

Some questions about Adams conditionals

Subject Matter with a Focus on Values

Teachur Philosophy Degree 2018

A Studying of Limitation of Epistemology as Basis of Toleration with Special Reference to John Locke

Personal Philosophy Paper. my worldview, metaphysics, epistemology and axiology which have traces of Neo-

Calisthenics November 1982

SCHOOL ^\t. MENTAL CURE. Metaphysical Science, ;aphysical Text Book 749 TREMONT STREET, FOR STUDENT'S I.C6 BOSTON, MASS. Copy 1 BF 1272 BOSTON: AND

BonJour Against Materialism. Just an intellectual bandwagon?

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Principles of Classical Christian Education

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

The Wisdom of Andrew Carnegie as told to Napoleon Hill

Charles Saunders Peirce ( )

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.


VIEWING PERSPECTIVES

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

COMITÉ SUR LES AFFAIRES RELIGIEUSES A NEW APPROACH TO RELIGIOUS EDUCATION IN SCHOOL: A CHOICE REGARDING TODAY S CHALLENGES

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 3e Free Will

A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University THE DEMANDS OF ACT CONSEQUENTIALISM

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Ecclesiastes: A Book of Philosophy. Humans differ from any other species on the earth. Our superior brain gives us a

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

Is the law of excluded middle a law of logic?

Summary Common Contexts Biblical and Theological Canons

THE DRESS. by Miles Mathis

From: Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (2005)

Eichrodt, Walther. Theology of the Old Testament: Volume 1. The Old Testament Library.

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Writing Module Three: Five Essential Parts of Argument Cain Project (2008)

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

At the Risk of Being Shot: An Analysis of Moral Development in Mark Twain's Huckleberry Finn

Critique of Cosmological Argument

Education. for a Democratic Culture

Syllabus Investigating Christian Theology 2

World View, Metaphysics, and Epistemology

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Calisthenics October 1982

Faith at Work Work and the Drama of Scripture

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER IX CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE

Why Study Christian Evidences?

is the edification of Christians. Clark asks some very penetrating questions, such as: Is it necessary to have saving faith?

The Rationale For This Web Site (As Seen Through the Eyes of Herb Gross)

On the Relation of Philosophy to the Theology Conference Seward 11/24/98

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

CRIMINAL JUSTICE MINISTRY

How to Teach The Writings of the New Testament, 3 rd Edition Luke Timothy Johnson

WHAT IS THEOLOGY AND WHY IS IT IMPORTANT?

J.f. Stephen s On Fraternity And Mill s Universal Love 1

Helping Young People Discover Commitment

Infallibility and Church Authority:

THE TOWARDS AN IDEAL BOTANICAL CURRICULUM. PART III.' ADVANCED UNIVRKSITY TEACHING.

It Ain t What You Prove, It s the Way That You Prove It. a play by Chris Binge

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to

Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory.

Pentateuch. BIB credits. Description: Objectives: Texts: Behavioral: 3 Author 3 Time period covered (not specific dates but length of time)

THE ESSAY. Some tips for writing good introductions Strategies for writing good introductions

I, for my part, have tried to bear in mind the very aims Dante set himself in writing this work, that is:

STUDY GUIDE ARE HUMANS MORE VALUABLE THAN ANIMALS? KEY TERMS:

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth).

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

x Philosophic Thoughts: Essays on Logic and Philosophy

A Warning about So-Called Rationalists

Doctrine of God. Immanuel Kant s Moral Argument

Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008

PROSPECTIVE TEACHERS UNDERSTANDING OF PROOF: WHAT IF THE TRUTH SET OF AN OPEN SENTENCE IS BROADER THAN THAT COVERED BY THE PROOF?

