EUGEN FINK & EDUCATION BEYOND THE HUMAN

Similar documents
Christian Lotz, Commentary, SPEP 2009 Formal Indication and the Problem of Radical Philosophy in Heidegger

INVESTIGATING THE PRESUPPOSITIONAL REALM OF BIBLICAL-THEOLOGICAL METHODOLOGY, PART II: CANALE ON REASON

ETHICS AND THE FUTURE OF HUMANKIND, REALITY OF THE HUMAN EXISTENCE

EXISTENTIALISM. Wednesday, April 20, 16

Process Thought and Bridge Building: A Response to Stephen K. White. Kevin Schilbrack

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

Canadian Society for Continental Philosophy

To Provoke or to Encourage? - Combining Both within the Same Methodology

MODELS CLARIFIED: RESPONDING TO LANGDON GILKEY. by David E. Klemm and William H. Klink

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things:

Summary of Sensorama: A Phenomenalist Analysis of Spacetime and Its Contents

Heidegger Introduction

Philosophy Courses-1

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

Response to Gregory Floyd s Where Does Hermeneutics Lead? Brad Elliott Stone, Loyola Marymount University ACPA 2017

Under contract with Oxford University Press Karen Bennett Cornell University

AFFIRMING THE DOCTRINE OF CREATION IN AN AGE OF SCIENCE

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of

The Metaphysics of Existence Sandra Lehmann

Response to The Problem of the Question About Animal Ethics by Michal Piekarski

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES

11/23/2010 EXISTENTIALISM I EXISTENTIALISM. Existentialism is primarily interested in the following:

The Other Half of Hegel s Halfwayness: A response to Dr. Morelli s Meeting Hegel Halfway. Ben Suriano

THE JOY OF LOVE. THE CHURCH AS THE GUARDIAN OF HUMAN LOVE Maryvale, 21 May 2016

PHILOSOPHY (PHIL) Philosophy (PHIL) 1

Qué es la filosofía? What is philosophy? Philosophy

Philosophy Courses-1

Towards a Theology of Resource Ministry December, 2008 Chris Walker

PART TWO: DEATH AS AN ONTIC EVENT: coming to terms with the phenomenon of death as a determinate possibility

Care of the Soul: Service-Learning and the Value of the Humanities

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have

Mark Coeckelbergh: Growing Moral Relations. Critique of Moral Status Ascription

Outline Lesson 2 - Philosophy & Ethics: Says Who?

Neo-Confucianism: Metaphysics, Mind, and Morality

Taoist and Confucian Contributions to Harmony in East Asia: Christians in dialogue with Confucian Thought and Taoist Spirituality.

BIBLICAL INTEGRATION IN SCIENCE AND MATH. September 29m 2016

The Development of Laws of Formal Logic of Aristotle

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

What is discernment?

Heidegger's What is Metaphysics?

Templeton Fellowships at the NDIAS

Undergraduate Calendar Content

I, for my part, have tried to bear in mind the very aims Dante set himself in writing this work, that is:

The Inter-Anglican Standing Commission for Ecumenical Relations

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

Topic Page: Heidegger, Martin,

Matthew E. Johnson November 29, 2013

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 110, No. 3. (Jul., 2001), pp

The Challenge of God. Julia Grubich

Gelassenheit See releasement. gender See Beauvoir, de

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

Philosophy (PHILOS) Courses. Philosophy (PHILOS) 1

Messiah College s identity and mission foundational values educational objectives. statements of faith community covenant.

On the Cultivation of Confucian Moral Practices

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness

Christian Evidences. The Verification of Biblical Christianity, Part 2. CA312 LESSON 06 of 12

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

UNCONDITIONAL SURRENDER AND LOVE

What can Heidegger s Being and Time Tell Today s Analytic Philosophy?

Theology of the Body! 1 of! 9

Chapter 2 Test Bank. 1) When one systematically studies being or existence one is dealing with the branch of metaphysics called.

