Frege's Gedanken Are Not Truth Conditions

Similar documents
THREE LOGICIANS: ARISTOTLE, SACCHERI, FREGE

Carlo Penco. Frege, Sense and Limited Rationality *

The early Wittgenstein s truth-conditional conception of sense in the light of his criticism of Frege

This is a longer version of the review that appeared in Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 47 (1997)

The Collected Papers of Bertrand Russell, Vol. 4, Foundations of Logic: , ed. by Alsdair Urquhard (London: Routledge, 1994).

Frege on Knowing the Foundation

Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory.

Remarks on Frege's Conception of Inference

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Reply to Robert Koons

Do Demonstratives Have Senses?

Conceivability and Possibility Studies in Frege and Kripke. M.A. Thesis Proposal. Department of Philosophy, CSULB. 25 May 2006

If we can t assert this, we undermine the truth of the scientific arguments too. So, Kanterian says: A full

Frege on Truth, Judgment, and Objectivity

FREGE AND SEMANTICS. Richard G. HECK, Jr. Brown University

FREGE S CONTEXT PRINCIPLE: ITS ROLE AND INTERPRETATION 1

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

Coordination Problems

[3.] Bertrand Russell. 1

Could have done otherwise, action sentences and anaphora

Against the Contingent A Priori

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

(1) A phrase may be denoting, and yet not denote anything; e.g., 'the present King of France'.

Correspondence via the backdoor and other stories 1

Reply to Florio and Shapiro

Frege s Definition of Number: No Ontological Agenda?

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Foundations of Logic, Language, and Mathematics

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026

In Reference and Definite Descriptions, Keith Donnellan makes a

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Hybrid Proper Names WOLFGANG KUNNE

Todays programme. Background of the TLP. Some problems in TLP. Frege Russell. Saying and showing. Sense and nonsense Logic The limits of language

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

Analytic Philosophy IUC Dubrovnik,

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Russell on Denoting. G. J. Mattey. Fall, 2005 / Philosophy 156. The concept any finite number is not odd, nor is it even.

Why the Traditional Conceptions of Propositions can t be Correct

Philosophy of Logic and Language (108) Comprehensive Reading List Robert L. Frazier 24/10/2009

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

Assertion and Inference

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Draft January 19, 2010 Draft January 19, True at. Scott Soames School of Philosophy USC. To Appear In a Symposium on

Can logical consequence be deflated?

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

HORWICH S MINIMALIST CONCEPTION OF TRUTH: Some Logical Difficulties

Cantor on Frege s Foundations of Arithmetic

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

Donald Davidson had nearly completed this book when he died

Structuralism in the Philosophy of Mathematics

ROBERT STALNAKER PRESUPPOSITIONS

A Defense of Contingent Logical Truths

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives

To Appear in Philosophical Studies symposium of Hartry Field s Truth and the Absence of Fact

Putnam and the Contextually A Priori Gary Ebbs University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign

Truth and Disquotation

Dummett and Frege on sense and Selbständigkeit

TRUTH VIRTUAL ISSUE NO. 1. Tr u t h MICHAEL DUMMETT

Twentieth-Century Analytic Philosophy by Avrum Stroll

THE FREGE-GEACH PROBLEM AND KALDERON S MORAL FICTIONALISM. Matti Eklund Cornell University

Pragmatic Presupposition

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

Chalmers on Epistemic Content. Alex Byrne, MIT

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

What conditions does Plato expect a good definition to meet? Is he right to impose them?

Review Article Blueprint for a Science of Mind:

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn

Propositions as Cognitive Event Types

Prior, Berkeley, and the Barcan Formula. James Levine Trinity College, Dublin

BonJour Against Materialism. Just an intellectual bandwagon?

ON DENOTING BERTRAND RUSSELL ORIGINALLY PUBLISHED IN MIND 14.4 (1905): THIS COPY FROM PHILOSOPHY-INDEX.COM.

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Propositional Attitudes and Mental Acts. Indrek Reiland. Peter Hanks and Scott Soames have recently developed similar views of propositional attitudes

HOW FINE-GRAINED IS REALITY?

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Personal identity and the radiation argument

A defense of contingent logical truths

out of the closet frege s boots

Is the law of excluded middle a law of logic?