24.00: Problems of Philosophy Prof. Sally Haslanger November 16, 2005 Moral Relativism

A Statement of Seventh-day Adventist Educational Philosophy* Version 7.9

Transcription:

useful meanings than does other sub ject matter. Some may be better uti lized by learners when they are of a certain age or have had certain expe riences in their background or have certain purposes. Practices in selecting and organizing curriculum content may well be judged by the extent to which they reflect con cern for an over-all objective of devel oping thinking-feeling-acting peoplepeople who have facts to think with or know where to get them; people who are doers; people who have good feel ings to make their thinking and act ing humane. Subject matter, processes, approaches, feelings the curriculum always contains some of all of these but it takes deliberate planning to capi talize on this wide range of content. A broad view of curriculum content helps to ensure learnings of high quality. Choice of Content I This article examines two assertions about the nature of man, to illustrate a way of thinking about the choice of curriculum content. WANT to tell you of the process.1 went through in developing the present article. It represents, I think, a transition from one level of thinking to another that many of us will have to struggle with as we try to raise the level of importance of our thinking about the significance of the content we choose for the curriculum. My first outline for this article had headings like these: What limits choice? among children: interests perceptions maturity of various kinds among teachers: personal experience and knowledge materials and other resources in the school's social context: the prevailing local opinion concern ing the place and function of the' school public stereotype of teaching method public notion of acceptable behavior by teachers and children in the school: sequence how content is related to child's past; to his future balance of learning: firsthand and vicarious; self and non-self; skill. understanding, conceptualizing. Now, this isn't a bad outline. There are fresh things that might be said under some of these headings, and an article written from them would be understandably organized. But there are two things wrong with the outline: it doesn't allow me to say what is upper most in my mind, and many of the readers of such an article probably could write it better than I. As it hap-

pens, I recently came to the conclu sion that a rather large proportion of the readers of Educational Leader ship write for educational periodicals themselves. I had a feeling, however, that the real difficulty with the outline was that it allowed me only to patch up what exists, when something more fundamental can be said about choice of content. What seems more fundamental is this: any content selected for seri ous consideration in the curriculum amounts to an assertion about the nature of Man. By what we encourage children to do and to avoid, we guide them toward what we think they ought to become. Let's not pretend that we don't finally choose content, even though we maintain a supportive class room climate and constantly involve children as we certainly must in the act of choice. If the choice we make is adequate, or inspiring, it is because we portray through it an adequate, or inspiring version of the nature of Man. If the choice of content should be called narrow, skill-dominated, "minimum-standardized," it is because we imply through it a narrow, mech anistic, standardized version of the nature of Man. What is thrilling about the ideals of Progressive Education is the vision of children as fellow human beings, rather than as cups to be filled or abstractions to be intellectualized about. In the days, a generation ago, when many of us were caught up in the educa tional ferment of the Progressive move ment, we felt as we did largely because we were able to act in the classroom according to our most deeply held ideals about what it meant to be a hu- Arthur W. Foshay is professor of educa tion and is director. Bureau of Educa tional Research, Ohio State University, / Columbus. man being. What has endured I from those days is the conviction many of us share that, at its best, education is a spiritual process; a process in which the teacher as artist works with the human spirit as his medium; a process in which the good life is treated as an actuality for children, not some thing to be postponed pending edu cation. The doctrine of the wholeness of a person's response to his environ ment, and the uniqueness of his re sponse, is an assertion that a human being is an integrated, individualistic, responsive creature. The doctrine of respect for the individual is a declara tion that mankind is worth whilc ; I propose in what follows to offer two assertions about the nature of Man, and to sec what each of these means, expressed as choice of curric ulum content. In doing this. I mean to illustrate a way of thinking about the curriculum that seems promising. 1 Man is a reasoning being, 'lliis is an obvious proposition to most of us, most of the time. While we are aware of irrationality, and during modern times have allowed it a legitimate place in our thinking about ourselves, we prize our ability to use reason-'in the 1 Many such formulations have been made by theologians, philosophers" and psychologists. One recent formulation that is very intriguing is by Gordon Allport, in his fascinating little book, Becoming ( Terry Lectures, Yale.University Press, 1955).

