City and Soul in Plato s Republic. By G.R.F. Ferrari. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, Pp $17.00 (paper). ISBN

Similar documents
Plato's Republic: Books I-IV and VIII-IX a VERY brief and selective summary

Unpacking the City-Soul Analogy

Moral Psychology and Degenerate Regimes in Plato's Republic

The Problem of Freedom. Taylor Thompson, Columbia University

We have a strong intuition that considerations of moral rightness or

Internalization and the Philosophers Best Interest in Plato s Republic

CGSC 281/PHIL 181: Phil&Sci Human Nature Gendler/Yale University, Spring Reading Guide The Ring of Gyges: Morality and Hypocrisy

Socratic and Platonic Ethics

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Synopsis of Plato s Republic Books I - IV. From the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Plato s Defense of Justice in the Republic. Rachel G.K. Singpurwalla

404 Ethics January 2019 I. TOPICS II. METHODOLOGY

Plato s Philosopher Kings. The Sun, Line, and Cave

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

William Meehan Essay on Spinoza s psychology.

Rethinking Bernard Williams Criticism of the City-Soul Analogy in Plato s Republic (draft)

IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?''

Short Answers: Answer the following questions in one paragraph (each is worth 5 points).

(born 470, died 399, Athens) Details about Socrates are derived from three contemporary sources: Besides the dialogues of Plato there are the plays

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

Huemer s Problem of Memory Knowledge

Topic III: Sexual Morality

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

First Treatise <Chapter 1. On the Eternity of Things>

What Is Virtue? Historical and Philosophical Context

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

Review of Thomas C. Brickhouse and Nicholas D. Smith, "Socratic Moral Psychology"

[Glaucon] You have shown me a strange image, and they are strange prisoners.

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

To link to this article:

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

Review: The Republic Book 1: Book 2:

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Defining Civic Virtue

Plato and the art of philosophical writing


Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp

Stout s teleological theory of action

Plato's Epistemology PHIL October Introduction

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

THE ALLEGORY OF THE CAVE

LODGE VEGAS # 32 ON EDUCATION

The Divided Line from The Republic, Book VII by Plato (~380 BC) translated by G.M.A. Grube (1974), revised by C.D.C. Reeve (1992)

BOOK REVIEWS. The Philosophical Review, Vol. 111, No. 4 (October 2002)

Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism

What God Could Have Made

The cosmological argument (continued)

Kant On The A Priority of Space: A Critique Arjun Sawhney - The University of Toronto pp. 4-7

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

Metaphysics and Epistemology

Nancey Murphy, Bodies and Souls, or Spirited Bodies? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006). Pp. x Hbk, Pbk.

Aristotle s Doctrine of the Mean and the Circularity of Human Nature

Wednesday, March 26, 14. Aristotle s Virtue Ethics

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Practical Wisdom and Politics

Are Humans Always Selfish? OR Is Altruism Possible?

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

PLEASESURE, DESIRE AND OPPOSITENESS

Plato s Protagoras Virtue & Expertise. Plato s Protagoras The Unity of the Virtues

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

Judith Jarvis Thomson s Normativity

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things:

38 SEVENTEENTH-CENTURY NEWS

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

Pollock and Sturgeon on defeaters

Edinburgh Research Explorer

On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology. In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with

Philosophy & Persons

5 A Modal Version of the

Plato s Republic. Important Terms

The unity of the normative

HYBRID NON-NATURALISM DOES NOT MEET THE SUPERVENIENCE CHALLENGE. David Faraci

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Plato c. 380 BC The Allegory of the Cave (The Republic, Book VII) Socrates And now, I said, let me show in a figure how far our nature is enlightened

what makes reasons sufficient?

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026

Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge by Dorit Bar-On

CONTEMPORARY MORAL PROBLEMS LECTURE 14 CAPITAL PUNISHMENT PART 2

Philosophy Club

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

What conditions does Plato expect a good definition to meet? Is he right to impose them?