Paul Lodge (New Orleans) Primitive and Derivative Forces in Leibnizian Bodies

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

Truth, Assertion, and the Horizontal: Frege on The Essence of Logic William W. Taschek

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought

Worldlessness, Determinism and Free Will

Jan Harald Alnes SENSE AND BASIC LAW V IN FREGE S LOGICISM

MEANING AND RULE-FOLLOWING. Richard Holton

Transcription:

Facta Philosophica 4, 2002: 231-238 Peter Lang, Switzerland Frege's Gedanken Are Not Truth Conditions Ari Maunu 1 Thoughts as truth conditions Michael Dummett has put forward the view, amounting to orthodoxy, that Frege's notions of Sinn, or sense, and Gedanke, or thought, are closely connected to truth conditions of (indicative) sentences. Dummett writes (1976, 87): Sense, Frege says, determines reference: but this could be understood in either of two ways. On the strong interpretation, to know the sense is to know the condition for the expression to have a given reference; on the weak interpretation, it is just that two expressions with the same sense could not have different references. It is clear to almost everyone that we need the strong interpretation so far as the sense of a sentencea thought-is concerned: to grasp a thought is to know the condition for it to be true. 1 Similarly, David Wiggins claims in. a recent Companion that, on Frege's view, 'which thought it is that a sentence expresses and how the thought attaches to the sentence [ ] depend[s] upon nothing other than this: under what conditions is the sentence to count as true?' (Wiggins 1997, 4). 2 My aim in this paper is to argue that Dummett and others are mistaken in their claim that, (1) To grasp a thought is to know the condition for it to be true, is Frege's view of thoughts and the grasping of them. 2 Frege and the correspondence theory of truth The claim that Frege advocates (1) is in my opinion already refuted by the fact that according to Frege, there are no conditions of truth: Giving a condition by saying that something is true because of this-and-this leads 1 See also, for instance, Dummett 1959 (p. 7), Dummett 1973 (e.g. 5, 102, 229, 446, 457-9, 488-9, 499), Dummett 1975 (117-8, 121, 132-3), Dummett 1978 (xlii), Dummett 1981 (e. g. 71, 80, 249-52, 270). 2 See also e. g. Wiggins 1971 (p. 17), Wiggins 1976 (223n6), Blackburn 1975 (198).

232 Ari Maunu to nowhere since it may be asked whether it is the case that this-and-this, i.e. whether it is true that this-and-this. This derives from Frege's contention that the notion of truth cannot be defined; one cannot say in any illuminating manner what it is to be true; truth is an inexplicable, primitive notion. In particular, the correspondence theory of truth does not say anything substantial, on Frege's view. According to the correspondence theory, truth is agreement or correspondence with something: Whatever it is that is true a sentence, statement, proposition, thought, belief, idea, judgement, Carnapian intension (as applied to a possible world), etc. it is true if and only if it corresponds to 'reality' a 'fact', 'obtaining state of affairs', 'how things really are', or 'the real world'. Frege's most important objection to the correspondence theory is that any attempt of defining truth is bound to be circular and thus useless which exactly shows that to be true is a primitive notion. Frege's point is that even if we said that A is true since it corresponds to B, it would still be possible to ask whether it is true that A so corresponds to B. Frege expresses this in his most important paper, 'Der Gedanke' (1918), as follows (Kleine Schnften 344 (Collected Papers 353)): Could we not maintain that there is truth when there is correspondence in a certain respect? But which respect? For in that case what ought we to do so as to decide whether something is true? We should have to inquire whether it is true that an idea and a reality, say, correspond in the specified respect. And then we should be confronted by a question of the same kind, and the game could begin again. So the attempted explanation of truth as correspondence breaks down. And any other attempt to define truth also breaks down. For in a definition certain characteristics would have to be specified. And in application to any particular case the question would always arise whether it were true that the characteristics were present. So we should be going round in a circle. So it seems likely that the content of the word 'true' is sui generic and indefinable. [H Truth does not consist in correspondence of the sense with something else, for otherwise the question of truth would get reiterated to infinity. 3 The conclusion is that truth cannot be defined. This does not mean that it is incorrect to say, for instance: The thought that the Dalai Lama is wise is true if the world is such-and-such. Rather, the conclusion is that such a statement is utterly trivial and unsubstantial: CA fact [Tatsache] is a thought that is true.'4 It is clear that Frege does not accept the correspondence theory of truth precisely in the sense that there is no (substantial) condition such that it 3 Frege expresses this same objection over two decades earlier, in 1897; see Nachgelassene Schnften 139-40 (Posthumous Writings 128-9). 4 Kleine Schnften 359 (Collected Papers 368). See also e.g. Kleine Schriften 264n (Collected Papers 275n), Nachgelassene Schnften 140, 142 (Posthumous Writings 129, 131), Wissenschaftlicher Briefwechse1120 (Philosophical and Mathematical Correspondence 184n18).

