Nominalism III: Austere Nominalism 1. Philosophy 125 Day 7: Overview. Nominalism IV: Austere Nominalism 2

Similar documents
Philosophy 125 Day 8: Overview

Philosophy 125 Day 4: Overview

Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview

Philosophy 125 Day 13: Overview

Lecture 3: Properties II Nominalism & Reductive Realism. Lecture 3: Properties II Nominalism & Reductive Realism

Philosophy 125 Day 12: Overview

Retrospective Remarks on Events (Kim, Davidson, Quine) Philosophy 125 Day 20: Overview. The Possible & The Actual I: Intensionality of Modality 2

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

A Logical Approach to Metametaphysics

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

Class 33 - November 13 Philosophy Friday #6: Quine and Ontological Commitment Fisher 59-69; Quine, On What There Is

Philosophy 148 Announcements & Such. Inverse Probability and Bayes s Theorem II. Inverse Probability and Bayes s Theorem III

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

Deflationary Nominalism s Commitment to Meinongianism

Russell: On Denoting

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Comments on Ontological Anti-Realism

Class #3 - Meinong and Mill

Philosophical Logic. LECTURE SEVEN MICHAELMAS 2017 Dr Maarten Steenhagen

Nominalism. From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Michael J. Loux. Philosophical Concept

Definite Descriptions: From Symbolic Logic to Metaphysics. The previous president of the United States is left handed.

Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames. sentence, or the content of a representational mental state, involves knowing which

To Appear in Philosophical Studies symposium of Hartry Field s Truth and the Absence of Fact

Imprint. A Quinean Critique of Ostrich Nominalism. Bryan Pickel. Nicholas Mantegani. Philosophers. University of Barcelona

2 Why Truthmakers GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA 1. INTRODUCTION

OBJECTIVITY WITHOUT THE PHILOSOPHER S SPECIAL OBJECTS: A PRIORIAN PROGRAM. James Van Cleve, University of Southern California

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Propositions as Cambridge properties

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism

Universals. If no: Then it seems that they could not really be similar. If yes: Then properties like redness are THINGS.

Abstract Entities THE TRADITIONAL PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS. I. Ontology. A. What is it?

Overview of Today s Lecture

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

On Truth At Jeffrey C. King Rutgers University

Possibility and Necessity

On possibly nonexistent propositions

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

Russell on Descriptions

Quine: Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes

Coordination Problems

CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC

Class 33: Quine and Ontological Commitment Fisher 59-69

The Summa Lamberti on the Properties of Terms

Necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pp. i-ix, 379. ISBN $35.00.

Introduction: Belief vs Degrees of Belief

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Against the No-Miracle Response to Indispensability Arguments

Ryle on Systematically Misleading Expresssions

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Phil 435: Philosophy of Language. P. F. Strawson: On Referring

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Millian responses to Frege s puzzle

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Theories of propositions

Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010).

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Supplementary Section 7S.10

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Lecture 4. Before beginning the present lecture, I should give the solution to the homework problem

Varieties of Apriority

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

Understanding Belief Reports. David Braun. In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection.

Why the Traditional Conceptions of Propositions can t be Correct

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames Draft March 1, My theory of propositions starts from two premises: (i) agents represent things as

Negative Facts. Negative Facts Kyle Spoor

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Russell s Problems of Philosophy

Todays programme. Background of the TLP. Some problems in TLP. Frege Russell. Saying and showing. Sense and nonsense Logic The limits of language

Phil 435: Philosophy of Language. [Handout 7] W. V. Quine, Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes (1956)

xiv Truth Without Objectivity

Analyticity and reference determiners

Ontological Justification: From Appearance to Reality Anna-Sofia Maurin (PhD 2002)

It turns out that there is an important class of sentences that we have so far pretty much avoided mentioning: modal sentences.

