Aristotle and Aquinas

Similar documents
Thomas Aquinas The Existence of God can be proved in five ways.

Five Ways to Prove the Existence of God. From Summa Theologica. St. Thomas Aquinas

Categories and On Interpretation. Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey

Scholasticism In the 1100s, scholars and monks rediscovered the ancient Greek texts that had been lost for so long. Scholasticism was a revival of

Proof of the Necessary of Existence

The Divine Nature. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 3-11) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian J.

The Five Ways of St. Thomas in proving the existence of

The Unmoved Mover (Metaphysics )

The Five Ways THOMAS AQUINAS ( ) Thomas Aquinas: The five Ways

Aquinas, The Five Ways

First Treatise <Chapter 1. On the Eternity of Things>

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII

Summer Preparation Work

Aquinas s Third Way Keith Burgess-Jackson 24 September 2017

Aristotle. Cause, Purpose and the Prime Mover

The Five Ways. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Question 2) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006) Question 2. Does God Exist?

P. Weingartner, God s existence. Can it be proven? A logical commentary on the five ways of Thomas Aquinas, Ontos, Frankfurt Pp. 116.

Avicenna, Proof of the Necessary of Existence

There Must Be A First: Why Thomas Aquinas Rejects Infinite, Essentially Ordered, Causal Series

John Duns Scotus. 1. His Life and Works. Handout 24. called The Subtle Doctor. born in 1265 (or 1266) in Scotland; died in Cologne in 1308

Chapter Six. Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality

Monday, September 26, The Cosmological Argument

Aquinas, The Divine Nature

Dartmouth College THE DIVINE SIMPLICITY *

ARTICLE PRESENTATION, EXAMPLE 2: AQUINAS PHI 101: INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY DR. DAVE YOUNT

by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB

On Being and Essence (DE ENTE Et ESSENTIA)

Aquinas 5 Proofs for God exists

St. Thomas Aquinas Excerpt from Summa Theologica

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

The cosmological argument (continued)

Previous Final Examinations Philosophy 1

Thomas Aquinas The Treatise on the Divine Nature

Lecture 4.2 Aquinas Phil Religion TOPIC: Aquinas Cosmological Arguments for the existence of God. Critiques of Aquinas arguments.

Stout s teleological theory of action

The Creation of the World in Time According to Fakhr al-razi

From Physics, by Aristotle

The Ten Categories of Being. The Primacy of Substance

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

WHAT ARISTOTLE TAUGHT

The Cosmological Argument

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION AND ARISTOTELIAN THEOLOGY TODAY

McKenzie Study Center, an Institute of Gutenberg College. Handout 5 The Bible and the History of Ideas Teacher: John A. Jack Crabtree.

Do you have a self? Who (what) are you? PHL 221, York College Revised, Spring 2014

II. In what way does the Unmoved Mover cause what it causes?

METAPHYSICS. The Problem of Free Will

Teleological: telos ( end, goal ) What is the telos of human action? What s wrong with living for pleasure? For power and public reputation?

QUESTION 3. God s Simplicity

Topics and Posterior Analytics. Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey

Disputation 20. On the First Efficient Cause and on His First Action, Which Is Creation

In Search of a Contemporary World View: Contrasting Thomistic and Whiteheadian Approaches Research Article

Philosophy is dead. Thus speaks Stephen Hawking, the bestknown

Today we begin our discussion of the existence of God.

Thomas Aquinas on the World s Duration. Summa Theologiae Ia Q46: The Beginning of the Duration of Created Things

From Aristotle s Ousia to Ibn Sina s Jawhar

On The Existence of God Thomas Aquinas

First Principles. Principles of Reality. Undeniability.

Plato s Euthyphro. G. J. Mattey. Spring, 2017 / Philosophy 1. Our first text will be from Plato and centered around his teacher Socrates ( BC).

The Platonic tradition and concepts of Freewill

Ibn Sina on Substances and Accidents

Does God Exist? Understanding arguments for the existence of God. HZT4U1 February

Sufficient Reason and Infinite Regress: Causal Consistency in Descartes and Spinoza. Ryan Steed

Plato s Euthyphro. G. J. Mattey. Winter, 2006 / Philosophy 1. Our first text will be from Plato and centered around his teacher Socrates ( BC).