10 CERTAINTY G.E. MOORE: SELECTED WRITINGS

Knowledge in Plato. And couple of pages later:

Reasoning with the Irrational: Moral Psychology in the Protagoras

On happiness in Locke s decision-ma Title being )

F. Rachel Magdalene Universität Leipzig Leipzig, Germany

Evidential arguments from evil

Is not the love of learning the love of wisdom, which is philosophy? friends and acquaintances, must by nature be a lover of wisdom and knowledge?

PHILOSOPHY 5340 EPISTEMOLOGY

Reading Euthyphro Plato as a literary artist

Williamson on Knowledge, by Patrick Greenough and Duncan Pritchard (eds). Oxford and New

Montreat Honors Program Scholar s Day Class Discussion Preparatory Reading

Published in Analysis 61:1, January Rea on Universalism. Matthew McGrath

Selections of the Nicomachean Ethics for GGL Unit: Learning to Live Well Taken from classic.mit.edu archive. Translated by W.D. Ross I.

Transcription:

174 good cannot be friends does much to illuminate Socratic eudaimonism. The translation of the dialogue is an outstanding work of scholarship. The authors either transliterate the Greek or discuss the difficulty of almost every relevant term. Overall the book is essential reading for anyone seriously interested in this short but difficult dialogue. (I thank George Rudebusch, Terry Penner, and Christopher Rowe for helpful comments.) Department of Philosophy California State University Sacramento CA 95819 City and Soul in Plato s Republic. By G.R.F. Ferrari. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2003. Pp. 130. $17.00 (paper). ISBN 3-89665-1706. Rachel Singpurwalla In this subtle and interesting book, Ferrari argues forcefully for a new interpretation of the vexed analogy between the city and soul in Plato s Republic. Along the way he offers original insights into several of the most contentious features of the Republic, including Socrates aims in deploying the city-soul analogy and his account of the values and motives of the philosopher-king. In chapter 1, Ferrari presents a character study of Glaucon and Adeimantus intended to illuminate their request for a defense of justice. According to Ferrari, Glaucon and Adeimantus are reluctant quietists: though attracted to political rule, they have retreated from aspiring to it because they see their society, and in particular its democratic tendencies, as defective and so unworthy of their efforts. They have chosen instead to pursue self-contained excellence: the perfection of their souls. The brothers want a defense of justice that justifies this decision. Socrates aims, however, are more comprehensive. He endeavors to provide an account of justice that answers to their needs, while also moving them away from quietism by showing them in what circumstances and for what reasons they might pursue political rule. According to Ferrari, the analogy between the city and soul is designed to accomplish this goal. In chapter 2, Ferrari reviews a dominant interpretation of the city-soul analogy, as well as the problems for this approach, as discussed by Bernard Williams in his classic article, The Analogy of City and Soul in Plato s Republic. According to Williams, the city-soul analogy involves a commitment to two claims: (i) a city is F if and only if its people are F, and (ii) the explanation of a city s being F is the same as the explanation of a person s being F. Unfortunately, however, Socrates joint commitment to (i) and (ii) appears to be problematic. Williams Ancient Philosophy 27 (2007) Mathesis Publications

