Commentary on Guarini

Similar documents

Commentary on Scriven

Should We Assess the Basic Premises of an Argument for Truth or Acceptability?

Living High and Letting Die

Abortion, Property, and Liberty

The Singer and the Violinist: When Pro-Abortion Ethicists Are Out of Tune

Van Inwagen's modal argument for incompatibilism

Informalizing Formal Logic

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 5

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

Commentary on Paglieri

HANDBOOK. IV. Argument Construction Determine the Ultimate Conclusion Construct the Chain of Reasoning Communicate the Argument 13

Argumentation Schemes for Argument from Analogy

Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology

Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge Gracia's proposal

The Reach of Abduction: Insight and Trial (Book Review)

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Pragmatic Considerations in the Interpretation of Denying the Antecedent

A Defense of Abortion 1. Judith Jarvis Thomson. Philosophy and Public Affairs, Vol. 1, No. 1, p. 47 (1971)

Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus

Commentary on Feteris

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Truth and Premiss Adequacy

Can logical consequence be deflated?

On the Very Concept of an Enthymeme

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER IX CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

The deepest and most formidable presentation to date of the reductionist interpretation

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Oxford Scholarship Online

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

Phil 114, April 24, 2007 until the end of semester Mill: Individual Liberty Against the Tyranny of the Majority

Zimmerman, Michael J. Subsidiary Obligation, Philosophical Studies, 50 (1986):

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

The analysis and evaluation of counter-arguments in judicial decisions

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence

Book Reviews/Comptes Rendus 30 I

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Introduction to Logic. Instructor: Jason Sheley

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Basic Concepts and Skills!

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Virtue Ethics without Character Traits

(1) A phrase may be denoting, and yet not denote anything; e.g., 'the present King of France'.

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

Squeezing arguments. Peter Smith. May 9, 2010

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome

Kitcher, Correspondence, and Success

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 3

Conductive arguments and the inference to the best explanation

Metaphysical Necessity: Understanding, Truth and Epistemology

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 8

A Defense of Contingent Logical Truths

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

AN EPISTEMIC PARADOX. Byron KALDIS

Lecture 4. Before beginning the present lecture, I should give the solution to the homework problem

The Future of Practical Philosophy: a Reply to Taylor

Philosophy 240: Symbolic Logic

1. Lukasiewicz s Logic

A New Parameter for Maintaining Consistency in an Agent's Knowledge Base Using Truth Maintenance System

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Is it Reasonable to Rely on Intuitions in Ethics? as relying on intuitions, though I will argue that this description is deeply misleading.

Did Jesus Commit a Fallacy?

Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

INHISINTERESTINGCOMMENTS on my paper "Induction and Other Minds" 1

Kant and his Successors

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

The paradoxical associated conditional of enthymemes

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers

AS Religious Studies. 7061/1 Philosophy of Religion and Ethics Mark scheme June Version: 1.0 Final

Nathaniel Goldberg. McTAGGART ON TIME

From: Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (2005)

REFLECTIONS ON SPACE AND TIME

INQUIRY AS INQUIRY: A LOGIC OF SCIENTIFIC DISCOVERY

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

Logical form and the link between premise and conclusion

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Kevin Scharp, Replacing Truth, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013, At 300-some pages, with narrow margins and small print, the work

ON HARMING AND KILLING: REPLIES TO HANSER, PERSSON AND SAVULESCU, AND WASSERMAN

Inquiry: A dialectical approach to teaching critical thinking

Definite Descriptions and the Argument from Inference

Inductive inference is. Rules of Detachment? A Little Survey of Induction

2. Refutations can be stronger or weaker.

Reply to Robert Koons

The myth of the categorical counterfactual

Quantifiers: Their Semantic Type (Part 3) Heim and Kratzer Chapter 6

Is Epistemic Probability Pascalian?

Statistical Syllogistic, Part 1

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Theories of propositions

SYSTEMATIC RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY. Contents

Transcription:

University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 4 May 17th, 9:00 AM - May 19th, 5:00 PM Commentary on Guarini John Woods Follow this and additional works at: http://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive Part of the Philosophy Commons John Woods, "Commentary on Guarini" (May 17, 2001). OSSA Conference Archive. Paper 54. http://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive/ossa4/papersandcommentaries/54 This Commentary is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty of Arts, Humanities and Social Sciences at Scholarship at UWindsor. It has been accepted for inclusion in OSSA Conference Archive by an authorized administrator of Scholarship at UWindsor. For more information, please contact scholarship@uwindsor.ca.

