Utilitas / Volume 25 / Issue 03 / September 2013, pp DOI: /S , Published online: 08 July 2013

Similar documents
Citation for the original published paper (version of record):

AN ACTUAL-SEQUENCE THEORY OF PROMOTION

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

DANCY ON ACTING FOR THE RIGHT REASON

CHECKING THE NEIGHBORHOOD: A REPLY TO DIPAOLO AND BEHRENDS ON PROMOTION

Why there is no such thing as a motivating reason

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS


Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives

Reasons as Premises of Good Reasoning. Jonathan Way. University of Southampton. Forthcoming in Pacific Philosophical Quarterly

Mill and the Footnote on Davies

STILL NO REDUNDANT PROPERTIES: REPLY TO WIELENBERG

Hume s Law Violated? Rik Peels. The Journal of Value Inquiry ISSN J Value Inquiry DOI /s

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Beyond Objectivism and Subjectivism. Derek Parfit s two volume work On What Matters is, as many philosophers

Practical reasoning and enkrasia. Abstract

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

SCHAFFER S DEMON NATHAN BALLANTYNE AND IAN EVANS

PRACTICAL REASONING. Bart Streumer

SCHROEDER ON THE WRONG KIND OF

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis

Do We Need to Make Room for Quasi-Supererogation?

FORCING COHEN TO ABANDON FORCED SUPEREROGATION

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

On the Connection between Normative Reasons and the Possibility of Acting for those Reasons

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

Aboutness and Justification

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Do We Need to Make Room For Quasi-Supererogation? Forbidden, The Indifferent and The Obligatory we must also make room for The

Objectivism and Perspectivism about the Epistemic Ought Conor McHugh and Jonathan Way University of Southampton. Forthcoming in Ergo

Stout s teleological theory of action

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

What is Good Reasoning?

The unity of the normative

hypothetical imperatives: scope and jurisdiction

THE CASE OF THE MINERS

Instrumentalism is the view that all requirements of practical reason can be derived

Propositional Attitudes and Mental Acts. Indrek Reiland. Peter Hanks and Scott Soames have recently developed similar views of propositional attitudes

Reasons With Rationalism After All MICHAEL SMITH

TWO ARGUMENTS FOR EVIDENTIALISM

Zimmerman, Michael J. Supererogation and doing the nest one can. American Philosophical Quarterly 30(4), October 1993.

Ought, Can, and Practical Reasons 1 Clayton Littlejohn

Can the lottery paradox be solved by identifying epistemic justification with epistemic permissibility? Benjamin Kiesewetter

Weighing Explanations

Action in Special Contexts

The fact that some action, A, is part of a valuable and eligible pattern of action, P, is a reason to perform A. 1

IS ACT-UTILITARIANISM SELF-DEFEATING?

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is

WHY WE REALLY CANNOT BELIEVE THE ERROR THEORY

ON PROMOTING THE DEAD CERTAIN: A REPLY TO BEHRENDS, DIPAOLO AND SHARADIN

Accounting for Moral Conflicts

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

The contrast between permissions to act and permissions to believe. Javier González de Prado Salas a. Universidad Autónoma de Madrid, Spain

The Good and the Right

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Two More for the Knowledge Account of Assertion

Is it Reasonable to Rely on Intuitions in Ethics? as relying on intuitions, though I will argue that this description is deeply misleading.

For the definitive version of this article, see Philosophical Studies. Normative Reasons as Good Bases

The normativity of content and the Frege point

A Contractualist Reply

Skepticism and Internalism

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 2. Background Material for the Exercise on Inference Indicators

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

what makes reasons sufficient?

Correct Beliefs as to What One Believes: A Note

holism, weight, and undercutting forthcoming in Noûs

PLEASESURE, DESIRE AND OPPOSITENESS

The Limits of Normative Detachment 1. Nishi Shah Amherst College Draft of 10/23/08

Correspondence. From Charles Fried Harvard Law School

DOES STRONG COMPATIBILISM SURVIVE FRANKFURT COUNTER-EXAMPLES?

RALPH WEDGWOOD. Pascal Engel and I are in agreement about a number of crucial points:

Lost in Transmission: Testimonial Justification and Practical Reason

AGAINST THE BEING FOR ACCOUNT OF NORMATIVE CERTITUDE

Royal Institute of Philosophy

Reply to Robert Koons

Moral Particularism and the Argument from Holism about Reasons

Attraction, Description, and the Desire-Satisfaction Theory of Welfare

Ethical non-naturalism

ARE THE MORAL FIXED POINTS CONCEPTUAL TRUTHS?

Abstract: According to perspectivism about moral obligation, our obligations are affected by

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Ethics.

EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION

Citation for published version (APA): Petersen, T. S. (2011). What Is Legal Moralism? Sats, 12(1), DOI: /sats.

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Democracy and epistemology: a reply to Talisse

THE BENEFITS OF COMING INTO EXISTENCE

OUGHT AND THE PERSPECTIVE OF THE AGENT


Reasons for action, acting for reasons, and rationality

CAN OBJECTIVISTS ACCOUNT FOR SUBJECTIVE REASONS? Daniel Wodak

Favoring. Antti Kauppinen Trinity College Dublin Forthcoming in Philosophical Studies.

Commitment: Worth the Weight To appear in Weighing Reasons, edited by Errol Lord and Barry Maguire, forthcoming from OUP

SEPARATING REASONS. David Dexter. Submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts

What s special about moral ignorance?

THE UNBELIEVABLE TRUTH ABOUT MORALITY

Rawls and Cohen on Facts and Principles

Transcription:

Utilitas http://journals.cambridge.org/uti Additional services for Utilitas: Email alerts: Click here Subscriptions: Click here Commercial reprints: Click here Terms of use : Click here A Millian Objection to Reasons as Evidence GUY FLETCHER Utilitas / Volume 25 / Issue 03 / September 2013, pp 417-420 DOI: 10.1017/S0953820813000095, Published online: 08 July 2013 Link to this article: http://journals.cambridge.org/abstract_s0953820813000095 How to cite this article: GUY FLETCHER (2013). A Millian Objection to Reasons as Evidence. Utilitas, 25, pp 417-420 doi:10.1017/s0953820813000095 Request Permissions : Click here Downloaded from http://journals.cambridge.org/uti, IP address: 192.41.128.64 on 24 Feb 2016

A Millian Objection to Reasons as Evidence GUY FLETCHER University of Edinburgh INTRODUCTION Stephen Kearns and Daniel Star have recently proposed the following theory of reasons: Reasons as Evidence: Necessarily,afactFisareasonforanagentA to iff F is evidence that A ought to (where is either a belief or an action). 1 In this article I present an objection, inspired by Mill s proof of the principle of utility, to the right-to-left reading of the biconditional. My claim is that the fact that you can perform some action can be evidence that you ought to do it without, itself, being a reason to do it. If this is true then Reasons as Evidence is false. 2 MILL S PROOF In chapter 4 of Utilitarianism, Mill argues for the hedonistic theory that pleasure alone is desirable. He claims that the only evidence that can be given for the view is that we desire pleasure alone. 3 One charitable way of reading Mill s argument is as combining the principle referred to as Ought Implies Can with the claim that we can only desire pleasure in order to conclude that pleasure alone is desirable (given that assumption that something is desirable). Mill s argument suggests an interesting kind of challenge to Reasons as Evidence. If the fact that you can in C is evidence that you ought to in C then, according to Reasons as Evidence, thefactthatyoucan in C is a reason to in C. This is prima facie problematic. Even those who think reasons come cheaply (that we have many more reasons than we usually report and more than we often believe or take ourselves to have) will baulk at the idea that you have a reason to in C simply 1 S. Kearns and D. Star, Reasons: Explanations or Evidence?, Ethics 119 (2008), pp. 31 56. 2 J. Brunero, Reasons and Evidence One Ought, Ethics 119 (2009), pp. 538 45, also argues against the right-to-left reading of Reasons as Evidence, using examples such as the fact that there is no reason not to. 3 J. S. Mill, Utilitarianism (1861). c Cambridge University Press 2013 Utilitas Vol. 25, No. 3, September 2013 doi:10.1017/s0953820813000095