Frege's Gedanken Are Not Truth Conditions 233 holds if and only if a given thought is true. However, the conception of thought entertained by Dummett and others, encapsulated in (1), apparently contains the claim that it is in Frege's theory proper to speak of conditions such as, (2) The thought expressed in the statement S is true if and only if the following condition holds: The condition C what else can Dummett mean by his talk of knowing the condition for a thought to be true than knowing something like 'the condition C' of (2)? However, it is precisely the conditions of the sort (2) Frege explicitly denies. Or, to be more precise, Frege can, and should, accept (2) in the trivial, unsubstantial sense in which it becomes, for example, something like (3) The thought expressed in the statement leibniz is a philosopher' is true if and only if Leibniz is a philosopher (i.e. iff the condition that Leibniz is a philosopher holds). However, Dummett does not take statements like (2) in this trivial sense, for according to him, 'we grasp the information that is conveyed by a sentence [i.e. its sense, i.e. the thought it expresses] just in case we know what is needed to establish it as true' (Dummett 1975, 132) and 'the truthand falsity-conditions for any sentence [ ] should [ ] be taken as ones which we are capable of recognizing effectively whenever they obtain' (Dummett 1973, 467). In numerous passages like the ones just given Dummett, quite unjustifiedly, imposes on Frege some sort of verificationist theory of truth. Also, Dummett 1973 (458-9) contrasts the redundancy (or deflationary) theory of truth according to which, roughly, truth is fully explicated by giving instances such as `"Leibniz is a philosopher" is true if and only if Leibniz. is a philosopher' with genuine or substantial truthconditions, opposing the redundancy conception precisely because it is trivial, or makes us 'impotent to explain the link between meaning and truth, and, in particular, to represent a grasp of meaning as a knowledge of truth-conditions' (Dummett 1973, 459). 5 5 Thus, Dummett seems to think that Frege would dispute the redundancy theory. This is a curious opinion in view of Frege's many apparent avowals of such a theory (see note 8 below). However, I shall not go into this matter here because the purpose of this paper is not to study theories of truth, and not even to consider which theory, if any, Frege accepts, but just to point out that Frege does not really explicate his notion of thought by means of truth conditions. (After all, (1) is not a formulation of a truth theory of any kind.)

234 Ari Maunu 3 Grundgesetze I, 32 To back up their account of thoughts in terms of truth conditions, Dummett and others appeal to the following passage in Grundgesetze der Arithmetik, Band I, 32: 6 Not only a referent [Bedeutung], but also a sense, appertains to all names correctly formed from our signs [of Begriffsschrift, i.e. Frege's formal system]. Every such name of a truth value [i.e. every statement (Satz)] expresses a sense, a thought. Namely, by our stipulations [for the basic signs of Begriffsschnft, cf. below], it is determined under which conditions the name denotes the True. The sense of this name the thought is the thought that these conditions are fulfilled. [Last two emphases mine.] Even though Frege may seem to confirm the 'thought is a truth condition' claim (1) in this passage, the following fact speaks against the claim that Frege is here 'clefinin. g' the notion of a thought by means of truth conditions: After his introduction, in 1891, of the notions of sense and thought, Frege is struggling to spell out definitely what he means by them. If he is giving here, in 1893, a truth-conditional conception of thoughts, what would have been more easier for him than to assert always, when talking about thoughts, that he means by them the conditions of truth? However, this seems to be the only place where Frege even appears to be talking about truth conditions (in reality, as we are about to see, he is not). More importantly, what Frege is actually saying in this passage can be shown to amount to nothing more than the following (for instance): A statement such as `Leibrużis a philosopher' expresses the thought that Leibniz is a philosopher. In order to see this, let us apply what Frege says in the quoted passage from 32 to a particular case: In 7 of Grundgesetze IFrege gives the following 'stipulation': T = A' shall denote the True if F is the same as A; in all other cases it shall denote the False. 7 6 See, for instance, Dummett 1981 (80, 250, 252), Wiggins 1997 (4). 7 This is not a definition of the sign `.-=' cf. Grundgesetze der Arithmetik, Band II 146n. In a (nominal) definition a new sign is introduced by means of previously introduced signs of the system at hand but one must obviously always presuppose something as already given when one starts to construct a system: Not everything can be defined' (Nachgelassene Schriften 290 (Posthumous Writings 271)). In the present case, the notion of identity is assumed to be known in advance, and it is here just told or 'stipulated' that `-=' is to be the sign for identity. It is in fact Frege's view that identity cannot be defined at all, because the notion of identity must be utilized in any definition; see especially Kleine Schnften 184 (Collected Papers 200).

