What is belief, such that first person authority can exist?

Similar documents
15 Does God have a Nature?

Rationality in Action. By John Searle. Cambridge: MIT Press, pages, ISBN Hardback $35.00.

Rawlsian Values. Jimmy Rising

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

The Assurance of God's Faithfulness

According to Russell, do we know the self by acquaintance? (hint: the answer is not yes )

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

Stout s teleological theory of action

1/12. The A Paralogisms

How Trustworthy is the Bible? (1) Written by Cornelis Pronk

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Craig on the Experience of Tense

Nancey Murphy, Bodies and Souls, or Spirited Bodies? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006). Pp. x Hbk, Pbk.

SHARPENING THINKING SKILLS. Case study: Science and religion (* especially relevant to Chapters 3, 8 & 10)

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Why Ethics? Lightly Edited Transcript with Slides. Introduction

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Calisthenics November 1982

FOREWORD: ADDRESSING THE HARD PROBLEM OF CONSCIOUSNESS

Evolution and Meaning. Richard Oxenberg. Suppose an infinite number of monkeys were to pound on an infinite number of

Chapter 15. Elements of Argument: Claims and Exceptions

1/10. Descartes Laws of Nature

BonJour Against Materialism. Just an intellectual bandwagon?

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII

Higher-Order Approaches to Consciousness and the Regress Problem

out in his Three Dialogues and Principles of Human Knowledge, gives an argument specifically

Dennett's Reduction of Brentano's Intentionality

Why Ethics? Lightly Edited Transcript with Slides. Introduction

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Realism and instrumentalism

xiv Truth Without Objectivity

Functions of the Mind and Soul

The knowledge argument

- 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance

A Scientific Model Explains Spirituality and Nonduality

CONSCIOUSNESS IS NOT THE HUMAN MIND

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

G = Omnipotent, omniscient, etc. P* =Rationality, P = Rationality,

A Lecture on Ethics By Ludwig Wittgenstein

Plato's Epistemology PHIL October Introduction

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition:

HANDBOOK. IV. Argument Construction Determine the Ultimate Conclusion Construct the Chain of Reasoning Communicate the Argument 13

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

17. Tying it up: thoughts and intentionality

William Meehan Essay on Spinoza s psychology.

Holtzman Spring Philosophy and the Integration of Knowledge

God is a Community Part 1: God

The Self and Other Minds

How to Write a Philosophy Paper

Comments on Saul Kripke s Philosophical Troubles

The Problem of Normativity

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

First Truths. G. W. Leibniz

Skepticism and Internalism

JUDICIAL OPINION WRITING

Philosophy of Mind. Introduction to the Mind-Body Problem

Reply to Hawthorne. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXIV, No. 1, January 2002

THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1. Dana K. Nelkin. I. Introduction. abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory.

Philosophy and Methods of the Social Sciences

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Thesis Statements. (and their purposes)

A Philosophical Critique of Cognitive Psychology s Definition of the Person

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

Mereological Ontological Arguments and Pantheism 1. which draw on the resources of mereology, i.e. the theory of the part-whole relation.

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Logical Puzzles and the Concept of God

EPISTEMOLOGY for DUMMIES

The Extended Mind. But, what if the mind is like that? That is, what if the mind extends beyond the brain?

SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5)

From Machines To The First Person

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order

AGENCY AND THE A-SERIES. Roman Altshuler SUNY Stony Brook

Possibility and Necessity

The Representation of Logical Form: A Dilemma

PHLA10 Reason and Truth Exercise 1

Artificial Intelligence Prof. Deepak Khemani Department of Computer Science and Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Trinity & contradiction

The nature of consciousness underlying existence William C. Treurniet and Paul Hamden, July, 2018

3. WHERE PEOPLE STAND

appearance is often different from reality, and it s reality that counts.