Tuomas E. Tahko (University of Helsinki)

Logic and Existence. Steve Kuhn Department of Philosophy Georgetown University

II RESEMBLANCE NOMINALISM, CONJUNCTIONS

Class #9 - The Attributive/Referential Distinction

Logic is Metaphysics

Aboutness and Justification

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

Molnar on Truthmakers for Negative Truths

Grounding and Analyticity. David Chalmers

ARMSTRONGIAN PARTICULARS WITH NECESSARY PROPERTIES *

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY

Armstrongian Particulars with Necessary Properties

The Representation of Logical Form: A Dilemma

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Why are Events, Facts, and States of Affairs Different?

Psillos s Defense of Scientific Realism

SYMPOSIUM : INTENTIONALITY NOTES ON INTENTIONALITY *

The Correspondence theory of truth Frank Hofmann

Intermediate Logic Spring. Extreme Modal Realism

The Language Revolution Russell Marcus Fall 2014

On Possibly Nonexistent Propositions

VAGUENESS. Francis Jeffry Pelletier and István Berkeley Department of Philosophy University of Alberta Edmonton, Alberta, Canada

Content and Modality: Themes from the Philosophy of Robert Stalnaker, edited by

Transcription:

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 1 Philosophy 125 Day 7: Overview Administrative Stuff First Paper Topics and Study Questions will be announced Thursday (9/18) All section locations are now (finally!) known (see website) Blog on regresses (my last word?!) available (see home page for link) Guest Lecture next Thursday: Ed Zalta on Nonexistent/Abstract Objects Agenda: Nominalism Austere Nominalism Plato s Beard A Puzzle for Nominalism, and a Proposed Solution by Quine Metalingusitc Nominalism Trope Theory Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 2 Nominalism III: Austere Nominalism 1 So, how does the austere nominalist account for or explain attribute agreement among concrete particulars? They don t. They say it isn t necessary. According to austere nominalism, attribute agreement among concrete particulars is simply a basic, unanalyzable, and inexplicable fact. Recall that perhaps the most popular realist reply to the (attribute agreement) regress we saw in the last chapter was to claim that each of a... n exemplifies F-ness does not itself require an explanation (within a realist framework). The austere nominalist agrees with this claim, but goes farther. They claim that the original fact (explanandum for the realist) does not even require explanation. The austere nominalist takes attribute agreement itself as basic. So, for the austere nominalist, attribute agreement is not something requiring explanation, and so this is only an apparent success story for the realist. How about an austere nominalist account of predication? Y yellow[0pt]c Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 3 Nominalism IV: Austere Nominalism 2 The nominalist does think that an explanation of the truth of a is F is needed. For the nominalist, though, this explanation is painfully simple. Nominalists adopt a very weak, minimal account of truth, based on: (T) a is F is true if and only if a is F. (viz., a is F is true because a is F) This is called a disquotational or deflationary account of truth. NOTE: (T) in and of itself is not inconsistent with a (realist) correspondence theory of truth, which requires there to be a language-independent truthmaker in virtue of which a is F is true. So, nominalists need not be anti-realists (more later). There is a dilemma for deflationary accounts of truth. It seems that there is much more to the truth of the sentence a is F than merely a s being F. After all, a is F must mean or assert that a is F (and that is not guaranteed merely by a s being F). So, (T) seems false if it is applied to sentences a is F. There is another horn here. Perhaps we should read (T) as asserting that the Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 4 proposition expressed by the sentence a is F is true iff a is F. But, then we face a difficulty with the explanation, which says a is F because a is F. If this, too, is read as a propositional claim (i.e., as the proposition that a is F is true because a is F ), then we seem to be able to deduce (using (T)) that a is F because a is F, which seems false (since because is not reflexive). But, then it seems we can t have both (T) and the explanatory claim as well. Thoughts? Realists may be tempted here to complain that (T) is (true, but) trivial. But, they must be careful, since the same charge may threaten their own account. Recall the realist paraphrase Socrates exemplifies courage. If this is equivalent to Socrates is courageous, then (plausibly) it is true iff Socrates is courageous back to (T). How does this lead to a less trivial explanation? If, on the other hand, Socrates exemplifies courage is not equivalent to Socrates is courageous, then how can the realist claim to be giving truth conditions for the latter using the former? We re back to our old dilemma! What about abstract reference? What do austere nominalists say about that?