Ludwig Feuerbach The Essence of Christianity (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 10/23/13 9:10 AM. Section III: How do I know? Reading III.

for Christians and non-christians alike (26). This universal act of the incarnate Logos is the

A Framework for the Good

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

The Soul Journey Education for Higher Consciousness

Kant and his Successors

Examining the nature of mind. Michael Daniels. A review of Understanding Consciousness by Max Velmans (Routledge, 2000).

A PHILOSOPHY OF EDUCATION. for the CHURCH OF THE NAZARENE

ONTOLOGICAL PROBLEMS OF PLURALIST RESEARCH METHODOLOGIES

Perspectival Methods in Metaphysics

Definition: The denial of the possibility of knowledge, philosophy, and value in anything.

THE ROLE OF A MENTOR

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Follow this and additional works at: Part of the Philosophy Commons

Catholic Social Tradition Theology, teaching and practice that have developed over centuries

It is because of this that we launched a website and specific programs to assist people in becoming soul centered.

The greatest is Love

Strange bedfellows or Siamese twins? The search for the sacred in practical theology and psychology of religion

Reading. The Impersonal Life

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

Youth Ministry Training Lesson Eighteen: Youth Ministry Shepherding Equipping Leaders. Introduction

The Spirit Speaks. By The Rt Revd Kenneth Fernando

THE ROLE OF A MENTOR

Discernment in the Life of the Vocation Director. NCDVD Convention 2018

Religious Instruction, Religious Studies and Religious Education

Fall 2016 Department of Philosophy Graduate Course Descriptions

Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

The Ethics of Self Realization: A Radical Subjectivism, Bounded by Realism. An Honors Thesis (HONR 499) Kevin Mager. Thesis Advisor Jason Powell

CHAPTER ONE What is Philosophy? What s In It For Me?

From tolerance to neutrality: A tacit schism

II. THE SACRAMENT OF PENANCE THE SOCIAL ASPECT OF THE SACRAMENT OF PENANCE

Spirituality: An Essential Aspect of Living

Transcription:

0 EUGEN FINK & EDUCATION BEYOND THE HUMAN Norm Friesen

1 Eugen Fink and Education beyond the Human Norm Friesen (Boise State University; Paper to be given at the annual conference of the Philosophy of Education Society, March 19.2017) Eugen Fink (1905 1975) earned his doctorate under Husserl and Heidegger and remained Husserl s loyal assistant, even when the latter was abandoned by Heidegger and persecuted by the Nazis for being Jewish. Regardless, the influence of Heidegger is much more evident in Fink s work than that of Husserl. Like both Husserl and Heidegger, Fink held a chair at the Albert Ludwigs University of Freiburg although Fink s was in philosophy and education. Fink saw the two disciplines as being inextricably intertwined. After the end of metaphysics, according to one commentator, Fink saw education not simply one of many possible topics for philosophizing; instead, he saw human becoming in its imminence as the concern par excellence for both philosophy and philosophical anthropology. 1 The way in which human beings are seen Fink emphasizes, predetermines the nature of education. In this presentation, I focus on one recently translated 1959 piece from Fink, The Questionableness of the modern Educator, and work to connect it to important themes in the German tradition of Bildung and Erziehung. 2 In so doing, I deal with existential questions about the limits and possibilities of the human, and possibilities and dangers presented what could be regarded as "beyond the human new, even previously unimagined possibilities of definition and self definition. I begin, however, with a central question for education raised in 1826 by theologian Friedrich Schleiermacher: What does the older generation actually want with the younger? Education for Schleiermacher as for Fink and for German thought in general is not a matter just of formal schooling, but about bringing up and raising children more broadly. These meanings are all captured by the German term Erziehung, which gives to education the significance of a kind of existentiale, a fundamental condition of existence: Education, Fink explains, is to be found whereever a difference between the generations exists, where those who are older feel responsible for the younger. Education, upbringing and human life itself are all indelibly and unavoidably marked by the responsibility of older generation for the younger. The mutual, formative (bildende) influence of the one on the other is one of its inescapable realities. A similar position may be familiar to One of the implications of these insights is that educating is neither primarily the specialized application of a knowledge base nor the use of a set of established scientific or pragmatic techniques to prepare the young for the world. Fink declares boldly: One is not an educator like one is a weaver, streetcar conductor or bank director but in the manner of being a worker, lover and fighter. 'Educating' [especially in the sense of upbringing] 1 Ferdinand Graf. Einführung in die Pädagogik Eugen Fink. In Anselm Böhmer (Ed. 2005) Eugen Fink: Sozialphilosophie Anthropologie Kosmologie Pädagogik Methodik. Pp. 72 84. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann. 2 This translation has not yet been finalized. See: Eugen Fink. Die Deutsche Schule: Zeitschrift für Erziehungswissenschaft und Gestaltung der Schulwirklichkeit 51(4; April 1959), 149 162.