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination

Kant s Transcendental Idealism

Lewis quoted Haldane: The Human Quest for Knowledge

Genus and Differentia: Reconciling Unity in Definition

Being and Substance Aristotle

KNOWLEDGE AND OPINION IN ARISTOTLE

Jewish and Muslim Thinkers in the Islamic World: Three Parallels. Peter Adamson (LMU Munich)

Secular Thought in the Islamic Golden Age

What God Could Have Made

Necessary and Contingent Truths [c. 1686)

Cartesian Aseity in the Third Meditation

William Ockham on Universals

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order

A New Argument Against Compatibilism

6. Topic # 1: Relativism and Truth

QUESTION 44. The Procession of Creatures from God, and the First Cause of All Beings

Spinoza, Ethics 1 of 85 THE ETHICS. by Benedict de Spinoza (Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata) Translated from the Latin by R. H. M.

QUESTION 19. God s Will

The Question of Metaphysics

- 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance

By J. Alexander Rutherford. Part one sets the roles, relationships, and begins the discussion with a consideration

On Generation and Corruption By Aristotle Written 350 B.C.E Translated by H. H. Joachim Table of Contents Book I. Part 3

Chapter 2: Reasoning about ethics

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

God, Natural Evil and the Best Possible World

From Physics, by Aristotle

3 The Problem of Absolute Reality

3. So, what-is-not cannot be the reason for saying that what-is was, or will be [i.e., what what-is grew out of or will grow into].

ST. THOMAS AQUINAS SUMMA THEOLOGICA

Anthony P. Andres. The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic. Anthony P. Andres

Thomas Aquinas. Summa Theologiae la Translated, with Introduction and Commentary, by. Robert Pasnau

Cosmological arguments for the Existence of God Gerald Jones Dialogue Issue 26 April 2006

FACULTY OF ARTS B.A. Part II Examination,

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

Aristotle. Aristotle was an ancient Greek Philosopher who made contributions to logic, physics, the

RCIA 2 nd Class September 16, 2015

DESCARTES ON THE OBJECTIVE REALITY OF MATERIALLY FALSE IDEAS

Transcription:

Aristotle and Aquinas G. J. Mattey Spring, 2017 / Philosophy 1 Aristotle as Metaphysician Plato s greatest student was Aristotle (384-322 BC). In metaphysics, Aristotle rejected Plato s theory of forms. Most importantly, he rejected Plato s claim that forms are distinct from the things that share in them. As a result, Aristotle gave natural science a central role in his philosophy and linked his metaphysics closely to the investigation of nature. In this segment, we will investigate excerpts from two of Aristotle s works: Metaphysics (metaphysics) Physics (natural science) Later, we will see how Aristotle s philosophy was adapted for Christianity by Thomas Aquinas. Plato s Account of Kinds Plato s general account of how a thing is of a kind: Form causes Quality in Thing An example of how a thing (some wine in a goblet) is of a kind (cold): Coldness itself causes The wine s coldness in The wine 1

Criticisms of Plato We saw in the last set of slides that Aristotle criticized Plato s theory of forms in three basic ways. There would be forms for things which should not have forms, such as negations and relatives. It is redundant to introduce separately existing forms if things have qualities that allow them to be sorted into kinds. The forms do not suffice to account for change in the natural world. We will now discuss Aristotle s remedies for these problems. Accident and Essence Plato used the word form (Greek: eidos) to describe what makes a thing the kind of thing that it is. Aristotle agreed with this usage, but he disagreed with the way in which it is applied to things. Only some of what can be said about a thing describe the kind of thing it is. Consider two cases: Socrates is pale (i.e., has pale skin). Socrates is human. The first case involves a quality that Socrates might or might not have (as he could spend more time in the sun). The second case involves a quality that Socrates must have if he is to be Socrates. Accidents A quality that a thing might or might not have is called an accident or incidental of the thing. In his book Categories, Aristotle described nine different sorts of accidents (with examples in parentheses). Quality, in a narrow sense (white), Quantity (two feet long), Relative (larger), Where (in the Lyceum), 2

When (yesterday), Being in a position (sitting), Having (has shoes on), Acting on (cutting), Being acted on (being cut). Essences In contrast to accidents, the essence of a thing or subject is what that subject is. The essence of a thing can be given in a definition. Socrates is (in essence) human. To be human is to be a rational animal. Species The essence of Socrates is to be human, and humanity is called the species to which he belongs. The accident, Socrates s being pale, also belongs to a species, paleness, and so on with the other accidents. In one sense, for Aristotle, the form is identified with the species. The form of Socrates is to be human. The form of Socrates s being pale is paleness. Thus far, the view of Aristotle appears to be the same as that of Plato. For example, a relative, such as being taller than, has a species, and hence a form. Limiting the Range of Forms Not all grouping of things into kinds, however, call for forms. The species are restricted to what is essential and what is accidental. Both essence and accident are described positively, as what something is. So if form is species, negations (Socrates is not dark) would lack a form. More generally, the range of forms is constrained by the account of what can be an essence or an accident. For example, pale human is not an essence, nor is it an accident of anything. 3