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 5 Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 6 Nominalism V: Austere Nominalism 3 Remember, the problem of abstract reference involves statements like: (2) Courage is a virtue. (4) John s eyes are the same color as his hair. (5) Those two species are cross-fertile. [This is Quine s example see below.] The realist accounts for the truth of these abstract claims in exactly the same sort of way that they account for the truth of more mundane claims like: (3) Socrates is a man. The nominalist must account for the truth of such claims without positing the existence of a universal that is denoted by the subject term of the sentence. Claims like (2) seem doable for the austere nominalist. They can say: (2 ) Courageous persons are virtuous. But, do (2) and (2 ) have the same meaning? (2) seems necessarily true, but (2 ) may well be false (imagine a courageous person with no other virtue). Nominalism VI: Austere Nominalism 4 Perhaps a successful austere nominalist translation strategy can be found here, but it seems it ll have to be more subtle. Perhaps we could say things like: (2 ) Ceteris paribus (other things being equal), courageous persons are virtuous. Problem: what is the force of the ceteris paribus clause? Intuitively, it means that courageous persons who have all the remaining virtues are virtuous. But, nominalists cannot say that it reintroduces what was to be eliminated. Try courageous persons who satisfy all the remaining virtue predicates are virtuous. But, there aren t enough virtue predicates to ensure that (2 ) cannot be false. Loux concludes that CP s are not fully nominalistically analyzable. Claims like (4) present further problems. The austere nominalist has to explain (4) in terms of concrete particulars agreeing in various ways. One could try to introduce adverbs here, and then translate (4) into: (4 ) John s eyes and John s hair agree colorwise. Loux: these adverbs must then be taken as explanatorily primitive (Why?). Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 7 Nominalism VII: Austere Nominalism 5 Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 8 Nominalism VIII: A Puzzle Concerning Nominalistic Discourse 1 Loux concedes that austere nominalism posits fewer ontological categories than realism (no universals, only particulars). But, he argues that austere nominalism is explanatorily more complex and less unified than realism. Austere nominalism seems to treat more things as explanatorily primitive Attribute agreement Their ceteris paribus clauses Their adverbial expressions Austere nominalism also seems to have a less unified account of the truth of subject-predicate claims especially in the case of abstract reference: They do not have a general recipe for generating nominalistic translations of abstract claims. These seem to be done piecemeal or one at a time. Realism, on the other had, has a unified explanatory scheme for subject-predicate discourse in general (esp. the case of abstract reference). How are we to weigh these conflicting assessments of parsimony? Here are two fundamental questions about nominalistic discourse: (Q1) When a nominalist (particularly, an Austere Nominalist) says There are no universals, what could this possibly mean (by their own lights)? (Q2) When a realist says There are universals, how can the nominalist make sense of this claim (and how can the nominalist engage the realist here)? Quine (in On What There Is ) suggests an answer to (Q1), based on Russell s On Denoting (which is assigned for next week s guest lecture). Quine also discusses (Q2), but only briefly. He suggests that the nominalist should resort to talking about the realist s sentences, and how they are used. Before we get to metalinguistic nominalism, I think it will be useful to digress somewhat and discuss Quine s application of Russell s theory of descriptions. Russell was concerned with the problem of empty names. Problem: How can we make sense out of singular claims with empty singular terms (subjects)?