2 belongs to the central phenomena fundamental to human existence. This simple truth however is generally forgotten, obscured or distorted, because in the modern world, the 'educator' has increasingly taken the role of a specific functionary in the process of social production, one specialist among countless others. The relation of the generations, the relation of this child or young person to me, is not an abstract one which I would observe as if from afar. It is instead a personal, often passionate relation where a great deal is at stake. It is one in which the teacher or adult generally engages with great conviction and a deep sense of individual investment. The intensive but socially sanctioned involvement of the teacher within this relationship between the generations makes his or her role special. As Fink explains, the teacher exemplifies a point of awareness, and exist[s] in a representative way for fellow human beings. It is not his or her specialization that distinguishes the teacher from others involved in upbringing. Instead, it is the depth of his or her passion and conviction, the direction of his or her interest, as well as the cultivation of her intelligence to this end. Fink emphasizes the terminology of the vocation and calling of the teacher, and speaks even of the internal mandate or inner life mission of the teacher. In her responsibility for the next generation, in exemplifying the relations between the generations, the educator is not just a mere technician in the transfer of cultural power that dominates at a given place and time. Instead, Fink continues, the teacher takes an active part in this power, takes part in shaping it, takes part as a subject or an active agent. He explains: It is the teacher who contributes and helps to shape the historic formation and living perpetuation of a comprehensive relation to world of a certain humanity. It is the teacher, in other words, who helps to shape the ongoing relation of a culture or collective to the world a relation characterized by a particular power and comprehensiveness. But what does Fink mean by power or in his description of this relation as comprehensive? And what might be some of the individual implications of these sweeping characterizations? To begin to address these questions, it is first important to recognize that Fink is speaking at this point not just of the teacher but of anthropology and ontology in the broadest sense. Fink s anthropology, understands human beings in terms of relation. 3 This relation is twofold, it is relation to the world, and also relation to oneself: [The human being] lives in relation to himself through understanding [Er lebt im verstehenden Selbstumgang]: He places himself into practical relation to his own existence [Dasein] and to the Being of all beings. However, such self relation is not a consequence of consciousness, it is not a conscious reflexivity, but rather a much more primordial and tension laden existential structure. The human being is his own task [ist sich aufgegeben ], he must become what he is, must look for and fulfil his essence or being. 3 E.g., see: Mario Ruggenini. Selbstbezug und Weltbezug Grundprobleme der Anthropologie Eugen Finks. In Anselm Böhmer (Ed. 2005) Eugen Fink: Sozialphilosophie Anthropologie Kosmologie Pädagogik Methodik. Pp. 141 153. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann.