Immanence For Aristotle, the essence of a thing is in the thing rather than existing separately, as Plato held. What is in a thing can be said to be immanent. The restiction of the forms to what is immanent answers the criticism that separately existing forms are redundant. Thus, being rational and being human are in Socrates as well as in all other human beings. Plato might respond by asking how the essences and accidents can be shared by many things unless there is a one over many that accounts for the sameness of essence in the things. Put in another way, if a form is a species, how could the species be shared by many objects unless it were itself a separate object? Do Forms Have Causal Powers? Aristotle might reply that the forms must be in the things, because if they were not, they could not be causes. A cause, for Aristotle, is what answers the question why a thing is as it is. For example, one form of change is change of the accident being in a position. We call this change motion. The evidence of the senses is that the motion of one thing is caused by the motion of another thing. Object A has the accident acting on object B, and this action is the source of B s movement. Then it is not the form or species, acting on, but rather A s action itself, that causes B to be acted upon. Forms as Causes In fact, Aristotle allowed that forms can be understood as causes. Form is one of four distinct kinds of causes. The formal cause applies to things that do not involve motion. 4

Consider, for example the causes of forms themselves. The species human being is defined as rational animal. The genus animal is part of this definition and could be said to be a cause of the species human being. Other formal causes can be found in the realm of numbers. The relation of 2 : 1 is the cause of the octave. In a concrete thing, the whole (e.g., a table) is the cause of its parts (e.g., its legs and top). Matter as Cause The relation of the table to the wood suggests a second kind of cause. That out of which a thing comes to be and which persists is considered a kind of cause of the thing. The wood of which a table is composed is its material cause. Like the formal cause, the material cause is not dynamic, in the sense that it is not an account of how a thing changes. The Agent as Cause What forms fail to be able to account for is the initiation of change. One way to answer the question why did this change come about? is by citing the agent that brought it about. The wood-worker is the agent who created the table (from its material cause, the wood). Change of motion is perhaps the most important kind of change that is explained by the agent. Starting and stopping, Speeding up and slowing down, Re-directing. 5

The End as Cause The fourth kind of cause identified by Aristotle is the end for which an object exists. The end of the construction of the table is to provide a stable, expansive, level surface for conducting various activities. Stating the end is a way of explaining why a thing is as it is. Teleology and Necessity Aristotle claims that nature acts for a purpose, rather than from blind necessity. If nature did not act for a purpose, its ends would be brought about by chance. The specialized functions of the parts of animals would be the products of chance. But to be brought about by chance is to be unusual, which the products of nature are not. Nature works teleologically, as do crafts: there is an end (telos) which nature has the means to bring about. In Defense of Teleology Apparent irregularities in nature can be explained as the result of failure to achieve the end, rather than by chance. Moving toward an end does not require deliberation, so nature does not need to deliberate in order to achieve its ends. The causes that are needed for the production of a thing need only be material. Necessity is found in the end, rather than in the antecedent conditions that produce something. Terminal Causes Aristotle argued that in any series of causes, there must be a terminal cause which is not itself caused. There then must be: 6

A form which defines other forms but which cannot itself be defined. A material from which all things are composed, but which is not composed of anything else. An agent which is responsible for all motion but which is not itself moved (an unmoved mover ). An end toward which all things change, but which has no end for itself. The unmoved mover must be eternal and generally unchangeable as well as not being moveable. The Regress Argument The argument for terminal causes proceeds by reductio ad absurdum. 1. Suppose that there is no terminal cause of a series of causes. 2. Then each cause itself has a cause. 3. Then there would be an infinite series of causes. 4. An infinite series of causes is impossible. 5. Therefore, there is a terminal cause. This kind of regress argument can be used to support the thesis that God exists. Theology According to Thomas Aquinas (1225-1274), Theology is the study of God: Whether God exists, What God s attributes are, How God is related to created things. There are two ways in which theology might be conducted: Through the authority of divine revelation, Through the use of natural reason. If one rejects divine revelation, then articles of faith cannot be used as first principles of theology. So natural reason is useful in theology. 7