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 9 Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 10 Nominalism IX: A Puzzle Concerning Nominalistic Discourse 2 Quine s Example: Consider a debate on the issue Whether Pegasus exists. The realist believes Pegasus is, and the nominalist believes that Pegasus is not. It seems strange for the nominalist to assert Pegasus does not exist. You can imagine the realist asking What does not exist?. It seems the nominalist is referring to something and then saying of that thing that it does not exist (!). To the realist, making such discourse meaningful seems to require having something in our ontology to which the singular term Pagasus refers. Many Realists do postulate such things, which do not (actually) exist in space and time. Some realists posit possible (concrete) objects, others postulate (actual) abstract objects. Zalta does the latter (next week s guest lecture). Quine rejects possible objects on the grounds that modality only applies to propositions as a whole, and not to bound variables (e.g., something ). Similar worries arise for theories of abstract objects, which also tend to involve mixtures of modal operators and bound variables (Zalta s lecture). Nominalism X: A Puzzle Concerning Nominalistic Discourse 3 Ed will address objectual issues next week, and we ll do modality in unit 3. I ll focus on Quine, Russell, and the nominalism/realism universals debate. As Quine explains, Russell provides a way to make such discourse meaningful, without presupposing that there is something to which such singular terms refer. The key here is Russell s theory of singular descriptions. Russell focuses on claims involving empty singular descriptions, like: (*) The present King of France is bald. There is no present king of France. So, how can we make sense of (*)? Russell: singular descriptions like the present King of France are (semantically incomplete) denoting expressions, which have meaning in the context of entire claims, like (*), in which they appear but no referent. In particular, Russell unpacks (*) as Something is the present King of France, and nothing else is the present King of France, which is false. Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 11 Nominalism XI: A Puzzle Concerning Nominalistic Discourse 4 Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 12 Nominalism XII: A Puzzle Concerning Nominalistic Discourse 5 Quine argues that Russell s trick can be applied to singular terms (seeming proper names) like Pegasus as well, by descriptionizing them. To wit, the claim Pegasus is not becomes The thing which is-pegasus is not. On Quine s approach, this becomes Nothing uniquely Pegasizes, or, more precisely, There is no x such that (x is-pegasus and every y which is-pegasus is identical to x) a, which is true iff the Pegasus-nominalist is correct. Thus, Pegasus is given a meaning (in the context of complete sentences in which it occurs), without having a referent. And, we seem to get the intuitively correct answers for the truth values of various claims involving Pegasus. This gives the Pegasus-nominalist a way to ground the truth of the claim Pegasus is not. How do realists do it? Ed Zalta will explain this next week. So far, this Russellian trick for particulars does not seem to directly help us with the debate between realists and nominalists about universals. Can it? a Even more precisely: ( x)[p(x) & ( y)(p(y) y = x)], where P(x) reads x is-pegaus. Quine argues this exposes a fallacy in the realist paraphrase strategy. Even if we grant the realist their paraphrase of Socrates is courageous into Socrates exemplifies Courage, it does not follow that the seeming name Courage refers to anything (either via naming or via connoting ). Quine: the conflation of meaning and reference (see Frege reading) causes people to believe Courage refers to a universal (or to an idea in the mind). Quine then considers some possible replies/objections, on behalf of the realist: OK for non-abstract S P discourse, but what about attribute agreement? Quine: Why think attribute agreement is something to explain at all?... that... houses and roses and sunsets are all of them red may be taken as ultimate and irreducible. Sound familiar (and austere)? Aren t meanings (distinguished by Quine from referents) universals? Quine: There are no meanings (only people using language). He is a behaviorist about meaning they re psycho/sociological dispositions.