175 notes that by (ii) the just city and the just soul are structurally isomorphic, which means that each contains a rational, spirited, and appetitive element. Plausibly, the rational element in the city is made up of individuals who are ruled by reason, the spirited element is made up of individuals ruled by spirit, and the appetitive element is comprised of individuals ruled by appetite. But then the just city contains individuals who are ruled by spirit and appetite, and this conflicts with (i), since Socrates does not think that an individual who is ruled by spirit or appetite is just. Williams suggests that we might try to get around this problem by revising (i) in the following way: a city is F if and only if the leading, most influential or prominent citizens are F. But Williams notes that this revised principle conflicts with Socrates characterization of the democratic city. If the revised version of (i) is true, then the most prominent citizens of a democratic city would be like the democratic individual, namely, erratic people who pursue whatever they happen to desire. But this is not how Socrates describes the leading citizens the general populace who make up a democracy. Rather, the populace contains every kind of character type, including, presumably, timocratic, oligarchic, and philosophic sorts of individuals. Ferrari contends that we should reject both formulations of (i), along with the corresponding thought that the rational element in the city is made up of people ruled by reason, and so on. The just city and the just soul have the same structure and that is all that can be said for the relationship between them: The fact that an individual has a character constructed analogously to a certain kind of city does not entail that he should be a member of it; likewise, the analogy has nothing to say about whether the virtues of virtuous individuals are to be found in the members of any class within the virtuous city (44). As evidence for this, Ferrari notes that in Republic iv, Socrates characterizes the virtues of wisdom and courage differently when discussing individuals in the city and individuals considered in isolation. For example, the wise ruler knows what is good for the city, while the wise individual knows what is good for himself; similarly, the auxiliary is brave with regard to facing dangers in the city; the courageous individual is brave with regard to facing all kinds of dangers and temptations, more often of a personal nature. The same is true for justice and self-control. Ferrari is careful to note that the analogy does not rule out the notion that just individuals might inhabit the just city, or that wise individuals make up the guardian class, or that courageous individuals make up the auxiliaries, or even that the city is made up of self-controlled individuals. The analogy is simply silent on these matters; it does not allow us to peer into the souls of the individuals who inhabit the city. Ferrari holds that if, for example, the wise individual is the ruler in the city, and knows both what is good for himself and for the whole, then this is a result of regularities of human nature (and not in virtue of the analogy), such as the tendency of good statesmen to be thoughtful people, and of thoughtful people to know what is good for themselves. In chapter 3, Ferrari argues that we ought to understand the analogy as a pro-

176 portional metaphor or simile. A proportional metaphor or simile states or implies a ratio, and is convertible or reversible. So the correspondence of the city and the soul implies both a comparison of the soul to a city (e.g., reason is the ruler of the soul), and a comparison of the city to the soul (e.g., rulers are the intelligence of the city). According to Ferrari, it is these points of likeness not causal relations, nor relations of whole and part that bind each city to the equivalent soul and each soul to the equivalent city (65). Ferrari thinks that this pattern is exemplified more clearly still in the discussion of timocracy, oligarchy, and democracy. Ferrari argues for this by noting differences between the rulers of timocratic cities and the timocratic man. For example, the rulers in a timocratic city and the timocratic man differ in their attitudes to money: the rulers in a timocratic city are secretive and stingy with their money, but passionate about it, while the timocratic man is at first contemptuous about money, but later openly enjoys it. The timocratic man lives a complacent and unconflicted life, quite different from that of the rulers in the timocracy different not just in its circumstances but in its ethical and psychological tenor (68). Thus, the timocratic man has the character of that regime, not the character of the rulers in that regime. In the same fashion, Ferrari argues that the rulers in an oligarchy are not oligarchic men. Rulers in an oligarchy are specifically said to include the idle, spendthrift rich, which is the very opposite of the tightfisted oligarchic man. Again, the oligarchic man resembles the corresponding oligarchic city, not its rulers. And finally, as we have already seen, the people in a democracy are not democratic characters. Ferrari concludes chapter 3 by considering the payoffs of looking at the citysoul analogy in this way. He thinks that mapping the moral character of a city onto the soul invites us to see whole and at a stroke what we normally would not see whole and at a stroke (77). Conversely, mapping the soul onto the city allows us to see piecemeal what we normally see as a unity. In sum, The correspondence recommends a joint awareness of political macrocosm and microcosm, of society and of self as organized wholes, at the expense of one s habitual focus on self in society, self in relation to others (79). Moreover, Ferrari thinks that the analogy answers the brothers particular needs: by making the city and soul analogues and nothing more, Socrates defense of justice in the soul leaves out the external rewards of justice and so locates the value of justice in self-perfection. But by discussing the analogous city Socrates can also recommend a civic way of life and so discuss justice in its more conventional social sense. In addition, the analogy recommends a political stance that can reconnect the brothers to political rule by presenting an ideal the philosopher-king who rises above the external rewards associated with justice while still undertaking political rule. In the final chapter, Ferrari argues that only in two cases do the soul-types rule their corresponding cities: the tyrant is the ruler of the tyrannical city, and the philosopher-king is the ruler of the just city. In neither case, however, is this due to the workings of the city-soul analogy, but rather to certain particularities and