Author: John Woods In Response to: Marcello Guarini s On the limitations of the Woods-Hudak reconstruction of analogical argument 2001 John Woods I am grateful to Marcello Guarini for the careful attention he has given By Parity of Reasoning, which I published with Brent Hudak in 1990. Thirteen years on, it is apparent that our account of analogical arguments harbours some obscurities that, in turn, give rise to the appearance if not the reality of outright error. I think that I can best honour Guarini s contribution not by answering it point by point; for not even I am ready to defend the original paper in every particular. Better, I think, to try again and see whether Guarini s objections have been satisfactorily dealt with in the retelling. One point of difference between then and now, is that I better appreciate the role of analogy in abductive reasoning, typified but not exhausted by best-explanation inferences. So in our present reprise, let me start there. A central task for the theorist of abduction is to elucidate the mechanics of hypothesis selection; in particular, he must try to answer the question of how, from an indefinitely large set of possibilities, only certain ones manage to qualify as candidateexplainers. Consider the following two schematic suggestions. Analogical Argument Darden s Schema problems posed by fact γ generalize general form of the problem γ analogize to general forms of similar problems with solutions ι plausible solution to this problem φ particularize general form of solution to problem φ construct general forms of other KNOWN solutions Darden s Schema [Darden, 1976, p. 142] reflects Hanson s influence, as evidenced by the following summary [Hanson, 1961, p. 33]. Hanson s Schema Some surprising, astonishing phenomena p 1, p 2, p 3,... are encountered. 1

Commentary on Marcello Guarini 2 But p 1, p 2, p 3,... would not be surprising where a hypothesis of H s type be obtained. They would follow as a matter of course from something like H and would be explained by it. Therefore there is good reason for elaborating a hypothesis of the type of H; for proposing it as a possible hypothesis from whose assumption p 1, p 2, p 3,... might be explained. Darden bids of the abducer to analogize. Hanson bids him to reason from types. As it happens, there is a ready-built theory of analogical argument that gives instruction on both these matters. It is the Meta-Argument Theory of Analogical Argument (MATAA) originated in Parity of Reasoning. 2. The Meta Approach Consider (again) what may have been one of the most commented-on analogical arguments of the century just passed [Thomson, 1971, p. 49]. You wake up in the morning and find yourself back to back in bed with an unconscious violinist. A famous unconscious violinist. He has been found to have a fatal kidney ailment, and the Society of Music Lovers has canvassed all the available records and found that you alone have the right blood type to help. They have therefore kidnapped you, and last night the violinist s circulatory system was plugged into yours, so that your kidney can be used to extract poisons from his blood as well as your own. The director of the hospital now tells you, Look, we re sorry the Society of Music Lovers did this to you we would never have permitted it if we had known. But still, they did and the violinist now is plugged into you. To unplug you would be to kill him. But never mind, it s only for nine months. By then he will have recovered from his ailment and can safely be unplugged from you. Is it morally incumbent on you to accede to this violation? No doubt it would be very nice if you did, a great kindness. But do you have to accede to it? What if it were not nine months, but nine years? Or longer still? What if the director of the hospital says, Tough luck, I agree, but you ve now got to stay in bed with the violinist plugged into you, for the rest of your life. Because remember this: All persons have a right to life, and violinists are persons. Granted you have a right to decide what happens in and to your body, but a person s right to life outweighs your right to decide what happens in and to your body. So you cannot ever be unplugged from him. Thomson develops her analogical argument as follows. If you judge The Violinist to be a good argument, then there is another argument similar to The Violinist that, by parity of reasoning, you must also judge good. This other argument (call it The Pregnancy) is one that concludes that maintaining a pregnancy arising from rape is not morally obligatory. Thomson is here invoking, without naming it, the Fundamental Rule of Analogy, which requires that similar cases be treated similarly. What the Fundament Rule does not make clear is what the relevant similarities between The Violinist and The Pregnancy would consist in. This is answered by the Meta-Argument Theory of Analogical Argument. It would be well to bear in mind at this juncture that Darden s schema has the reasoner generalizing and Hanson s schema has the reasoner arguing from type. So consider the following schema, which we ll call The Generalization.