Kelly and McDowell on Perceptual Content. Fred Ablondi Department of Philosophy Hendrix College

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Department of Philosophy TCD. Great Philosophers. Dennett. Tom Farrell. Department of Surgical Anatomy RCSI Department of Clinical Medicine RCSI

Williamson, Knowledge and its Limits Seminar Fall 2006 Sherri Roush Chapter 8 Skepticism

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1

Aristotle and the Soul

On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology. In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle

What one needs to know to prepare for'spinoza's method is to be found in the treatise, On the Improvement

Reason fundamentalism and what is wrong with it John Broome For the Oxford Handbook of Reasons and Normativity, edited by Daniel Star

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Are There Moral Facts

Debate Vocabulary 203 terms by mdhamilton25

Course Learning Outcomes for Unit V

Carnap s notion of analyticity and the two wings of analytic philosophy. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle

Christ-Centered Critical Thinking. Lesson 6: Evaluating Thinking

REVIEW. St. Thomas Aquinas. By RALPH MCINERNY. The University of Notre Dame Press 1982 (reprint of Twayne Publishers 1977). Pp $5.95.

Transcription:

What is belief, such that first person authority can exist? Jimmy Rising December 12, 2002 In First Person Authority, Davidson asks why first person authority exists. First person authority is the peculiar knowledge that one has about one s own beliefs, accessible to that one without pain or penalty. Davidson asks why first person authority exists. I want to ask how belief can possibly admit first person authority. 1 Beliefs as Propositional Possessions I want to explore a particular analogy. Davidson argues that beliefs about propositions have as their informational content nothing more than the proposition believed. Consider another possession which shares this property: a piece of paper on which any given proposition is written. The goal in this exploration is to determine what other properties beliefs must have by how closely the analogy matches. The belief that I will consider is that George Washington was the first President. Beliefs exist as relationships between the believer and a proposition. This relationship is isomorphic to the relationship of a possessor to a possession, with the believer as the possessor. 1

The possessor can do a number of things with his piece of paper. He can pack the piece of paper away, make it more readily accessible, study it, or lose it. Let us suppose that for some reason, he cannot show it to others (to make it more like a proper belief), although he can tell others about its contents. However, with the proper scientific instruments, and through extended scrutiny or evasive methods, it is perfectly conceivable that others could determine the contents of the page, just like they could study a person s brain to determine its stored information, with instruments and physical and biological understanding. By analyzing the patterns of neuron firing and brain connections, and with time for analysis, anything in the brain ought to be open to third persons, although there remains the problem of translation. In contrast, the possessor of either the belief or the paper may check the nature of the proposition whenever he wants, without translation (it is without translation in the case of the paper if we assume that the possessor is also the author, as argued by Davidson). In all of these ways, the piece of paper is like a belief. I believe there are three (metaphysical) ways that these two differ: in immediacy, coherence, and activity. Beliefs appear to be immediately accessible. There is no noticeable process isomorphic to retrieving the page and reading it. Whether or not any work is needed to retrieve the belief, there is no work done in determining the contents of our current beliefs. One just knows. One does need to spend time and energy to explore the extents and implications of a proposition, but that is the case with both the belief and the paper. By coherence, I mean the following difference between beliefs and pieces of paper. When the possessor of the paper reads the text, he gains another belief, namely that the paper expresses the proposition that George Washington was the first President, as he wrote it at an earlier time to reflect his own belief on the subject. Even as he reads the page, he is forming this proposition. These new beliefs could in turn be isomorphic to additional pieces of paper, but with the result that there is a proliferation of beliefs-about-beliefs, something that does not happen for normal beliefs (unless it is made to happen intentionally). Beliefs are monadic enough that they are complete both in storage and use. 2