understanding and solution of prob lems. Let us see what this proposition im plies for the content of the curriculum. What experiences in school can lead children to understand and make use of their own rationality? Arithmetic is one category that has obvious rele vance here. Arithmetic is a form of logic of reasoning. At its root, arith metic consists of reducing reality to a certain kind of symbol, then manip ulating the symbols according to a more or less fixed logical plan, in order to deduce from the known some prop erty that is unknown. When children are helped to formulate arithmetic problems, they are learning to ration alize, arithmetically. When children are restricted to computation alone the so-called "fundamental processes" they are prevented from learning the logic. In the degree that drill is used in the absence of a logic that is under standable to a child, the child is "con ditioned" like Pavlov's dog. He is not treated as a rational being. Another form of reasoning is rep resented by language and the language arts. When language is so used as to help children formulate truth about themselves and others, it is an aid to an understanding of humans as ra tional beings. How could language be used this way? One way is through the gathering and ordering of information. If one takes the rational quality of man into account, the conventional "re port" by a child, representing his (or his committee's) attempt to put facts in meaningful order is an exceedingly important learning activity. Science certainly is a discipline based on reasoning. The rational nature of science is expressed in the logic of experimentation the logical form through which most scientific concepts are built. In an elementary school, a teacher who sees science as a way of asserting the rationality of man would go beyond the teaching of concepts to the more subtle area in which chil dren are helped to make their own generalizations about the physical en^* vironment. I have chosen for these illustrations three subject matter fields which often arc viewed simply as skill areas, or in formation areas. Social studies as it is now conceived lends itself far more easily to the kind of treatment implied by the kind of approach being explored here. Obviously, when children are taken through experiences as close to their immediate living as their own communities, or are encouraged to study how people live under varying conditions, the opportunities to build skill in reasoning are rich. Moreover, almost any study of men implies that men are rational for it is the rationale of their work that one studies when one asks, "How does the policeman help us?" or "How do boys and girls live in Cleveland? How does this differ from the way they live in Monte video?" Looking at these three subject-matter areas arithmetic, language arts, and science in this way leads us to em phasize certain aspects of these fields. Instead of placing most of our em phasis on the errors children make in "doing" arithmetic, we ask, "How can children learn to be good formulators of arithmetic problems?" Not that ac curacy in computation isn't essentialit's simply not a sufficient view of the

contribution of this logical form. In reading, instead of putting most of our emphasis on comprehension, we arc led through this approach to a step be yond comprehension to the ordering of what is comprehended. We ask, "I low can'children learn to ptut facts in logical order?" The answer to this ques tion would lead us to correct the widely held impression among children that their chief task in reading is to remem ber what they have read. Their chief task, as rational human beings, is to interpret. Rote memory was never enough. In science, this approach leads us away from an exclusive emphasis on the mastery of information and con cepts, toward an emphasis on the meth ods of science the rationales. We might ask, "How can children learn scientific 'knowing'?" Man is a self-evaluator. It is often pointed out that among all the ani mals, only Man can will his own de struction. There have been men who conclude that they are worthless, and so evaluating themselves, act on the conclusion. At a less dramatic level, all of us are aware of our self-evaluation. Children constantly, even anxiously, appraise themselves. The unspoken question on a child's mind is, "Who am I?" "What docs my existence sig nify?" The content we choose in school implies a partial answer to this eternal question. It is our business as teachers, therefore, to help children to make their self-evaluation as realistic and ap propriate as they can, considering their maturity and experience. Expressed as choice of content, we recognize Man as a sclf-cvaluator when we encourage children to read about people who have tried to evaluate themselves or explain themselves to themselves, as Tom and Huck often do in Huckleberry Finn: to talk and think about what makes people admirable. It lends important meaning to the idea of art as expressiveness. One can learn to understand one's self through the examination of one's own expression. A teacher in the language arts in the elementary school can introduce such themes as, what I like and don't like about myself, what I want to become, things that make me feel joyful, or angry, or fearful, and the completion of unfinished stories involving the be havior of children in problem -situa tions. Most lyric poetry deals with this same theme. Perhaps poetry would seem less repugnant to children if we stressed its form less, and emphasized what the poet is saying that would help us in our self-evaluation. I have tried, through a very brief "spelling out" of two assertions about the nature of Man, to illustrate a way of thinking about the choice of cur riculum content. This way of thinking has the advantage of allowing me to approach the subject anew, with little feeling that I must be bound by the field as it is. A structure for thinking that allows me to relate my most im portant beliefs to my professional be havior is, of course, more satisfying than one that tends to separate the two. Moreover, an attempt to derive curriculum content from assertions about the nature of Man suggests sig nificant curriculum research. I propose continuing with it. Perhaps others whose work has led them to deal with similar concerns will help toward a clarification of these beginnings.

Copyright 1956 by the Association for Supervision and Curriculum Development. All rights reserved.