Commentary on Marcello Guarini 3 The Generalization Human beings H 1 and H 2 are so related that without H 2 's consent, H 1 has placed H 2 in a state of vital dependency; the period of dependency is indeterminate (perhaps nine months, perhaps nine years, perhaps forever). the dependency is a grievous impediment both to locomotion and to (stationary) mobility; the dependency constitutes a grievous invasion of privacy; it is an invitation to social disaster, for H 2 (and H 1 as well) is a laughing stock, it threatens H 2 's economic self-sufficiency; therefore, it would be morally permissible for H 2 to terminate the vital dependency. Suppose, for present purposes, that Thomson is right in claiming parity between The Violinist and The Pregnancy; then MATAA furnishes the answer to what it is that these two quite different arguments nevertheless have in common. The MATAA proposal takes seriously the mention of cases in the Fundamental Rule to treat similar cases similarly. Accordingly, it is proposed that what The Violinist and The Pregnancy are cases of is a common deep structure represented here by The Generalization. Thus an analogical argument is a meta-argument; it is an argument about arguments. It is an argument in the form Meta-Argument 1. Argument A posses a deep structure that provides that the premisses of A bear relation R to its conclusion. 2. Argument B shares with A the same deep structure. 3. Therefore, B possesses a deep structure that provides that its premisses likewise bear R to its conclusion. 4. Hence, B is an analogue of A, A and B are good or bad arguments, by parity of reasoning, so-called. In our example, argument A is The Violinist. R is a strong consequence relation. B is The Pregnancy. The deep structure is The Generalization. The MATAA analysis requires that the analogizer generalize on an argument whose assessment is already settled, and then instantiate to a different argument. To achieve the desired parity, it is essential that the property that the original argument is assessed as having (e.g., validity) is preserved by the generalization and preserved by the subsequent instantiation (Darden calls this particularization ). It is well to note the significance of target propertypreservation. For ease of exposition let us agree to denote by P that property of The Violinist in virtue of which we regard it as a successful argument (assuming that we do). Then if the move from The Violinist to The Generalization is P-preserving and the instantiation from it, in turn, to The Pregnancy is also P-preserving, then one cannot in strict consistency ascribe P to The Violinist but not to The Pregnancy. This is important. It shows that good MATAA reasoning makes it a requirement of consistency that The Pregnancy be given the identical evaluation as The Violinist, contrary to Guarini s reservations. But let us also note in passing that this is not at

Commentary on Marcello Guarini 4 all the same as holding that one cannot in strict consistency accept the premisses of The Pregnancy and withhold or reject its conclusion. For nothing requires that the P that gets preserved in successful MATAA reasoning is always the property of validity. Perhaps this is the source of Guarini s confusion. 3. Abduction How does this bear on abduction? In a typical case the abducer has a target T for which he seeks an H such that for his belief-set, {H} T. His principal task is to find the requisite H. By Darden s and Hanson s lights, the abducer reasons his way to H by analogy. Doing so involves generalization and instantiation, and reasoning from type. If he proceeds in the manner prescribed by MATAA, the abducer looks for a distinct consequence structure 1. * {H * } T * that generalizes to 2. {H } T in ways that preserve the truth of (1). A Condition on this generalization is that the target T of the abducer s present abduction problem instantiate the T of the generalization of the original consequence structure. He then instantiates from and H to the required and H. What this represents is a rather commonplace situation in which there is a conclusion that you want to find some justification for. This is a premiss-selection task. You look for a conclusion whose sole similarity to your intended conclusion is that it is justified by premisses of a type (Hanson) that would likewise justify your intended conclusion. So you look for the requisite similarities among putative premisses. Except for tightly circumscribed situations, there are no algorithms for this that abducers actually execute. On the other hand, the MATAA has some powerful advantages. One is that it reduces analogizing to target property-preserving generalization and instantiation, which, given their commonness is a significantly simplifying reduction. The other that it gives some content to the schematic insights of Darden and Hanson. But what of Guarini s other reservations, especially those that bear on the question of obscurity or under-exposition? The answer is that in neither the original paper of 1990 nor in this note have I explained the notion of deep structure and the relation of being-a-case of. Clearly, the familiar quantifier rules of the predicate calculus tell part of this story. Attempts to tell the other parts may be found in due course in The Reach of Abduction, which Dov Gabbay and I are in the midst of writing (Gabbay and Woods, 2004). Bibliography Gabbay, Dov M. and John Woods. To appear, 2004. The Reach of Abduction. Amsterdam: North- Holland, 2004. Volume 2 of A Practical Logic of Cognitive Systems. Hanson, N. R. 1961. Is There a Logic of Scientific Discovery? in Herbert Feigl and Grover Maxwell

Commentary on Marcello Guarini 5 (eds.), Current Issues in the Philosophy of Science, pages 20 35. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston. Thomson, Judith Jarvis. 1971. A Defence of Abortion. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 1: 41 66. Woods, John and Brent Hudak. 1989. By Parity of Reasoning. Informal Logic, XI: 125 140.