Frege's Gedanken Are Not Truth Conditions 235 Here 'F' and 'X are not schematic letters or variables in any sense but are used 'as if they were names denoting something, although [ ] their denotation' is left 'unspecified' (Grundgesetze I 5n); and in 'the developments of the Begriffsschrift itself they will occur no more than will [placeholders such as] " a" and "C"' (ibid.). It is thus clearer and in fact more correct to consider an example with real singular terms (Frege's Eigennamen) such as '3 6' and '739'. Accordingly, the following is an instance of the stipulation Frege gives in 7 of Grundgesetze `3 6 =739' denotes the True if 3 6 is the same as 739; in all other cases it denotes the False. Applying this to what Frege says in 32, quoted above, we have: The thought expressed by `3 6 =739' is the thought that the condition that 3 6 is the same as 739 is fulfilled. Here, it is obvious that 'the thought that the condition that 3 6 is the same as 739 is fulfilled' means precisely the same as, 'the thought that it is true that 3 6 is the same as 739'. The latter, in turn, says no more and no less than 'the thought that 3 6 is the same as 739', as Frege explicitly states over and over again. 8 Thus, what Frege is really saying in 32, is, as applied to our case, (4) The thought expressed by '3 6=739' is the thought that 3 6 is the same as 739. Thus, what Frege is saying in 32 turns out to be entirely trivial in view of the 7 stipulation of the use of the identity sign '='. 9 In particular, there is no 'condition of truth' trivial or not to be found in (4) at all. All in all, the often cited 32 fails to give any support for the claim (1). It is not a sound objection that this analysis is problematic just because it makes Frege's statement in Grundgesetze I 32 trifling. There are myriads of trivial statements in the writings of philosophers this does not constitute a reason for looking for some secret deep meaning in them. For example, when a philosopher of language states, 'A singular term purports to refer to an in. dividual', we do not presume that since such a triviality is hardly worth stating, something else is secretly meant. I think Frege is in 32 only mentioning in passing what he means by his term Gedanke' viz., that it is what is expressed. Frege has no reason for saying anything really substantial in this connection. 8 See e. g. Kleine Schriften 345, 347, 361 (Collected Papers 354, 356, 370); Nachgelassene Schriften 138, 153-4, 211, 251-2, 271-2 (Posthumous Writings 127, 141-2, 194, 233-4, 251); Wissenschaftlicher Briefwechsel 245 (Philosophical and Mathematical Correspondence 163). 9 Cf. here Haaparanta 1985 (69-70).

236 Ari Maunu 4 Thoughts What I think is Frege's foremost characterization of the notion of thought is that thoughts are something for which the question of truth arises in the first place, or just something serving as bearers of truth values. Frege quite often presents this rather an abstract explanation; he says that a thought is 'something of which one can say that it is true' (Kleine Schriften 316 (Collected Papers 332)); that c[a] criterion for whether a mode of connection [ VerknUpfung] constitutes thinking [i.e. thought-grasping] g] is that it makes sense to ask whether it is true or untrue' (Nachgelassene Schriften 189 (Posthumous Writings 174)); that `[w]hat is capable of being judged true or false [ ] alone is of concern to logic and is what I call the thought expressed' ( Wissenschaftlicher Briefwechsel 106 (Philosophical and Mathematical Correspondence 70-1)); that `[a] statement must have a sense if it is to be useful [ ; w]ithout a sense, we would have no thought, and hence also nothing that we could recognize as true' (Wissenschaftlicher Briefwechsel 127-8 (Philosophical and Mathematical Correspondence 79-80)); and that he `introduce[s] a thought as that to which the question "Is it true?" is in principle applicable'l (Nachgelassene Schriften 273 (Posthumous Writings 253)). Further, in 'Der Gedanke' we find (Kleine Schriften 344-6 (Collected Papers 353-5)): Without offering this as a defmition, I mean by 'a thought' something for which the question of truth can arise at all. [ ] A command [ has a sense], but this sense is not such that the question of truth could arise for it. Therefore I shall not call the sense of a command a thought. For Frege, there are no conditions or circumstances that somehow determine whether a truth is true (so to speak), e.g. conditions under which a statement is true. 11 Ari Maunu University of Turku Department of Philosophy FIN-20014 Turku ari.maunu@utu.fi 10 Compare: An object perceptible by sight is that to which the question 'Is it blue?' is in principle applicable. (And not that with respect to which we ask: Under which conditions is it to count as blue?) 11 Cf. here Kemp 1995 (39-40). I wish to thank the anonymous referee of Facta Philosophica for constructive criticism of an earlier version of this paper.