177 contingencies. The tyrant is the ruler of the tyrannical city because he has a natural propensity to reduce his city to an expression of his individual will so that he can maintain absolute power, and the philosopher-king rules the corresponding city because of the laws of the founders. According to Ferrari, in writing the Republic this way, Plato intends to contrast his ethical position with one articulated by Isocrates, who held that an individual should become self-controlled so that his soul provides a model for the structure of the city and its citizens, which in turn makes him fit to rule. Implicit in this view is that political rule is the greatest task a human can undertake a point of view that Glaucon at least might find compelling. Socrates, by contrast, thinks that the individual who aims to rule (the tyrant) is miserable, while the one who is not interested in ruling (the philosopher-king) is happy. For the philosopher-king, the highest good is philosophy, and thus he rules both the non-rational parts of his own soul and the city as a matter of necessity only. Ferrari s interpretation of the city-soul analogy, if successful, not only avoids the objections that Williams raises, but also suggests new ways of looking at certain central features of the Republic. I will now suggest, however, that we should hesitate to accept Ferrari s interpretation of the analogy, since it is incompatible with two important sets of textual evidence. I begin by quoting the two most difficult passages for Ferrari s interpretation. Both state that the psychological and moral attributes of a city are due to the psychology of its citizens, and both are used to justify Socrates comparison of the soul to the city. The first occurs at 435e-436a, where Socrates justifies his first transition from a discussion of the city to a discussion of the soul. He says: we are surely compelled to agree that each of us has within himself the same parts and characteristics as the city? Where else would they come from? It would be ridiculous for anyone to think that spiritedness didn t come to be in cities from such individuals as the Thracians, Scythians, and others who live to the north of us who are held to possess spirit, or that the same isn t true of the love of learning, which is mostly associated with our part of the world, or the love of money, which one might say is conspicuously displayed by the Phoenicians and Egyptians. (Grube/Reeve trans.) This strongly implies that Socrates thinks that the character of a city is due to the character of its citizens. The second passage is 544e, where Socrates justifies his transition from a discussion of degenerate cities to degenerate souls: And do you realize that of necessity there are as many forms of human character as there are of constitutions? Or do you think that constitutions are born from oak or rock and not from the characters of the people who live in the cities governed by them, which tip the scales, so to speak, and drag the rest along with them?