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 13 Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 14 Nominalism XIII: A Puzzle Concerning Nominalistic Discourse 6 Abstract Reference: What would Quine say about Courage is a virtue? Descriptionizing gives: The thing which is-courage is a virtue. But, on Quine s account, this becomes Something uniquely couragizes, and that thing is a virtue, which is false for a Courage-nominalist. But, courage is a virtue! This seems to make it impossible for a Courage-nominalist to affirm claims like Courage is a virtue, which seem to express truths about courage. Other versions of nominalism (metalinguistic, austere) allow the Courage-nominalist to affirm the (intuitively true) claim Courage is a virtue. Quine talks about abstract reference elsewhere, and he suggests (where possible) the paraphrase strategies (above) adopted by austere nominalism. For (Q2), Quine goes meta-linguistic: nominalists can t (consistently) say There are things the realist has in his ontology but I do not ; they can talk about the realist s sentences & what to do with them (i.e., debate their usage). Nominalism XIV: A Puzzle Concerning Nominalistic Discourse 7 Quine s view seems to be that one s ontological commitments are determined by the ineliminable bound variable expressions in one s best theory of the world i.e., the entities (ineliminably) quantified over in one s best theory. We may say... that some dogs are white and not thereby commit ourselves to recognizing either doghood or whiteness as entities. Some dogs are white says that some things that are dogs are white; and, in order that this statement be true, the things over which the bound variable something ranges must include some white dogs, but need not include doghood or whiteness. On the other hand, when we say that some zoological species are cross-fertile we are committing ourselves to recognizing as entities the several species themselves, abstract though they are. We remain so committed at least until we devise some way of so paraphrasing the statement as to show that the seeming reference to species on the part of our bound variable was an avoidable manner of speaking. Quine says classical mathematics is committed to various abstract entities (e.g., sets), and he says science is too (sets are indispensible to best science). Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 15 Nominalism XV: Epilogue on Quine Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 16 Let us by all means see how much of the physicalistic conceptual scheme can be reduced to a phenomenalistic one... physics also... demands pursuing, irreducible in toto though it be. Let us see... to what degree, natural science may be rendered independent of platonistic mathematics; but let us also pursue mathematics and... its platonistic foundations. Here, Quine hints that realism about some physical universals (e.g., species) and some mathematical universals (e.g., sets) may be ineliminable. Provided merely that [the nominalist s] ontology countenances linguistic forms, or at least concrete inscriptions and utterances, [she] can talk about [the realist s] sentences. Here, Quine suggests that the nominalist go meta-linguistic in their reconstruction (or paraphrase ) of realist discourse. Interesting. More? BUT Here, Quine makes it clear that ontological debates are not about language (even if we reconstruct the discourse in this way). They re about which theory is best, and what it quantifies over. Segué into metalinguistic nominalism...... we must not jump to the conclusion that what there is depends on words. Translatability of a question into semantical terms is no indication that the question is linguistic.

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 17 Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 18 Nominalism XVI: Metalinguistic Nominalism 1 Metalinguistic nominalism has only recently been carefully worked out (20th centuty: Carnap and Sellars), but its roots are in medieval philosophy, in the work of Roscelin, Abelard, and William of Ockahm. Roscelin : talk about universals is really talk about certain linguistic expressions, those that can be predicatively ascribed to many individuals. a And, linguistic expressions are physical vocalizations (mere breaths of air). Abelard: universals are meaningful linguistic expressions (not mere breaths); and, the challenge for nominalism is to explain how predicable expressions can be meaningful in the absence of multiply exemplifiable entities. William of Ockham: Abelard is right, but the meaningfulness of written or spoken language requires an inner language of the soul (language of thought). All agree that the notion of universality itself is to be explained in terms of the linguistic activity of predication (this turns realism s scheme on its head!). a Only names that are general terms (nomina) can have universality the origin of nominalism. Nominalism XVII: Metalinguistic Nominalism 2 Metalinguistic nominalists think that realists and austere nominalists make the same kind of mistake: thinking that there must be some non-lingusitic entities to which terms like courage (in, e.g., Courage is a virtue ) refer. For realists, these entities are universals, for austere nominalists, the entities are concrete particulars (e.g., courageous persons). The metalingustic nominalist thinks both the realist and the austere nominalist are incorrect. Carnap sketches how a systematic and precise metalinguistic nominalistic theory might be worked out. Carnap proposes (roughly) that claims like Courage is a virtue get unpacked as claims about predicates in languages: Courage is a virtue Courageous is a virtue predicate in English. Trangularity is a shape Triangular is a shape predicate in English. Problems: (1) Linguistic types vs linguistic tokens (trading new universals for old ones?), (2) Language relativity (abs. claims don t seem language relative).