The Five Ways Aquinas presented five arguments from natural effects to the existence of a divine cause. These arguments are known as the five ways of proving God s existence. The model for these arguments is found in the metaphysics of Aristotle. The Argument from Motion This argument is described as the first and more manifest way. 1. Some things in the world are in motion. [Evident to our senses] 2. If a thing is in motion, its potential to move is made actual by something that is actual. 3. Nothing s potential to do x can be made actual by the thing s actually doing x. 4. So, any motion of a thing is made actual by something other than that thing. [1, 2, 3] 5. If the motion of everything is made actual by something itself actually moving, then there is an infinite chain of movers. 6. There is no infinite chain of movers. 7. So, not all motion is made actual by something actually moving. [5, 6] 8. So, there is an actual mover that is not actually moving. [7] 9. An actual mover that is not actually moving is God. 10. So, God exists. [8,9] The Argument from Causality The basic idea of the argument from causality is that there must be a first efficient cause: An efficient cause is an agent that brings about a change in something else. 1. Nothing can be prior to itself. 2. An efficient cause in nature is prior to its effect. 3. So, no efficient cause in nature is the effect of itself. [1,2] 8

4. For any effect x in nature, x has an efficient cause. 5. So, for any effect x in nature, there is an efficient cause y that is distinct from x. [3,4] 6. If there is no efficient cause that is not an effect, then there is an infinite chain of efficient causes. [5] 7. There is no infinite chain of efficient causes. 8. So, there is an efficient cause of an effect in nature that is not itself an effect. [6,7] 9. An efficient cause that is not an effect is God. 10. So, God exists. [8,9] The Argument from Contingency 1. What is contingent might or might not exist at any time. 2. Suppose everything is contingent. 3. Then it is possible for nothing to exist at all at a time. [1,2] 4. Nothing can come to exist from nothing. 5. So, it is possible that nothing ever exists. [3,4] 6. The possibility of nothing ever existing is absurd. 7. So, not everything is contingent, and something is necessary (existing at all times). [2-6] 8. There cannot be an infinite chain of causality by necessary things. 9. So, there is a being that is necessary in itself and the cause of all necessity. [7,8] 10. Such a being is God. 11. So, God exists.[9,10] The Argument from Gradation 1. Some beings have a higher grade of perfection (of goodness, truth, nobility) than others. 2. The degree of perfection of a thing is always measured against a being with a maximum of perfection (the good is measured against the best, etc.). 9

3. So, for each perfection, there is a being with a maximum of that perfection. [1,2] 4. The being with the maximum of a given perfection is the cause of that perfection. 5. So, for each perfection, there is a being which is the cause of that perfection. [3,4] 6. The cause of all perfections must be found in a single being. 7. So, there is a being which is the cause of all perfections in all beings. [5,6] 8. A being which is the cause of all perfections of all beings is God. 9. So, God exists. [7, 8] The Argument from Governance 1. Natural bodies act so as to obtain the best results. [Aristotle] 2. Acting so as to obtain the best results is acting on the basis of knowledge of the end. [Contra Aristotle] 3. So, natural bodies act on the basis of knowledge. [1,2] 4. Many natural bodies act on the basis of knowledge without having knowledge. [3, observation] 5. If a natural body acts on the basis of knowledge without having knowledge, then it is directed by a being that has such knowledge. 6. So, many natural bodies are directed by a being that has knowledge of their ends. [4,5] 7. A being who directs all natural bodies toward their ends is God. 8. So, many natural bodies are directed toward their ends by God. [6,7] 9. So, God exists. [8] Limitations of the Arguments The arguments from natural effect to divine cause have an inherent limitation. The effects are finite, while God is infinite. So the role of God as cause in each of the arguments does not yield perfect knowledge of God s essence. Together, the five arguments (if successful) only establish the existence of beings with the following features: 10

Being a mover that is not moved, Being a cause that is not an effect, Being unable not to exist, Possessing a maximum of goodness and all perfections, Being director of all natural things. Hume in the eighteenth century exposed a limitation of the arguments not acknowledged by Aquinas. A unitary God would explain all the effects, but several different beings as causes could explain them. The Argument from Evil One of the chief problems with the notion of a perfectly good and powerful God is how evil can exist. Aquinas formulates the problem in this way: 1. If God exists, then goodness is infinite, and there is no evil in the world. 2. There is evil in the world. 3. So, God does not exist. [1,2] One response, given by followers of Plato, is to deny the second premise. Evil has no being, but instead is a privation or lack of being. Aquinas allows that the second premise is true, so he denies the truth of the first premise. Aquinas claims that God allows evil in order to produce the good. This strategy in philosophy is called compatibilism. In this case, the existence of God and of evil are claimed to be compatible with each other. 11