178 Here Socrates explicitly states that the cause of the political constitution of a city is the psychological constitution of its corresponding citizen. Indeed Jonathan Lear, in his influential article, Inside and Outside the Republic, seizes on these passages to defend a causal version of the dominant interpretation: the city and soul are analogous because, inter alia, just people rule just cities, timocratic people rule timocratic cities, and so on. Ferrari notes these passages, but his primary reason for dismissing them is to point to all of the evidence that suggests that there is not a causal or constitutive relationship between cities and souls of the same types. But this does little to explain Plato s purpose in making these claims that suggest otherwise. Ferrari argues that in each case Plato is giving a prima facie reason to expect characteristics at the level of the individual to reappear at the level of the city and vice versa, but that Plato goes on to deny this relationship (43, 50). But this attempt to explain away the conflicting textual evidence is unconvincing. Why would Plato explicitly justify his move from city to soul with certain claims but then put forward a picture that is at odds with those claims, without ever noting that the prima facie claim has turned out to be false? In the absence of an explanation for this, there is significant pressure to find an interpretation of the city-soul analogy that accommodates the natural reading of these two important passages. Ferrari s account also fails to explain another feature of the text: Socrates refers to prominent citizens in each type of city by the same names he uses to refer to the soul types that are analogous to that city. In the case of timocracy, for example, Socrates refers to both the ruling citizens in a timocracy and the timocratic soul as spirited (547, 550b), and as victory and honor-loving (548c, 549a, 550b). In the case of oligarchy, he refers to both the leading citizens in an oligarchy and the oligarchic soul as money-loving (551a, 553d). Moreover, we know from Republic ix that Socrates characterizes the parts of the soul in terms of their loves, so we know that a victory and honor-loving individual is dominated by the spirited part, and a money lover by the appetitive part (580d-581c). These passages suggest that the prominent citizens of a city type have the same broad psychological structure as the corresponding soul type. Ferrari might respond by conceding that individuals who rule in a timocracy and timocratic individuals are both victory and honor-lovers, but that this is where the similarity ends, and likewise for money-lovers. And indeed Ferrari does say that not every spirited person is a timocratic man (69); and, not every money-lover has the character of the oligarchic man (71). Ferrari seems to think, then, that you can be an honor-lover without having a timocratic soul; and you can be a money-lover without having an oligarchic soul. But if this is Ferrari s view, then it is incumbent on him to fill out this new taxonomy of Plato s moral psychology. Is the idea that there are various species of an honor-loving or money-loving soul? If so, then we need an account of the relevant differences, the psychological and ethical significance of these differences, and the explanation for why one honor-lover turns out one away, and another a different way. We should hesitate, however, to accept the idea that two individuals both of

179 whom love and are ruled by honor or money can have salient differences in psychological structure. Plato s aim in the Republic is to show us the effect of what we value on our psychological health and happiness. He argues that only someone who is ruled by reason, either his own or that of another, can achieve psychological harmony, since only reason can determine how we should live such that each aspect of ourselves is fulfilled (442c). But if this is one upshot of Socrates claim that reason should rule, then he ought to think that there is some principled reason why loving and being ruled by honor, for example, will give you a certain kind of life, and similarly in the other cases. Do we really want to say with Ferrari that one honor-lover lives a complacent, carefree life, while another suffers from inner turmoil? And similarly for money-lovers? If it is possible to value honor or money or freedom and live a fulfilling enough life, then Plato has lost one intuitive reason he might give us to aspire to having a soul ruled by reason. There are, then, significant obstacles to Ferrari s interpretation of the city-soul analogy. The textual evidence he must overcome, however, does not diminish the textual evidence he has accumulated in favor of his view. And thus, just as Ferrari must contend with the evidence discussed here, anyone who wants to defend the dominant interpretation must respond to Ferrari s evidence. A successful response to Ferrari s evidence should, I think, proceed in two stages. First, a defender of the dominant interpretation must show that the differences that Ferrari cites between the psychological account of the rulers of cities and the corresponding souls are only surface differences. Second, she must provide an explanation for the surface differences. One promising strategy could be to argue, along the lines mentioned above, that one of Plato s aims in the Republic is to show us the effect of what we value on both our interaction with others and our interaction with the various parts of ourselves. When he discusses the individual in the city, Socrates is interested in the effect of what we value on our social interactions; when he discusses the individual soul he is interested in the effect of what we value on our interaction with ourselves. A defender of the dominant interpretation could then argue that this difference in emphasis explains the variation between Plato s accounts of the individual in a city and the corresponding soul type. Given the richness of evidence that Ferrari has accumulated for his interpretation, however, this would indeed be a considerable project. In sum, then, Ferrari provides a powerful challenge to the dominant interpretation of the city-soul analogy. In particular, his discussion of Republic viii draws attention to important differences between the ruling citizens of a city and their corresponding soul types that have not been sufficiently noted. Consequently, anyone interested in understanding this central feature of Plato s Republic is well advised to come to terms with this slim but substantial book. Department of Philosophy Southern Illinois University at Edwardsville Edwardsville IL 62026