3 The human for Fink is someone who lives in a relation to himself and to the world, not through a conscious and deliberate positing or positioning, but through practical habit, through familiar and customary ways of doing things, routine was of regarding oneself and the world around one. These customary relations of self to self and to world, their expression and reflection are what Fink means by culture, and he sees these at once as having a particular power to shape and perpetuate themselves, but also as entities subject to change, influence and individual agency. At the same time, though, these relations are tension laden. They compel the human being to regard him or herself, and his or her fulfilment, as a problem and a project. In this sense, human beings manifest a strange incompleteness, [an] existential imperfection that they are compelled to address. The questionability of the teacher is one that can be extended to the questionability of humanity as a whole. At the same time, Fink sees this fragmentary nature as the basis for human education and Bildung, and also for human freedom all of which are similarly incomplete and fragmentary in nature. The indeterminate and incomplete nature of the human being [Dasein] for Fink is the condition and precondition for the shaping of the educational imprimatur. Education, thus, has the formative task of working with this underdetermined and incomplete being. Its purpose, however, is hardly one of fulfilment and completion. Instead, it is to undertake the task of shaping the existential relations of self to world and self to self. Its formative task, in other words, is ultimately to foster a free, thinking relation of everyone to themselves, as Fink puts it. And this free thinking self relation according to Fink, must in turn be recognized as the basic life shaping humanforming power. However, there is a conspicuous circularity in this remark: A free thinking relation of oneself to onesself is at once the aim of Erziehung and Bildung, and also the basic power that is presupposed in them. In concluding my presentation, I show how this circularity both opens up and forecloses on possibilities for Fink s anthropology. These are possibilities, moreover, that have been the focus of this panel. For example, in some of his other work on education, Fink openly affirms the anthropology of the homo faber discussed by Fernando. Although Fink regards education as something that is intrinsically cultural and personal rather than rationally instrumental, the postwar era for Fink is one that is irremediably technological and scientific. Consequently, Fink advocates for the direct engagement of education with the contemporary, scientific and technological relation of human beings to their world. Fink speaks of a technical Bildung as necessary for his time. Sounding perhaps a bit like Marcuse, he explains that such an education must teach people to empower and meaningfully shape the richness of machine made products and the excess time that arises from technological automation. 4 But unlike Marcuse, Fink did not see sexuality or eros as something that would consequently be liberated or opened to experimentation or redefinition. Although Fink, writing in the Questionableness of the Modern Educator, acknowledges that we live in relationship to our own sexuality, he places 4 Eugen Fink. Technische Bildung als Selbsterkenntnis. Die Deutsche Schule: Zeitschrift für Erziehungswissenschaft und Gestaltung der Schulwirklichkeit 55(1963), 176 177.

4 unmistakeable limits on the freedom that might be exercised overall in one s relation to one s sexuality, oneself and the world. This is clear in his characterizations of the educator as taking part in [the] power of free reflection rather than as controlling or redirecting it; it is also evident in Fink s characterization of the ontological and broadly educational self relation as being not a consequence of consciousness but rather a much more primordial and tension laden existential structure. So although education is made possible in terms of our relation to the world and to ourselves, it hardly free to change these at will. The ability of the individual and of the educator for Fink is significantly limited by the fact that they exist in a history, culture and collectivity. This is registered in Fink s classical Greek vocabulary through the term Polis. Speaking specifically of the educator Fink emphasizes that the educator is one in whom the general will, the interest of the Polis, is glowing. In this regard, too, the educator is representative. Going even further, Fink describes sexuality in this context in terms of quasimythological characteristics of tender femininity and tenacious masculinity. Unfortunately, aspects of Fink s anthropology, like those of Heidegger s, tend towards the provincial and parochial, rather than being particularly open to the cosmopolitan; the elements he tends to affirm are ultimately proper to the traditional Gemeinschaft rather than the contemporary international Gesellschaft. To sum up my presentation and to speak to the other presentations in this panel, I want to emphasize that regardless of this and other significant moments, Fink did indeed attempt to stretch the normative boundaries of the human. He also perceptively brought the question of these boundaries into clear if not completely direct relation with education and the educator. Fink and philosophical anthropology generally can be said to offer valuable points of reference for thinking more radical possibilities for the technological, sexual and collective in terms of education and the relations between self and world. What Fink wrote of human beings in 1963 is certainly as true today as it was in his German post war milieu, namely, that We know a priori that human power is limited, but how it is limited, we do not know. 5 5 Fink, Technische Bildung, 175.