It also seems like beliefs are in some sense active. They present themselves for review or as lenses through which to view the rest of the world at the least provocation. In trying to interpret the world, we are forced to interpret it using the propositions that we hold true. If someone mentions the first President, it seems impossible to ignore one s belief about the specific referent of that phrase. In some ways, clearly, a belief is not like a piece of paper. It is not, however, obvious where, if anywhere, first person authority appears in these differences. Speed does not seem to be a necessary quality of what it means to know things as a first person. The coherence property I ascribed to beliefs could simply be a result of our ability to ignore information we do not need. All knowledge is active, both first person and third person knowledge, so it is not clear how that can be useful for distinguishing between the two. 2 First Person Authority At this point is it useful to describe what I consider to be the primary characteristics of first person authority before returning to these points in more detail. Davidson says that It comes closer to characterizing first person authority to note that the selfattributer [of a belief statement] does not normally base his claims on evidence or observation, nor does it normally make sense to ask the self-attributer why he believes he has the beliefs, desires, or intentions he claims to have. (4) The claim that self-attribution is not based on evidence may be an unjustified simplification. Our claims about our beliefs do come from data of our brain-state contents. It just so happens that our mechanisms for collecting that data are so streamlined and transparent that we do not notice. 3

Here, however, we need to tread carefully. These words conjure up images of an inner eye with an eye-stock sticking into the interior of the mind. Davidson ridicules this view, because it requires a separation between self, process, and information which cannot exist in a system as integrated as the brain (assuming that everything mental and subjective is subvenient on the brain). Consider the process of interpreting a belief, more carefully this time. In the first person case, the informational content of the belief is an essential part of the program which produces the claim. In the third person, a data-collection and interpretation program is run on whatever inputs it is given, and these inputs could be the the very information fed to the first program, but as an input to the second the result would be different. The difference might be the difference between the beliefs that I think George Washington was the first President and that Jimmy thinks that George Washington was the first President. Although the propositions are the same, as well as the other entity in the belief relationship (me), the nature of the belief is subtly shifted (and could have been shifted more). Based on the brain-data understanding of beliefs, it does make sense to ask why one believes that one has certain beliefs. However, because the process is different for these beliefs, the first person beliefs have coherence that the third person beliefs do not. Another way to understand this point is as an interpretation. The awareness of a belief is based on data, both in the first and third person. Moreover, the process of recognizing it as a belief and determining the contents of the belief must occur in both the first and third person. However, in the third person, this process of recognition involves evaluation and analysis. Not so for the first person. As a result, the third person has unignorable beliefs about beliefs (just like the possessor of the proposition-containing paper), while the first person does not. Davidson points out the role of interpretation in a complete understanding of first person authority. Davidson considers it the fundamental difference: There is a presumption an unavoidable presumption built into the nature of interpretation that the speaker knows what he means. So there is a presumption that if he knows the he holds a sentence true, he 4

knows what he believes (14). I agree that it is important, but I think it is only the tip of an iceberg of the differences. 3 Awareness and Its Consequences Evaluation and analysis are processes in the realm of objective reason. In as much as subjective considerations play a role in attempts at analysis, the analysis is biased and crippled. Reason is fundamentally third person. It acts by following the consequences of definitions which anyone might choose to explore. So long as reasoner make no mistakes in such an exploration, and if they follow the same lines of reasoning, they are forced into the same result. This is what makes reason so powerful. In fact, the difference between third person-ness and first person-ness is, from the point of view of reason, exactly first person authority. If two people have access to exactly the same information with the same immediacy, it is impossible for them to distinguish between each other. Nagle would say that the objective method is exactly the process of abstracting away the central-ness of oneself in one s own world. This is like the example of the two omnipotent gods, one of which is in a valley and one of which is on a mountain, but neither knows which one he is. A practical effect which makes this distinction easy is that our knowledge about the universe is centered at a particular place in space and time and takes effort to expand, but these differences do not appear fundamental. I keep using the phrase from the point of view of reason because there exist other methods of considering these problems of the nature of belief. I will present another, and some discussion to evaluate if it is appropriate for the task. To do this, I will be considering the ideas and arguments presented in Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance, which is far more about the philosophy of objectivity and subjectivity than about motorcycles. I want to introduce another concept into this discussion, which Davidson intentionally leaves 5