418 Guy Fletcher because you can in C. 4 And notice that Reasons as Evidence would not only be committed to the claim that when you can perform some action then there is a reason to do it. Rather, it would be committed to the claim that this fact thatyoucanperformtheaction isareason to do it (in any case where ability to is evidence that one ought to ). It is tempting to hold that the fact that you can is never, itself,a reason to. 5 However, for my purposes, I do not need to defend that claim. Here I claim only that there is at least one case where being able to in C is not a reason to in C, whilst nonetheless being evidence that you ought to in C. I describe such a case below. Those who hold Reasons as Evidence must reply to the case in one of two ways. They must either (a) deny that being able to is evidence that you ought to in this case or (b) hold that being able to is areasonto in this case. CAN THE ABILITY TO BE EVIDENCE THAT YOU OUGHT TO? If an agent is unable to perform some action then it is not the case that she ought to perform that action. 6 This is a gloss on the principle ought-implies-can and some version of the principle seems undeniable for at least the kinds of ought claims relevant here, which are practical ought claims. 7 If we denied this principle we would be left seemingly unable to explain why it is not true that I ought to bring about world peace by clicking my fingers. 8 An analogous principle holds for reasons. Ihavenoreasontousemymicrowavetotravelbackintimeandbring about the early discovery of penicillin. The best explanation for this is the fact that I cannot perform this action. Given that ought implies can, your being unable to is conclusive evidence that it is not the case that you ought to.ifyouknowthatyou cannot perform some action then you know that it is not the case that you ought to perform that action. Because this is true, it is plausible 4 Hereafter I sometimes omit the in C clause, for brevity. 5 Putative counterexamples to this are nearly always cases that look to be handled by a pragmatic alternative explanation. 6 Note that the relevant claim is: it is not the case that they ought to perform the action. Itisnotthat:they ought not to perform the action. 7 The kinds of ought claims plausibly constrained by ought-implies-can are what are sometimes called deliberative, agential or practical ought claims. These are the only ought claims I discuss herein. For discussion of the different varieties of ought see M. Chrisman, Ought and Control, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 90 (2012), pp. 433 51; M. Schroeder, Ought, Agents, and Actions, Philosophical Review 120 (2011), pp. 1 41; and R. Wedgwood, The Meaning of Ought, Oxford Studies in Metaethics 1 (2006), pp. 127 60. 8 This type of argument is one used by B. Streumer, Reasons and Impossibility, Philosophical Studies 136 (2007), pp. 351 84.

A Millian Objection to Reasons as Evidence 419 to hold that on at least some occasions being able to is evidence that one ought to. 9 I grant that it does not always follow from P s implying Q that QisevidencethatP.Forwhethersomefactisevidenceforanother fact is dependent upon the background facts, and presumably there could be unusual cases in which being able to perform some action is evidence that it is not the case that one ought to perform the action. 10 Nevertheless, if there is any case in which being able to is evidence that one ought to without at the same time being a reason to,then Reasons as Evidence is in trouble. In this vein, consider the following example: Bone Marrow: Arenownedscientist,closetodevelopingtechnology that would reverse climate-change a century from now, needs a bonemarrow transplant. A hospital informs you that you are the only possible remaining candidate to be a bone-marrow donor and asks if you would mind being screened. You agree to be screened. You later find out that you are a match. My contention is that in this case your being able to donate bone marrow to the scientist is evidence that you ought to donate bone marrow to the scientist without being a reason to do so. Can Reasons as Evidence take Horn A to avoid the case? Horn A was: (a) Deny that being able to is evidence that you ought to in this case. This reply is implausible. In this case the stakes were such that you knew that you ought to donate your bone marrow if you were a match. You also knew that if you were unable to donate, this would be decisive evidence that it was not the case that you ought to donate. So when you discovered that you are in fact a match, you acquired evidence that you ought to donate your bone marrow to the scientist. Thus, Reasons as Evidence cannot avoid this case by denying that ability was evidence in this case. Can Reasons as Evidence take Horn B? Horn B was: (b) Hold that being able to is areasonto in this case. But this reply is implausible too. In discovering that you were able to donate bone marrow to the scientist you did not discover additional reasons to do so. You already knew what reasons there would be 9 Of course it will not often, if ever, be decisive evidence that one ought to, butit can still be some evidence that one ought to. 10 It might even be evidence that one ought not to perform the action.

420 Guy Fletcher to donate (the climate-change and subsequent suffering that would be prevented) if it turned out that you could donate. If, before the screening, you were asked what reasons you would have to donate, should you turn out to be a match, it would be false to include among them the fact that you would be able to donate (even though this was evidence that you ought to donate). Reasons are facts that count in favour of actions whereas the fact that you can perform an action is, in and of itself, normatively neutral. If my claims about the case are correct then Bone Marrow is a case in which the fact that you can is evidence that you ought to but not, itself, a reason to, pace Reasons as Evidence. A general feature of Reasons as Evidence one which explains the difficulty it has with Bone Marrow and why such a problem is generalizable is that it cannot allow reasons to have enabling conditions whose obtaining is evidence that an agent ought to. On the Reasons as Evidence view, such enabling conditions must, themselves, be reasons. 11 But ability to is an enabling condition of reasons to and so can be evidence that one ought to without being areasonto. 12 guy.fletcher@ed.ac.uk 11 On discussion of this see Brunero, Reasons and Evidence One Ought, and K. Setiya, What is a Reason to Act?, Philosophical Studies (forthcoming). For discussion of the reasons/enablers distinction, and its denial (the No Background View, in Schroeder s terms), see J. Dancy, Ethics Without Principles (Oxford, 2004), ch. 3, and M. Schroeder, Slaves of the Passions (Oxford, 2007), ch. 2. 12 Many thanks to Debbie Roberts, Alex Gregory, Daniel Star, Jonathan Way, and anonymous referees for comments and discussion.