Frege's Gedanken Are Not Truth Conditions 237 References Blackburn, S. (1975), The Identity of Propositions', in Blackburn, S. (ed., 1975), Meaning, Reference and Necessity: New Studies in Semantics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 182-205. Dummett, M. (1959), 'Truth', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 59,141 62. Page references are to the reprint, with a postscript (1972), in Dummett, M. (1978), Truth and Other Enigmas, London: Duckworth, 1-24. Dummett, M. (1973), Frege: Philosophy of Language, London: Duckworth. (Second rev. ed. 1981.) Dummett, M. (1975), Trege's Distinction between Sense and Reference', in Dummett, M. (1978), Truth and Other Enigmas, London: Duckworth, 116-44. Dummett, M. (1976), Trege As a Realist', Inquiry 19, 455-68. Page references are to the reprint in Dummett, M. (1991), Frege and Other Philosophers, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 79-96. Dummett, M. (1978), Truth and Other Enigmas, London: Duckworth. Dummett, M. (1981), The Interpretation of Frege's Philosophy, London: Duckworth. Frege, G. (1893), Grundgesetze der Arithmetik, begnffsschnftlich abgeleitet, Band I, Jena: H. Pohle. Reprinted 1962, Darmstadt: G. Olms. Partial English translation in Frege, G. (1964), The Basic Laws of Arithmetic: Exposition of the System, ed. & tr. M. Furth, Berkeley: University of California Press, 1-126. Frege, G. (1903), Grundgesetze der Arithmetik, begriffsschnftlich abgeleitet, Band II, Jena: H. Pohle. Reprinted 1962, Darmstadt: G. Olms. Partial English translation in Frege, G. (1952), Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege, ed. & tr. P.T. Geach & M. Black, Oxford: Blackwell (second ed. 1960), 159-233; and in Frege, G. (1964), The Basic Laws of Arithmetic: Exposition of the System, ed. & tr. M. Furth, Berkeley: University of California Press, 127-43. Frege, G. (1967), Kleine Schnften, ed. I. Angelelli, Hildesheim: G. Olms. Frege, G. (1969), Nachgelassene Schnfien, ed. H. Hermes, F Kambartel & F Kaulbach, Hamburg: Felix Meiner. (Second rev. ed. 1983.) Frege, G. (1976), Wissenschaftlicher Briefivechsel, ed. G. Gabriel et al., Hamburg: Felix Meiner. Frege, G. (1979), Posthumous Writings, ed. H. Hermes, F Kambartel & F Kaulbach, tr. P. Long & R. White, Oxford: Blackwell. Frege, G. (1980), Philosophical and Mathematical Correspondence, ed. G. Gabriel et al., tr. H. Kaal, Oxford: Blackwell.

238 Ari Maunu Frege, G. (1984), Collected Papers on Mathematics, Logic, and Philosophy, ed. B. McGuinness, tr. H. Kaal et al., Oxford: Blackwell. Haaparanta, L. (1985), Frege's Doctrine of Being, Acta Philosophica Fennica 39. Kemp, G. (1995), 'Truth in Frege's "Law of Truth', Synthese 105,31-51. Wiggins, D. (1971), 'On Sentence-sense, Word-sense and Difference of Word-sense: Towards a Philosophical Theory of Dictionaries', in Steinberg, D.D. & Jakobovits, L.A. (ed., 1971), Semantics: An Interdisciplinary Reading in Philosophy, Linguistics and Psychology, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 14-34. Wiggins, D. (1976), 'Frege's Problem of the Morning Star and the Evening Star', in Schirn, M. (ed., 1976), Studies on Frege Vol. H: Logic and Philosophy of Language (Studien zu Frege Band Logik and Sprachphilosophie), Stuttgart: Frommann-Holzboog, 221-55. Wiggins, D. (1997), 'Meaning and Truth Conditions: From Frege's Grand Design to Davidson's', in Hale, B. & Wright, C. (ed., 1997), A Companion to the Philosophy of Language, Oxford: Blackwell, 3-28.