out: awareness. Awareness has a number of levels and object. One can be aware with respect to full propositions: I am aware that George Bush is the president of the United States or I am aware that I believe George Bush to the the president of the United States. More primitive awareness happens with respect to more direct things. I am aware of the words I am writing on this page. Or I am aware of the computer screen and the keyboard. Or I am aware of something in the tactile world and something in the visual world, but I have not yet recognized that it is the computer screen and keyboard and that they are related. Awareness also admits a kind of implicit interpretation. We are aware of thing as other things. This awareness is build on top of a set of beliefs. One can be aware of someone as English and try to interpret their words in to English (because one has the belief that they will speak English), but then have to revise that belief when the interpretation fails. Pirsig talks about awareness in the context of the problem of the time lag between perception and recognition, awareness and understanding. Any attempts to think rationally about things in one s environment have to have as their objects a more complete understanding of those things than possible in awareness, and that understanding exists only in the memory. Above, I said that from the point of view of reason, this time lag is not important. However, from a subjective standpoint, it is central. 4 First Person Authority as Awareness Consider the differences between the paper and the belief, this time considering the qualities that relate to awareness that is, the subjective qualities. Immediacy suddenly becomes more important in the context of time lag. Our very ability to think is based on this readiness or persistence of beliefs. Thought does not happen in the memory (we do not only remember having thought something); it happens in the present, even as we are simultaneously interpreting the present into future past. The object we think about in the present are things of the past, but the opinions we have about those things 6

are part of the thoughts themselves. Recognized objects are not pieces of our present, but beliefs are. Beliefs as an awareness also explain their coherence. It is not that beliefs have been already interpreted; they are awarenesses, and have not yet been interpreted. If I think about my belief that George Washington was the First President, I can ask if I know what those various elements of the belief mean, and ask many questions about the belief. The reason that the one question that is difficult to truthfully ask is do I believe this proposition is because I would have to ignore an aspect of the universe as I am currently aware of it to do that, namely the belief. The activity of beliefs takes a new meaning under subjectivity. No longer are beliefs objects of a rational process (although they are this from the point of view of reason). Subjectively, beliefs are agents or subjects which have the interpretation of other things as their object. The reason for this is nothing more than that everything subjectively is a free agent, because the understanding of what forces cause it to exist in a certain manner are in the realm of objective reason. One might object that really either beliefs are self-effected or they are not, but I think the truth of self-effecitity is in the relation of a thing to other things. These characteristics, which are essential to first person authority, cannot be understood just with reason. They concern awareness, which exists before reason. In other words, the objective conception of beliefs, that beliefs are rational relations between subjects and proposition, is incomplete. 5 Subjective Understanding The problem of what belief is, beyond any particular mode of understanding, is greater than can be considered in this paper. I only wish to outline one attempt, made by Pirsig in this direction. In exploring these ideas, he conjures up a train as a metaphor for life. 7

In my mind now is an image of a huge, long railroad train, one of those 120- boxcar jobs that cross the prairies all the time with lumber and vegetables going east and with automobiles and other manufactured goods going west. I want to call this railroad train knowledge and subdivide in into two parts: Classic Knowledge and Romantic Knowledge. In terms of the analogy, Classic Knowledge, the knowledge taught by the Church of Reason, is the engine and all the boxcars. All of them and everything that s in them. If you subdivide the train into parts you will find no Romantic Knowledge anywhere. And unless you re careful it s easy to make the presumption that s all the train there is. This isn t because Romantic Knowledge is nonexistent or even unimportant... Romantic Quality, in terms of this analogy, isn t any part of the train. It s the leading edge of the engine, a two-dimensional surface of no real significance unless you understand that the train isn t a static entity at all. A train really isn t a train if it can t go anywhere. In the process of examining the train and subdividing it into parts we ve inadvertently stopped it, so that it really isn t a train we are examining. This is the reason we have such a difficult time trying to describe subjective experience. It is because the process of describing it is the process of taking it apart and transforming it from romantic knowledge into classic knowledge. The process of taking apart a belief leaves only the proposition, but that is not all that a belief is. However, a belief is also a mental object in motion. The belief is that subjective object which contains the proposition of the belief. 8